The Greek Philosophical Sources in Cicero’s De Fato
Abstract
1. Introduction
2. Historical and Philosophical Context of the Treatise De Fato
3. The Influence of Greek Philosophy on De Fato: Greek Philosophical Schools and Their Treatment of Fate
I call fate what the Greeks call heimarmene (εἱμαρμένη), that is the order and series of causes, when cause linked to cause produces of itself an effect. That is an eternal truth which flows from all eternity. Because this is so, nothing has happened which was not going to happen and for the same reason nothing will happen the efficient causes of which nature does not contain. From this we recognize that Fate is not what is called superstitiously but what it is called scientifically, the eternal cause of things, why things that are passed have happened and why impeding events occur and why what follows will be.(Cicero 1923, De Divinatione I, 55, 125–126).
4. The Debate Between the Stoics and the Epicureans on Fate
5. Cicero’s Appropriation and Critique: Structure and Method
6. Cicero’s Three Approaches to Fate
7. The Influence of the Treatise De Fato
8. Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Philosophical syncretism refers to the blending of different philosophical traditions and schools of thought. Cicero was particularly adept at integrating Greek philosophical ideas into Roman thought, creating a unique synthesis that was accessible and relevant to the Roman political and social context. |
2 | The political crisis refers to the tumultuous period in Rome after the assassination of Julius Caesar, which led to civil wars and the eventual downfall of the Roman Republic. The resulting instability deeply influenced Cicero’s philosophical reflections, especially on the issues of fate and free will. |
3 | The Stoics believed that the gods were rational and operated according to a divine, unchangeable plan. In contrast, the Epicureans viewed the gods as detached from human affairs, living a life of blissful indifference. This theological debate set the stage for Cicero’s later discussions on fate. |
4 | For a detailed discussion on this issue, see: Wynne (2019, pp. 50–82). |
5 | Divination was a central aspect of Roman religious and political life. It involved interpreting omens or signs from the gods to guide human action. Cicero critiqued this practice, especially in relation to the idea of an immutable fate. |
6 | The assassination of Julius Caesar in 44 BCE marked a pivotal moment in Roman history. Cicero, who had been a vocal supporter of the Roman Republic, was deeply affected by the event, which spurred his reflections on political destiny and personal autonomy. |
7 | The clinamen is an essential concept in Lucretius’ philosophy, which introduces the idea of random atomic swerve to explain the possibility of free will in an otherwise deterministic universe. In Epicurus, this concept is referred to as parénklisis or “atomic deviation”, which plays a fundamental role in his ethical framework. Cicero explores this idea in his own critique of the Stoics and Epicureans in De Fato. |
8 | The Homeric poems and Greek tragedies, particularly the Iliad and Odyssey, often present fate as an unavoidable force, governed by the gods or cosmic principles. Moira and Tyche represent different aspects of fate: moira as the personification of fate and tyche as the goddess of chance. See: (Homer 1999, pp. 417–20). |
9 | Heraclitus’ doctrine of the unity of opposites and the flux of the universe suggests that although the world is in constant change, it follows an underlying rational principle or law—what Cicero might interpret as fate. See: Fragments, DK B30. |
10 | Empedocles’ theory of the four elements and the forces of philía (love) and neîkos (strife) that bind and separate them reflects a cosmic balance that Cicero could associate with fate, governing the elements’ interactions. See: Fragments, DK B17. |
11 | Democritus’ atomism suggests that all events, including human actions, are the result of mechanical necessity. Everything happens as a result of the interaction of atoms, with no room for randomness or free will, leading to a deterministic worldview. See: Fragments, DK B156. |
12 | Aristotle’s concept of causality is more complex than that of earlier philosophers. His introduction of chance (tykhe) contrasts with necessity (anágké), allowing for a more flexible understanding of fate and causality in the natural world. See: Physics II, 4–6. |
13 | In fact, this “essence of necessity” reflects Stoic influence, in which fate is an unalterable cosmic principle, yet tempered by Cicero’s emphasis on human autonomy. |
14 | |
15 | Cicero’s De Natura Deorum and De Divinatione also explore the intersection of fate, divine providence, and human agency. His translation of Timaeus helped frame his own views on fate and divine order. See Cicero, Timeus, 3, 10. |
16 | Socrates’ encounters with his daimonion (divine voice) are often interpreted as moments of divine intervention. Cicero references this in De Divinatione, linking the philosopher’s guidance from this voice to a belief in divine fate or providence. |
