The Symposium of Methodius of Olympus and the Critique of Fatalism
Abstract
1. Introduction
Now it is possible for us to determine beforehand and to prefer what is better instead of what is earthly, since we have received minds that are independent of all compulsion (αὐτοκράτορα καὶ αὐτεξούσιον τὸν λογισμὸν εἰληφότας καὶ πάσης ἀνάγκης ἐκτὸς) in the choice of whatever we, as our own masters (αὐτοδεσπότως), think best: we are not slaves to Fate or to the whims of Fortune (οὐ δουλεύοντας εἱμαρμένῃ καὶ τύχαις). *** So that each one of us might not be merely human, but might become good and blessed by following the human examen of Christ and by modelling oneself on Him and living in imitation of Him.(Methodius, symp. VIII,13,30–36)9
2. The Virgin Thecla and Her Argument Against Fatalism
- (§§ 210–217) The nature of the signs of the zodiac, the constituent elements of astrology, is based on myths and legends with no rational foundation. The cosmological model that those who practice astrology defend is presented. Furthermore, if the signs of the zodiac are only present in the sky from a certain point in time, did our ancestors live without a destiny?
- (§§ 218–219) If the stars are endowed with a divine nature, how can they determine the most negative actions of human beings? If they are alien to passions and pain, how can they determine in human life that to which they themselves are alien?
- (§§ 220–224) If man is governed by the movement of the heavenly bodies, which, in turn, is caused by God, the latter is the cause of evil. However, if justice is distinct from injustice, God cannot be the cause of injustice. The same is said with respect to temperance and intemperance and, more generally, with respect to good and evil. In conclusion, God cannot be the cause of evil, because He is good.
- (§§ 224–227) Laws and fatalism cannot be reconciled: if a violent act is determined by the necessity of fate, laws seek to prevent what has been determined by fate. They, therefore, eliminate fatalism, as they show that virtue, being directed towards the freedom of the human being, can be taught.
- (§§ 227–229) If the wicked are wicked because of the necessity of fate and the good are good for the same reason, then the former are not deserving of punishment and the latter are not deserving of praise. However, wickedness is blameworthy, while virtue is pleasing to God.
Those who lay down the definition that man has no free will (μὴ εἶναι τὸν ἄνθρωπον αὐτεξούσιον) but is governed by the ineluctable necessities and the unwritten decrees of Fate, commit impiety against God Himself, since they declare that He is the source and cause of man’s sins (τὸν θεὸν παρεκτικὸν τῶν ἀνθρωπίνων αὐτὸν κακῶν καὶ ποιητὴν). For if He harmoniously directs the entire circular motion of the stars with ineffable and inscrutable wisdom, and if, on the other hand, the stars produce the qualities of vice and virtue in life, dragging men to these things by the chains of necessity, then they declare that God is the cause and source of all evil (αἴτιον τῶν κακῶν τὸν θεὸν ἀποφαίνονται καὶ δότην). But God is not the cause of harm to anyone. Hence there are no horoscopes.(Methodius, symp. VIII,16,12–23)29
so that even a child could by now see clearly and perceive their error; for good and evil are within our power and are not determined by the stars (ἐφ̕ ἡμῖν ἐστι τὸ διαπράξασθαι τὸ καλὸν ἢ τὸ κακὸν καὶ οὐκ ἐν τοῖς ἀστράσι). For we have two motions within us, the desire of the body and that of the soul (Δύο γὰρ κινήσεε ἐν ἡμῖν ἔστον· ἐπιθυμία πεφυκότε σαρκὸς καὶ ψυχῆς), and they are distinct from each other. Hence too they have received two different names, virtue and vice (ἡ μὲν γὰρ ἀρετῆς, ἡ δὲ κακίας). And we of course, should be led on by the most glorious and golden persuasion of virtue, choosing what is best rather than what is base.(Methodius, symp. VIII,17,5–11)44
3. The Importance of the Theme of Freedom in the Symposium and a Comparison with On Free Will
4. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | See Jerome, vir. ill. 83. Jerome attributes to Methodius the episcopal see of Olympus of Lycia and that of Tyre. In fact, the reference to Phoenicia appears only in Jerome’s testimony and is not found in later sources, which, in any case, take what Stridonense says about Methodius as source material. The date of his martyrdom is also certainly problematic. In fact, Jerome himself proposes two possible circumstances that would have caused this event, namely “the last persecution” (“Ad extremum novissimae persecutionis”, see the edition by Ceresa-Gastaldo 1988, p. 190) or that of Decius and Valerian. The former would most probably be that of Diocletian, which took place under Maximinus Daza. The latter, in turn, would refer to two separate persecutions, that of Decius in 249–250 and that of Valerian in 258–259. However, Jerome, among the various works of Methodius, also mentions the writing Against Porphyry: if Porphyry composed his Against the Christians around 270, the author of Against Porphyry cannot have been martyred under either Decius or Valerian. Evidently, the most plausible hypothesis is that Methodius was sentenced to death under Maximinus Daza between 311 and 312. For a concise presentation of the issues surrounding Methodius’ life, see Franchi (2015, pp. 25–42), and Mejzner and Zorzi (2010, pp. 5–33). Further bibliographic indications can be found in the introductory parts of the two cited volumes. |
2 | In the 10th century, a translation into Old Slavonic was made in Bulgaria of the following writings of Methodius: On Free Will, On the Resurrection, On Leprosy, On the Food, On the Leech and On Life. Of the latter three, there are no fragments left in Greek, nor were we aware of their existence from ancient testimonies. Questions have been raised about the reasons that might explain the making of this translation. I endorse Bracht’s thesis (Bracht 1999, p. 12), which, in turn, reconsiders the thesis formulated by Dujčev (1977): the themes addressed in the dialogue On Free Will would have served to counter some doctrinal errors committed by the Bogomils, proponents of a cosmological dualism in tenth-century Bulgaria. |
3 | Vaillant (1930, pp. 649–53), in introducing the critical edition of On Free Will, states that Methodius, a disciple of Origen, turns against him in the name of orthodoxy. According to the scholar, the Symposium seems to belong to the first phase in which Methodius sympathises with Origen’s thought; On Free Will heralds the break with Origenism; in The Resurrection, he attacks it violently and explicitly. Patterson (1997, pp. 26–34), who devoted his doctoral thesis to the reconstruction of the chronology of the works, takes up and develops the argument of the evolution of the Methodian attitude towards the Origenian heritage. Contrary to Vaillant, Patterson believes that the Symposium, a work in which Methodius is said to be nothing more than a follower of Origen as far as the interpretation of Scripture is concerned, is later than On Free Will, from which the writer is said to have taken up themes and summarized them in writing the dialogue on chastity. According to Patterson (1997, pp. 31–33), when Methodius wrote On Free Will, he was not yet aware that the Alexandrian had made his own those positions that he was criticizing in his writing. It is only during the writing of On the Resurrection that he would become aware of it and, in fact, only in the last part of the work is Origen explicitly named as the polemical target of the writing. |
4 | Prinzivalli (1985, pp. 10–11, n. 6), in fact, blurs the terms of the question, affirming that it is not correct to consider On the Resurrection as a fierce attack against Origen, devoid of admiration for the Alexandrian, just as it is not correct to make the Symposium a writing completely in line with Origenian thought. Indeed, in all of Method’s writings, it is possible to notice a never disavowed Origenian forma mentis, at least from an exegetical point of view (see Prinzivalli 1985, p. 13). As Prinzivalli (1985, p. 127) notes in conclusion, the expertise of the bishop of Olympus in the exegetical sphere depends to a great extent on the acquisition of the hermeneutical advances made by Origen. His doubts about the Alexandrian are exclusively on the level of certain doctrinal contents. This judgement is valid for all the works written by Methodius during his lifetime. |
5 | It is good to specify that with ἁγννεία, a term that appears in the original title of the dialogue (ΣΥΜΠOΣΙOΝ H ΠΕΡΙ AΓΝΕΙAΣ), Methodius is pointing to a broader reality than παρθενία: it is not just abstention from sexual relations, but an ideal that embraces all the virtues of the Christian spiritual life, a total consecration in body and spirit to the Lord. On the main terms of the Symposium, see Zorzi (2009). |
6 | With regard to the relationship between the Methodian Symposium and Plato’s dialogues, see Tomaselli (2020), an article in which I attempted to highlight some points of contact between the image of the house and the clay in Methodius’ second discourse of the Symposium and some passages from Plato’s Republic, including the famous myth of the cave. From the article, it is possible to derive further bibliographical indications regarding the relationship between Methodius’ Symposium and Plato’s writings. |
7 | It seems that the virgin must indeed be identified with the saint instructed by Paul according to the Acts of Paul and Thecla. This writing originated as a simple section of the Acts of Paul; however, it soon began to circulate as an independent work and in this version it achieved great success among many Church Fathers and communities of believers. That the Methodian Thecla is precisely the character from the Acts of Paul, i.e., the woman from Iconium (Asia Minor) who, on hearing Paul’s preaching, converted to Christianity and decided to remain a virgin, is shown by the fact that in the Symposium Virtue, in giving the word to the virgin, alludes to the training she received from Paul (see Methodius, symp. VIII, intro., 8–10), not to mention the allusions to the Saint’s martyrdom (see ibid. VIII,2,14–19; VIII,17,30–34; himn 4–5). Thecla is the only one of the ten Methodian virgins that, with the knowledge we have, we can associate with a real personage. The figure of Thecla in the Symposium, moreover, is one of the clues in Methodius’ writings that demonstrate the author’s belonging to a micro-Asiatic context, where in fact, the cult and traditions relating to Thecla were of great importance and experienced great development. On the cult of St Thecla, see Davis (2001). |
8 | Regarding the debate on fate in early Christian literature, see: Bandini (2003, pp. 15–28); Motta (2008, pp. 13–29); Ramelli (2009, pp. 61–75, 104–6); Franchi (2015, pp. 367–71). |
9 | In this study I use the translation by Musurillo (1958, p. 120) and the critical edition by Musurillo and Debidour (1963, p. 236). |
10 | |
11 | See the previous note. |
12 | |
13 | See Macías and González (2005, p. 319). The study presents the arguments Thecla develops in the section of her discourse against astrology; it also offers a Spanish translation of the passage in question, accompanied by an apparatus of notes. I refer to this article above all for the numerous astrological and astronomical pieces of information it offers, information that allows us to understand the final section of Thecla’s discourse even in its most concrete details. |
14 | According to Patterson (1997, pp. 102–3) this exchange of lines between Thecla and Virtue may be nothing more than a literary device to break up a very long presentation. However, it could also be a device that, in its exceptionality, seeks to emphasize the theme of the following section. |
15 | If we consider the paragraph division of the critical edition by Musurillo and Debidour (1963), we see that Thecla’s speech consists of 61 paragraphs (§§ 169–230), while the second longest speech is that of the virgin Thalia, the third speaker, whose speech consists of 40 paragraphs (§§ 51–91). |
16 | Translation by Musurillo (1958, p. 120) and critical edition by Musurillo and Debidour (1963, p. 238). |
17 | This is what Bandini (2003, pp. 26–27) says about the writing Against Fate by Gregory of Nyssa. The scholar affirms that this perspective is not at all obvious, if one juxtaposes the philosophical framework of the Nissenian’s writing with Origen’s arguments on the subject of free will, all of which are founded on the exegesis of passages of Holy Scripture. Bandini also quotes Philo of Alexandria, who, at the beginning of his On Providence (I,1), stated that his arguments were based on “argumentis a ratione petitis” (edition by Hadas-Lebel 1973, p. 126). |