17 | The Stoic conception of fate as a series of unalterable causes linked to divine providence suggests that all events are part of a larger, rational plan that human beings should align themselves with. |
18 | Chrysippus, a key Stoic philosopher, attempted to reconcile determinism with human freedom by suggesting that while events are determined, human beings can still act freely within this framework through reason. |
19 | Diodorus Cronus, a Megarian philosopher, argues that only what is true or will be true can be possible, thus introducing a strict form of determinism based on logical necessity. |
20 | Epicurus introduced the concept of clinamen to explain how free will can exist in a world that might otherwise be deterministically governed by the laws of nature. This swerve of atoms represents an escape from fate’s laws. |
21 | The core difference between the Stoics and Epicureans lies in their interpretation of fate and human autonomy. While the Stoics believe that fate is a necessary and divine part of the universe’s structure, the Epicureans assert that humans have a measure of freedom due to the clinamen or the “swerve” of atoms, which introduces unpredictability into the natural order. This swerve allows for human agency to disrupt the chain of causes that would otherwise lead to determinism. |
22 | The image of the dog tied to a cart is a powerful representation of Stoic thought. The dog symbolizes the individual who, although tethered to the larger framework of fate (represented by the cart), can choose to align or resist its course. Stoics argue that harmony with fate—accepting one’s circumstances—leads to tranquility, whereas resistance brings suffering. “When we are told both that everything is fated, and also that our souls are somehow free, it seems natural to conclude that there is a sort of causal fire-wall separating inside from outside, insulating the soul within from the ineluctable causal nexus without. The dog’s body may be fated to move, but its mind is still free to cooperate or not. Or at least, however it goes for dogs, our human minds are free to think, choose, decide and react however we want, and the mental events are not fated, not caused, and not destined—surely that is the point of Stoicism, to counsel virtue through resignation, and to give us the freedom to cooperate with the dictates of fate. But we have seen ample evidence that this simply was not their view. There is, to begin with, the repeated afirmation that everything, without exception, happens by fate and as the result of antecedent causes—and the arguments used to bolster this claim are just as applicable to mental events as to extra-mental events. Furthermore, there is the fact that their account of the soul makes it simply another parcel of matter in a material world—a part of the cohesive and coherent pneuma that constitutes the cosmos. Had they wished to purchase it some exemption from causation, they might at least have made it of a different stuff, or no stuff at all. Consider, too, the care with which they elaborated the causal connections between the soul and the rest of the world, working in both directions. The theory of perception tells us how the objects around us impose a physical alteration on our impressionable souls; the theory of impulse tells us how our souls reach out to change the world in turn” (T. Brennan 2005, p. 316). |
23 | Chrysippus’ distinction between primary and auxiliary causes is central to Stoic determinism. Primary causes are those intrinsic to an object, like the shape of a rolling cylinder, while auxiliary causes are external influences, such as the initial push. This distinction illustrates that while external factors may influence actions, they are not the primary drivers of events, maintaining the Stoic view that the universe operates in a deterministic and interconnected manner. |
24 | Carneades questions the Stoic belief in divination as a means of knowing the future. He argues that if everything is predetermined by fate, divination would be futile, as it would neither alter nor predict the inevitable course of events. His critique points to the inherent contradictions in the Stoic worldview, where the existence of free will and predictive practices like divination seem incompatible. |
25 | Cicero, in his discussion of the Stoic position, recognizes the distinction between necessary causes and necessary conditions, which helps Stoics argue that while some events are inevitable, others are merely facilitated by specific conditions. However, Cicero points out the difficulty in reconciling this view with human nature, as even our own character—considered a primary cause—can be influenced by factors beyond our control, raising questions about true autonomy. |
26 | The Latin term fatum is derived from Greek concepts such as heimarmenē and anankē. Both of these terms emphasize the inevitability and determinism associated with fate. In Greek philosophy, heimarmenē refers to a portion of the cosmos allocated to an individual, indicating an element of fate assigned by the natural order, while anankē refers to necessity or the unchangeable nature of fate. |