18 | See, in this regard, Macías and González (2005, p. 322). |
19 | On the difference between the meaning of γένεσις and that of εἱμαρμένη, see Macías and González (2005, p. 336, n. 73). The interpretation offered in this study of the term γένεσις is the same as that found in Amand (1973, p. 335), who understands γένεσις as “destin de naissance ou fatalité congénitale”. Genethliac astronomy is a technique based on the representation of the celestial positions as seen at the time and place of an individual’s birth. |
20 | Patterson (1997, p. 82) observes that the Symposium of Methodius contains two interludes consisting of short exchanges between Eubulion and Gregorion, the first positioned after Thalia’s speech and the second after Thecla’s speech. In his view, these two interludes indicate two changes in direction within the dialogue. |
21 | The study by Macías and González (2005) uses Inglebert’s (2001) monograph as a source. However, with respect to the question of the cosmic model advocated by Methodius, the two studies disagree: according to Inglebert (2001, pp. 40, 52) Methodius is a defender of the Greek cosmic model, whereas, according to Macías and González (2005, p. 326), what Thecla does is to summarize and not accept what the defenders of astrology advocated. |
22 | In orat. 9 Tatian, after mentioning figures from myth transformed into constellations, asks: “then how was it that heaven was in disorder until these bodies were placed in their pre-arranged stations?” (translation by Whittaker 1982, p. 19). |
23 | According to Scott (1991, p. 131), “Though believing that the heavenly bodies are spiritually comparable to humanity, Origen never doubts that the stars have a much happier life. Following a long philosophical tradition, Origen thinks that the life of the rational bodies in heaven must be one of great peace and order, in contrast to the troubles which plague the life below”. |
24 | See Scott (1991, pp. 143–44). |
25 | Origen, princ. I,7,2: “For Job appears to show that not only may the stars be subject to sins, but even that they are not clean from the contagion of sin. For it is written thus: ‘The stars also are not clean in his sight’ (Iob 25:5)”. The translation is by Behr (2017, p. 123). On this passage from Origen, see Scott (1991, pp. 137–38). |
26 | The aforementioned article, in its conclusion (Burns 2017, pp. 217–20), establishes a parallelism between the notion of a demon proposed by Plato in the Symposium and the presentation of the stars offered by Thecla in Methodius’ work of the same name. According to Socrates, in fact, who in turn relates what he learnt from the priestess Diotima of Mantinea, ἔρος is a demon and not a god: his nature is, in fact, marked by lack, from which desire arises, i.e., the impulse to obtain what one does not possess. This conception seems to be alluded to by the eighth Methodian virgin, who derives the impulse to sin from the sense of deprivation, absence and emptiness. Heavenly bodies are incapable of evil, as they know no lack and, consequently, no desire. According to the scholar, the parallelism with Plato’s masterpiece is intended to show Methodius’ attempt to exempt the stars not only from sin, but also from their identification with demons. |
27 | Concerning the Liber legum regionum or Against Fate of Bardaisan of Edessa, in addition to the edition by Ramelli (2009), which offers an extensive introduction, the original text, a translation into Italian and an extensive set of notes, see also Drijvers (2014, pp. 88–108). |
28 | The only fate admitted by Bardaisan is not an autonomous power, but depends entirely on God, as it coincides with God’s established order. Fate and the stars from which it derives are subject to God’s order, but human free will is not subject to them. One could, therefore, say that fate and the stars influence, but do not constrain. They may condition external events, but they do not morally determine human choices. Indeed, Bardaisan states: “Just as we see that fate annihilates nature, so too we see that man’s free will rejects fate and annihilates it: though not entirely, just as fate itself does not reject nature in everything. For it is fitting that these three things, nature and fate and free will, should be held in their existence until the process is complete and the measure and number are completed” (see Ramelli 2009, pp. 171–73). |
29 | Translation by Musurillo (1958, p. 125) and critical edition by Musurillo and Debidour (1963, p. 248). |
30 | Translation by Musurillo (1958, p. 125) and critical edition by Musurillo and Debidour (1963, p. 248). Among the divine characteristics listed, Thecla particularly insists on freedom from the passions (ἀσύμπλοκον πάθους). In fact, immediately afterwards, she presents temperance (σωφροσύνη) as a good, the opposite of which is intemperance (ἀκολασία), which will therefore be an evil (Methodius, symp. VIII,16,31–38). It is as if human temperance were a reflection of that characteristic of God which is freedom from the passions: that is why God is pleased with temperance (χαίρει δὲ ὁ θεὸς τῇ σωφροσύνῃ, ibid. VIII,16,40, Musurillo and Debidour 1963, p. 250) which He sees embodied in men. It is hardly surprising that among the various divine characteristics the virgin insists on this one, within a work dedicated to the theme of chastity. |
31 | “But the divine is beauty, wisdom, goodness, and all such qualities” (τὸ δὲ θεῖον καλόν, σοφόν, ἀγαθόν, καὶ πᾶν ὅ τι τοιοῦτον). Translation by Fowler (1982, p. 473). The Greek text I refer to is the one in the same volume. |
32 | Translation by Musurillo (1958, p. 128) and critical edition by Musurillo and Debidour (1963, p. 254). |
33 | Translation by Shorey (1980, p. 507). The Greek text I refer to is the one in the same volume. Other possible Platonic echoes in the anti-astrological section are pointed out by Jahn (1865, pp. 59–63). |
34 | Perhaps the best known testimony is found in Homer, Il. XXIV,525–530, where the two jars are evoked, one full of evils and the other full of goods, from which Zeus extracts now evils, now goods to assign to man. It is important to note that in Homer we also find the first attempt to relieve the deity of responsibility for evil: I refer, of course, to Homer, Od. I,34, a verse that Thecla, moreover, quotes twice. |
35 | |
36 | I refer here to Theophila’s response to Marcella’s objection, who asks, with a polemical attitude, whether her assertion that no one is born at the margin of God’s will also applies to illegitimate children. In order to demonstrate how God works directly for the birth of any human being, the virgin Theophila proposes the image of a house with many entrances, inside which a craftsman moulds all the clay offered to him from outside, even if it is brought in illicitly. Theophila then explains that there are no evil realities in themselves, but that they become so according to the use made of them. The image evoked by Theophila and his explanation can be found in Methodius, symp. II,4–5. In Tomaselli (2020), I have highlighted the Platonic influence in Theophila’s evocation of the image in question and, at the same time, tried to show how the content of this part of his discourse is in fact far removed from Platonic inspiration. |
37 | Translation by Musurillo (1958, p. 127) and critical edition by Musurillo and Debidour (1963, p. 252). |
38 | Translation by Musurillo (1958, p. 128). |
39 | Concerning the argument of the νόμιμα βαρβαρικά employed by Carneades, see Amand (1973, pp. 55–60). |
40 | On the argumentation of the νόμιμα βαρβαρικά in Bardaisan and other Christian authors, see Ramelli (2009, pp. 104–6). |
41 | Studies questioning the argumentation of the νόμιμα βαρβαρικά in the discourse of the virgin Thecla and its possible sources include: Amand (1973, pp. 338–40); Ramelli (2013, pp. 272–73); Burns (2017, pp. 211–13). The latter believes that Methodius “must have known the νόμιμα βαρβαρικά via contemporaries, in turn likely reliant on Bardaisan, as were near-contemporaries such as Eusebius of Caeserea or the author of the Pseudo-Clementine Recognitions” (Burns 2017, p. 212). |
42 | In 2 apol. 7,6–7 Justin also closely links the argument of the νόμιμα βαρβαρικά, albeit only hinted at, to the properly moral argument: “And this is the nature of all that is made—to be capable of vice and virtue. For neither would any of them be praiseworthy unless there was also power to turn to both. And this also is shown by those people everywhere who have made laws and conducted philosophy according to right reason, by their agreeing to do some things and refrain from others”. Translated by Barnard (1997, pp. 78–79). The moral argumentation in an anti-fatalist function also appears in Justin, 2 apol. 43. |