27 | The Stoics adopted heimarmenē as a chain of causality, positing that everything in the universe was interconnected and followed a causal order dictated by divine reason (the logos). This reinterpretation signaled a shift from a more passive conception of fate to an active process of cause and effect governing the cosmos. |
28 | The term fatum in Latin takes on a more emotionally charged connotation compared to its Greek counterpart. While heimarmenē could be understood as a more neutral or impersonal portion of fate, the Latin fatum evokes a sense of inevitability, as seen in the melancholic cultural tradition of fado, the Portuguese music genre that expresses resignation to an inescapable destiny. |
29 | Cicero’s De Fato explores the idea of fate as an “everlasting series of causes” (causarum series sempiterna), a notion borrowed from Stoic philosophy. This interpretation implies that fate operates through an unbroken chain of events that stretch across time, dictated by rational principles. Cicero’s treatment of this concept reflects his engagement with Stoic thought while seeking to shape his own understanding of fate and free will. |
30 | Cicero’s dialectical method in De Fato follows a pattern similar to his other philosophical works, such as the Tusculan Disputations, in which he uses a dialog format. A disciple proposes a thesis, and the master, Cicero in this case, provides counterarguments. This approach facilitates the exploration of multiple perspectives on the issue of fate. |
31 | The dialog structure in De Fato reflects the influence of the Academic Skeptic tradition, which Cicero followed. The master’s role in this tradition is to question all assumptions and challenge every argument, as exemplified by Arcesilaus, a leading figure in Academic Skepticism. This method aims to uncover the truth by scrutinizing every claim. |
32 | In De Fato, Cicero emphasizes the importance of questioning rather than affirming. His statement, “I do not affirm anything and question everything”, aligns with the skeptical approach of doubting all propositions, even his own conclusions. This method was central to his philosophical approach, which aimed at testing the limits of knowledge and certainty. |
33 | Cicero introduces the term perì dynatôn, meaning “concerning the possible” to discuss questions about the future. This idea falls within the realm of logic, where philosophers engage with the possibility of future events. Cicero underscores the importance of logic as a “science of argumentation” in addressing such questions about fate and contingency. |
34 | Cicero notes that, unlike in some of his other works, where the arguments for and against a particular view are presented in a straightforward manner, in De Fato, the discussion on fate does not proceed without interruption. This method reflects the Roman philosophical tradition of cautious deliberation and careful analysis, rather than quick conclusions. |
35 | The idea of sympátheia or “universal sympathy” is central to Stoic cosmology, which holds that all parts of the universe are interconnected. According to the Stoic doctrine, every element of the cosmos is linked to all others through a rational principle, the logos, which is both the governing force and the organizing principle behind the universe (Long 2006). This idea suggests that everything that happens in the cosmos is part of an ordered and rational plan, with each part playing its role in a unified whole. |
36 | The Stoic logos is often described as a divine reason or rationality that permeates the universe. It is through the logos that the Stoics explain both the existence of the cosmos and the harmonious interrelation of all its parts. In this worldview, fate is not a random occurrence but a necessary and rational sequence of events determined by the logos. This view of the universe as a living organism is foundational to understanding Stoic ethics, where everything is connected by a web of rationality and necessity. |
37 | Cicero critiques the Stoic idea of sympátheia by examining the influence of environmental factors on a person’s fate. He uses examples like the lighter atmosphere in Athens, which supposedly makes its inhabitants more astute, and the denser atmosphere in Thebes, which makes its people “coarser and more vigorous.” These examples reflect an attempt to show how external factors might influence a person’s character and actions, but Cicero ultimately questions whether such factors alone can fully explain a person’s fate. |
38 | Cicero’s response to the Stoic notion of universal sympathy reflects his belief that the influence of external factors, such as the environment or the stars, is not absolute. While he acknowledges that such factors may play a role in shaping certain aspects of a person’s fate, he emphasizes the complexity and diversity of natures and argues that fate cannot be determined solely by these external influences. This perspective critiques the determinism inherent in the Stoic worldview (Rist 1972). |
39 | In the Stoic view, fate is synonymous with the idea of heimarmenē, the chain of causes that extends from the beginning of time to the end. This deterministic view posits that every event is the result of an unbroken sequence of causes, meaning that nothing happens by chance. For the Stoics, even seemingly random events are the result of a rational and divine order, and human free will is subordinated to this cosmic plan. |
40 | Cicero challenges the Stoic view of fate by raising questions about human freedom. If everything is interconnected and every event is part of an unbreakable chain of causes, Cicero asks whether humans can truly exercise free will. He argues that if all actions are predetermined by the causal chain, the concept of personal responsibility and moral agency becomes meaningless. This critique of determinism invites a more nuanced view of human action and the possibility of free will. |
41 | Contemporary beliefs in astrology, which claim that a person’s character and fate are determined by the positions of the stars at birth, are reminiscent of the deterministic ideas that Cicero critiques in De Fato. Just as Cicero questions the role of physical traits in shaping a person’s destiny, modern critiques of astrology argue that such beliefs oversimplify the complexity of human nature and the influence of free will and personal effort in shaping one’s life. |
42 | The anecdote about Socrates’ physiognomy, as interpreted by Zopyrus, highlights Cicero’s skepticism about the deterministic interpretation of physical traits. Zopyrus’ absurd conclusion that Socrates’ facial features determined his character or fate illustrates the dangers of reducing complex human nature to a set of physical characteristics. Cicero uses this example to argue that fate cannot be determined by physical traits alone. |
43 | Cicero rejects the idea that fate is determined by external factors such as physical traits or environmental influences. Instead, he argues that “will”, “effort”, and “learning” are the true determinants of a person’s fate. These factors, which reflect a person’s ability to shape their own destiny through conscious effort and decision-making, are key to Cicero’s conception of human freedom. For Cicero, the capacity for personal growth and self-determination is what truly defines an individual’s fate (Cicero, De Fato, 5–11). |
44 | Cicero’s philosophy emphasizes the importance of moral and educational development as essential tools for achieving virtue. In a world where many believed in a predetermined fate governed by the stars or physical traits, Cicero proposes a more optimistic vision in which individuals can shape their own destinies through reason, effort, and education (Rist 1972). This vision empowers individuals to take responsibility for their actions and strive for moral excellence. |
45 | Cicero’s perspective on fate in De Fato reflects a balance between determinism and human agency. While he critiques the Stoic notion of absolute fatalism, he does not wholly reject the idea that external forces influence human lives. Instead, he adopts a more pragmatic approach that acknowledges a degree of cosmic order while emphasizing the role of human will, reason, and education in shaping one’s destiny. This perspective is deeply rooted in the Roman intellectual tradition, which sought to adapt Greek philosophical doctrines—particularly Stoicism and Academic Skepticism—into a practical framework suitable for political and ethical life (Rist 1972). Cicero’s argument serves not only as a philosophical inquiry but also as a rhetorical tool reinforcing the Roman ideal of the virtuous statesman: an individual capable of navigating external constraints through wisdom and ethical action. By maintaining that moral development and effort remain central to personal excellence, Cicero presents a vision of fate that allows for self-determination within a structured but not wholly predetermined cosmos. |
46 | Augustine’s engagement with Cicero’s De Fato reflects an attempt to reconcile classical philosophy with Christian doctrine. By integrating Stoic and Ciceronian notions of fate with theological ideas on divine providence and free will, Augustine helped shape medieval debates on predestination and human agency. |
47 | The political structure of the Italian city-states, such as Florence and Venice, promoted values of civic participation and individual responsibility, which aligned with Ciceronian ideals of active citizenship and personal virtue. |
48 | Lorenzo Valla’s De libero arbitrio challenged Scholastic determinism, reinforcing a humanistic approach to free will that drew from Cicero’s critique of fatalism. |
49 | The concept of “fortuna” in the Renaissance literature, notably in Machiavelli’s The Prince, echoes Cicero’s discussions on fate by emphasizing the balance between external circumstances and human agency. |
50 | Petrarch’s admiration for Cicero led to the widespread revival of Ciceronian ideals during the Renaissance, influencing figures such as Erasmus and Thomas More. |
51 | Cicero’s nuanced stance on fate and freedom influenced later Enlightenment thinkers, including Rousseau and Montesquieu, who sought to reconcile necessity with moral responsibility (Berlin 1976). |
52 | The philosophical discussions on fate and free will continued in early modern philosophy, particularly in Descartes’ theory of innate ideas, Leibniz’s concept of pre-established harmony, and Kant’s transcendental idealism, which sought to balance determinism and autonomy (Kuehn 2001). |