43 | Concerning Carneades’ elaboration of the moral argument, see the second and third chapters of Amand’s monograph (Amand 1973, pp. 41–68). Other texts—pagan, Jewish or Christian—that present the same or similar arguments are listed by Bandini (2003, p. 21, n. 38). |
44 | Translation by Musurillo (1958, p. 129) and critical edition by Musurillo and Debidour (1963, pp. 256–58). |
45 | The expression coined by Prinzivalli (1998, p. 47), according to which Methodius represents “una sorta di ponte culturale”, has had some success: on the one hand, he shows himself to be the heir and interpreter of traditions of Asian culture; on the other, he appears to be sensitive to and akin to modern Alexandrian culture. In the specific case of the Symposium, one must then consider what I like to call the polyphony of the ten virgins. Methodius did not compose a simple treatise on chastity, but gave voice to ten distinct characters, from whose speeches one cannot derive a systematic and coherent theological thought. None of the ten virgins’ speeches represent, taken in isolation, Methodius’ viewpoint; on the contrary, they contain elements that can be traced back to different theological traditions, which Methodius considered compatible with his own vision. |
46 | See, for example, Methodius, res. I,58,5–6 and I,59,1. |
47 | With regard to the judgement expressed above, I am indebted to Cantalamessa (1976, pp. 431–32). According to the Capuchin scholar, continence does not need marriage to be repudiated in order to be recognized in its validity. On the contrary, it does not make sense apart from the simultaneous affirmation of marriage. In Jesus, in fact, we observe this freedom in the face of marriage, as in the face of all reality. |
48 | This is the general conclusion reached by Theophila: “Now an art always operates on the material submitted to it. And there is nothing that is to be considered evil of itself, but rather becomes such by the act of the men who use it (οὐδὲν γὰρ αὐτό τι καθ̕ ἑαυτὸ τῶν πραγμάτων ἡγητέον εἶναι κακὸν ἀλλὰ παρὰ τὴν πρᾶξιν τῶν χρωμένων τοιοῦτο γίνεσθαι). For when a thing is dealt with in a good and prudent way, the result is good; and bad when it is treated improperly and disgracefully”. Translation by Musurillo (1958, p. 54) and critical edition by Musurillo and Debidour (1963, p. 80). After proposing a general statement, the virgin presents some examples: iron is not responsible for its use in warfare; metals such as gold, silver and bronze are not to blame if they are used in the creation of statues that foment idolatry; one who works wool merely uses it for the project he has in mind, even if it has been supplied to him by the person who stole it; the same applies to an adulterous relationship, where the responsibility falls solely on the one who commits adultery, not on the fruit of the relationship. |
49 | On the fruitfulness of life’s trials, see, firstly, Methodius, De vita 3, where he is defined as stronger than others who has endured great labours. In arbitr. 20,2–8, the orthodox character states that God, although he was able to annihilate the devil, he allowed the devil to exist so that men, who had previously been overcome by him, could overcome him. The world, therefore, is nothing but the gymnasium in which God’s disciples wrestle against the Evil One: he who wins against the Enemy is praised by God, while he who does not try hard enough and is knocked down is condemned. This section is characterized by the use of agonistic terminology, probably of Pauline derivation, also used in several passages of the Methodian Symposium, including, for example, symp. epil. 107–113. The theme of the positivity of the experience of trial in human existence is, moreover, developed in De cibis 2–5, where the trials that man is called upon to go through are compared to the fertilizer that makes gardens more beautiful and lush (ibid. 5,4). In res. II,5,1–2, on the other hand, we do not go so far as to speak of the positivity of being put to the test, but only of its necessity. |