53 | The enduring relevance of Cicero’s ideas can be seen in modern discussions on political philosophy, particularly in liberalism and republicanism, where his emphasis on virtue and civic responsibility continues to inspire contemporary thought (Pocock 1975). |
References
Primary Sources
Cicero, Marcus Tullius. 1923. De Divinatione, in: On Old Age. On Friendship. On Divination. Translated by William Armistead Falconer. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Cicero, Marcus Tullius. 1933. De Natura Deorum, in: On the Nature of the Gods. Academics. Translated by Harris Rackham. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Cicero, Marcus Tullius. 1942. De Fato, in: On the Orator: Book 3. On Fate. Stoic Paradoxes. Divisions of Oratory. Translated by Harris Rackham. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Cicero, Marcus Tullius. 1998. The Republic and The Laws. Translated by Niall Rudd. With an Introduction and Notes by Jonathan Powell and Niall Rudd. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Secondary Sources
- Akopyan, Ovanes, ed. 2021. Fate and Fortune in European Thought ca. 1400–1650. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Baker, Patrick. 2015. Italian Renaissance Humanism in the Mirror. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Berlin, Isaiah. 1976. Vico and Herder: Two Studies in the History of Ideas. New York: Viking Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bobzien, Susanne. 1998. Determinism and Freedom in Stoic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Brennan, Chris. 2017. Hellenistic Astrology: The Study of Fate and Fortune. Denver: Amor Fati Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Brennan, Tad. 2005. The Stoic Life: Emotions, Duties, and Fate. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Brittain, Charles. 2001. Philo of Larissa: The Last of the Academic Sceptics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Epictetus. 1995. Discourses. Translated by William Abbott Oldfather. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Frede, Michael. 2011. A Free Will: Origins of the Notion in Ancient Thought. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Grafton, Anthony. 2000. Defenders of the Text: The Traditions of Scholarly Editing in the Renaissance. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hankinson, Robert James. 1998. Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Homer. 1999. The Iliad. Translated by Robert Fagles. New York: Penguin Books. [Google Scholar]
- Inwood, Brad. 1985. Ethics and Human Action in Early Stoicism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Inwood, Brad. 2005. Stoicism: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kuehn, Manfred. 2001. Kant and Cicero. In Kant und die Berliner Aufklärung: Akten des IX. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Edited by Volker Gerhardt, Rolf-Peter Horstmann and Ralph Schumacher. Berlin: de Gruyter, vol. III, pp. 270–78. [Google Scholar]
- Long, Anthony A. 2006. Stoic Studies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Long, Anthony A., and David N. Sedley. 1987. The Hellenistic Philosophers, Volume 1. Translations of the Principal Sources, with Philosophical Commentary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lucretius. 1992. De Rerum Natura. Translated by William Henry D. Rouse, and Martin Ferguson Smith. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Oakeshott, Michael. 1986. The Politics of Faith and the Politics of Scepticism. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. 1902. Timaeus. In Platonis Opera. Oxford: Clarendon Press, vol. 4. [Google Scholar]
- Pocock, John Greville Agard. 1975. The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rist, John Michael. 1972. Stoic Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sedley, David. 2006. Creationism and Its Critics in Antiquity. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Vernon, Paul. 1998. A History of the Portuguese Fado. Brookfield: Ashgate. [Google Scholar]
- White, Michael J. 2003. Stoic Natural Philosophy (Physics and Cosmology). In The Cambridge Companion to The Stoics. Edited by Brian Inwood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 124–52. [Google Scholar]
- Wynne, John P. F. 2019. Cicero on the Philosophy of Religion: On the Nature of the Gods and On Divination. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Grande Sánchez, P.J. The Greek Philosophical Sources in Cicero’s De Fato. Religions 2025, 16, 824. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070824
Grande Sánchez PJ. The Greek Philosophical Sources in Cicero’s De Fato. Religions. 2025; 16(7):824. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070824
Chicago/Turabian StyleGrande Sánchez, Pedro José. 2025. "The Greek Philosophical Sources in Cicero’s De Fato" Religions 16, no. 7: 824. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070824
APA StyleGrande Sánchez, P. J. (2025). The Greek Philosophical Sources in Cicero’s De Fato. Religions, 16(7), 824. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070824