50 | That virginity has been revealed is, for example, the presupposition of the whole description of human progress made by Marcella (cf. Methodius, symp. I,2–5). In the first discourse, however, we also find explicit statements on the subject: in ibid. I,1,20–21 virginity is described as a drink that cannot flow from the earth, but only from heaven; in ibid. I,2,1–3 it is described as a plant that was sent from heaven to men at a certain moment in the history of salvation; finally, in ibid. I,4,7–9, Marcella explicitly states that only the Lord could proclaim the μάθημα of virginity, an assertion that is motivated throughout the paragraph. The notion of virginity as a gift from Christ appears several times, until the speech of the last speaker, Domnina, who interprets the fable of Jotham found in Iud 9:8–15. With this tale, according to Domnina, the Bible alludes to the different legislations up to Christ. The last commandment directed to man in salvation history is precisely that of virginity, which Christ offers to the apostles (cf. Methodius, symp. X,3–4). |
51 | The translation is mine, while the critical edition is that of Descortieux (1999, p. 252). |
52 | Critical edition by Bonwetsch (1917, p. 186). |
53 | See the previous note. |
54 | Critical edition by Bonwetsch (1917, p. 188). |
55 | Vaillant (1930, pp. 649–53) and Buchheit (1958, p. 172) argue for the anteriority of the Symposium; in addition to Patterson, Franchi (2015, pp. 108–10) is of the opposite opinion. |
56 | Translation by Musurillo (1958, p. 121) and critical edition by Musurillo and Debidour (1963, p. 240). |
References
- Amand, David. 1973. Fatalisme et liberté dans l’antiquité grecque. Recherches sur la survivance de l’argumentation morale antifataliste de Carnéade chez les philosophes grecs et les théologiens chrétiens des quatre premiers siècles. Amsterdam: Adolf M. Hakkert. [Google Scholar]
- Bandini, Michele. 2003. Gregorio di Nissa. Contro il fato. Bologna: Edizioni Dehoniane Bologna. [Google Scholar]
- Barnard, Leslie William. 1997. St. Justin Martyr. The First and Second Apologies. New York and Mahwah: Paulist Press. [Google Scholar]
- Behr, John. 2017. Origen. On First Principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press, vol. I. [Google Scholar]
- Bonwetsch, Nathanael. 1917. Methodius. Leipzig: J. C. Hinrichs’sche Buchhandlung. [Google Scholar]
- Bracht, Katharina. 1999. Vollkommenheit und Vollendung. Zur Anthropologie des Methodius von Olympus. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. [Google Scholar]
- Buchheit, Vinzenz. 1958. Studien zu Methodius von Olympos. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Burns, Dylan M. 2017. Astrological Determinism, Free Will, and Desire According to Thecla (St. Methodius, Symposium 8.15–16). In Women and Knowledge in Early Christianity. Edited by Ulla Tervahauta, Ivan Miroshnikov, Outi Lehtipuu and Ismo Dunderberg. Leiden and Boston: Brill, pp. 206–20. [Google Scholar]
- Cantalamessa, Raniero. 1976. Etica sessuale e matrimonio nel cristianesimo delle origini. Bilancio di una ricerca. In Etica sessuale e matrimonio nel cristianesimo delle origini. Edited by Raniero Cantalamessa. Milan: Vita e Pensiero, pp. 423–60. [Google Scholar]
- Ceresa-Gastaldo, Aldo. 1988. Gerolamo. Gli Uomini Illustri. Firenze: Nardini editore. [Google Scholar]
- Davis, Stephen J. 2001. The Cult of Saint Thecla: A Tradition of Women’s Piety in Late Antiquity. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Descortieux, Patrick. 1999. Clément d’Alexandrie. Les Stromates. Stromate VI. Paris: Les Éditions du Cerf. [Google Scholar]
- Drijvers, Jan Willem. 2014. Bardaisan of Edessa. Piscataway: Gorgias Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dujčev, Ivan. 1977. L’ oeuvre de Méthode d’ Olympe “De libero arbitrio” et les discussions entre orthodoxes et hérétiques. Balcanica 8: 115–27. [Google Scholar]
- Ferrari, Franco. 1998. Theologia. In Platone. La Repubblica. Edited by Mario Vegetti. Napoli: Bibliopolis, vol. II, pp. 403–25. [Google Scholar]
- Ferrari, Franco. 2017. Il dibattito antico intorno all’origine del male: Platone e la tradizione platonica. In Eranos Yearbook 2015–2016. The World ant its Shadow/Il mondo e la sua ombra. Edited by Fabio Merlini and Riccardo Bernardini. Ascona and Einsiedeln: Daimon Verlag, pp. 42–89. [Google Scholar]
- Fowler, Harold North. 1982. Plato. Euthyphro. Apology. Crito. Phaedo. Phaedrus. Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press and William Heinemann Ltd. [Google Scholar]
- Franchi, Roberta. 2015. Metodio d’Olimpo. Il Libero Arbitrio. Milan: Paoline. [Google Scholar]
- Hadas-Lebel, Mireille. 1973. Philon d’Alexandrie. De Providentia I et II. Paris: Les éditions du Cerf. [Google Scholar]
- Inglebert, Hervé. 2001. Interpretatio Christiana. In Les Mutations des Savoirs (Cosmographie, Géographie, Ethnographie, Histoire) Dans l’Antiquité Chrétienne (30–630 Après J.-C.). Paris: Institut d’Études Augustiniennes. [Google Scholar]
- Jahn, Albert. 1865. S. Methodius Platonizans. Halle: C. E. M. Pfeffer. [Google Scholar]
- Macías, Cristóbal, and Marta González. 2005. El Banquete de Metodio de Olimpo y sus argumentos contra la astrología. MHNH. Revista Internacional de Investigación sobre Magia y Astrologías Antiguas 5: 307–42. [Google Scholar]
- Mejzner, Mirosław, and M. Benedetta Zorzi. 2010. Metodio di Olimpo. La Risurrezione. Rome: Città Nuova. [Google Scholar]
- Motta, Beatrice. 2008. Il Contra Fatum di Gregorio di Nissa nel Dibattito Tardo-Antico sul Fatalismo e sul Determinismo. Pisa and Rome: Fabrizio Serra Editore. [Google Scholar]
- Musurillo, Herbert. 1958. St. Methodius. The Symposium: A Treatise on Chastity. New York and Ramsay: Newman Press. [Google Scholar]
- Musurillo, Herbert, and Victor-Henry Debidour. 1963. Méthode d’Olympe. Le banquet. Paris: Les éditions du Cerf. [Google Scholar]
- Patterson, Lloyd George. 1997. Methodius of Olympus. Divine Sovereignty, Human Freedom, and Life in Christ. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Prinzivalli, Emanuela. 1985. L’esegesi Biblica di Metodio di Olimpo. Rome: Institutum Patristicum «Augustinianum». [Google Scholar]
- Prinzivalli, Emanuela. 1998. Desiderio di generazione e generazione del desiderio. Metodio di Olimpo e le polemiche sull’Eros fra III e IV secolo. In L’Eros Difficile. Amore e Sessualità Nell’antico Cristianesimo. Edited by Salvatore Pricoco. Catanzaro: Rubbettino, pp. 39–66. [Google Scholar]
- Ramelli, Ilaria. 2009. Bardesane di Edessa. Contro il Fato. Rome and Bologna: Edizioni San Clemente and Edizioni Studio Domenicano. [Google Scholar]
- Ramelli, Ilaria. 2013. The Christian Doctrine of Apokatastasis. A Critical Assessment from the New Testament to Eriugena. Leiden and Boston: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Scott, Alan. 1991. Origen and the Life of the Stars. A History of an Idea. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Shorey, Paul. 1980. Plato. Republic. Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press and William Heinemann Ltd., vol. II. [Google Scholar]
- Tomaselli, Davide. 2020. Il paradeigma della casa e dell’argilla nel Simposio di Metodio di Olimpo: Punti di contatto e differenze rispetto al modello platonico. Adamantius 26: 135–47. [Google Scholar]
- Vaillant, André. 1930. Le De autexusio de Méthode d’Olympe. Paris: Brepols. [Google Scholar]
- Whittaker, Molly. 1982. Tatian. Oratio ad Graecos and Fragments. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Zorzi, Benedetta. 2009. The Use of the Terms ἁγνεία, παρθενία, σωφροσύνη, and ἐγκράτεια in the Symposium of Methodius of Olympus. Vigiliae Christianae 63/II: 138–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Tomaselli, D. The Symposium of Methodius of Olympus and the Critique of Fatalism. Religions 2025, 16, 1159. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16091159
Tomaselli D. The Symposium of Methodius of Olympus and the Critique of Fatalism. Religions. 2025; 16(9):1159. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16091159
Chicago/Turabian StyleTomaselli, Davide. 2025. "The Symposium of Methodius of Olympus and the Critique of Fatalism" Religions 16, no. 9: 1159. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16091159
APA StyleTomaselli, D. (2025). The Symposium of Methodius of Olympus and the Critique of Fatalism. Religions, 16(9), 1159. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16091159