2.1. Identity and Meaning for ‘Psychological Man’
I begin with a discussion of the work of Philip Rieff (1922–2006), for whom the contemporary approach to identity and meaning is synonymous with what he calls ‘psychological man’. Rieff was an early commentator on a developing cultural hegemony as regards human self-understanding, which he considers the result of Freudian psychology. Rieff is particularly fruitful for this discussion because he incorporates his diagnosis of contemporary personhood into a broader theory as to the nature and purpose of culture itself. He is also exceptional for his time, being a sociologist who assumes the necessity of religion, or the ‘sacred’, for culture to function properly
as culture, which will be explained below. Insofar as Rieff considers post-Freudian human self-understanding to have effectively displaced the role of religion, he understands contemporary culture as an ‘anti-culture’ and not culture as such. (
Rieff 2006, p. 13). Put in terms of the Gaudium et spes definition above, for Rieff, culture no longer cultivates the goods and values of human nature, and therefore no longer functions as culture proper.
Rieff presents ‘psychological man’ as the dominant ‘type’ of the contemporary human being. Psychological man appears last on a developmental typological scheme that begins in Ancient Greece with ‘political man’. In the classical world, says Rieff, ‘the health and stability of a person is analogous to—and moreover, dependent upon—the health and stability of the political order’. ‘Greek political philosophy’ was, therefore, also ‘Greek psychology’, he claims, for society and selfhood were basically coterminous (
Rieff 1990, pp. 3–4). Rieff writes that this type was superseded by ‘religious man’, most obviously in the European Christendom which Rieff holds adapted ‘Greek intellectualism’ to Christianity, resulting in a ‘Western personality type’ that posited faith ‘as superior to reason’ (Ibid.). Yet society and selfhood remain basically coterminous for ‘religious man’, it is just that faith is given the prominent role, and the symbolic system at play is the Christian religion. There is a significant change in the modern period, however, when Rieff’s third type, ‘economic man’, holds sway. This is described as ‘one who could rationally cultivate his very own garden, meanwhile solacing himself with the assumption that by thus attending to his own lower needs a general satisfaction of the higher needs would occur’ (Ibid.) Here, selfhood and society begin to draw apart but are not separated. The collective needs of society are still a crucial element for human self-understanding and meaning, although they now stand secondary to the ‘lower’, individual, needs.
Rieff is clear that ‘economic man’ was swiftly replaced by ‘psychological man’ during the advent of modernity. During this replacement, individual responsibility for and toward the social order is steadily eroded. Psychological man is described as ‘profoundly sceptical of the received hierarchy of values to which even his immediate predecessors assented’ (Ibid.). Psychological man ‘lives by the ideal of insight—practical, experimental, and leading to the mastery of his own personality’ (Ibid.). In short, it is not the polis, a religion, nor economic participation that is now the centre of gravity for human self-understanding; it is one’s own sense of self.
Any typology like this, especially so briefly summarised, cannot constitute an exhaustive historical scheme. Nor should it, for, as put by Antonius A.W. Zondervan, Rieff offers ‘a theory of ideation, dealing with character ideals that were or are used to form human identities’ (
Zondervan 2005, p. 46). In the case of psychological man, the most significant factor is the loss of connectedness to both the natural and the social order, resulting in Rieff’s distinctive understanding of individualism. In terms of nature, Rieff holds that premodern political and religious ideals involved a set of assumptions about reality, in which ‘[q]uestions about how to live smoothly passed into descriptions of human nature’ and an ethos consisted in offering a total view of reality and ideas’. Then, we read, ‘“is” and “ought” blended in a natural way’ (
Rieff 1963, p. 15). For psychological man, by contrast, ‘the universe is neither accepted or rejected; it is merely there for our use’. Psychological man is an ‘autonomous individual’ who ‘establishes his freedom to choose from the possibilities’ available to him (
Zondervan 2005, p. 29). As regards society at large, psychological man tends toward isolation, being the expression of the Freudian contention that ‘instinctual desires are “egoistic” by nature’ (Ibid., p. 36).
2 Psychological man considers his personal identity to be found in exploring his ego-centred instincts.
This leads in turn to how meaning functions for Rieff’s psychological man. The instincts are the primary source of identity, which, by being expressed or released, offer ‘[i]ndividual autonomy’ as ‘the highest goal to be attained’ (Ibid., p. 49). Autonomy is thus what renders life meaningful. This is not about mere self-direction, but more specifically about disregarding that which restrains or prohibits. In psychological man, the connection between identity/meaning and society is severed. Psychological man finds meaning by seeking ‘to wean away the ego from either [an] heroic or a compliant attitude to the community’ (
Rieff 1979, pp. 329–30). Meaning is found through distancing oneself from social and cultural norms. The ‘self is now conceived of as an “authentic core”’, and to find meaning the human being must accept that ‘social and cultural demands alienate man from this inner core’ (
Zondervan 2005, p. 52).
Rieff claims that, for political and religious man, such meaning was found through ‘modes of willing obedience, or faith, in which he found a sense of wellbeing and, also, his freedom from that single criterion’ (
Rieff 1987, p. 14). This means that the prior cultural systems brought consolation to one’s sense of self in ways that reduced or even eliminated the drive for self-satisfaction. In modernity, the criterion of wellbeing holds sway. Wellbeing is co-extensive with the satisfaction of instinctive desire, and Reiff suggests wellbeing has become a telos of meaning in and of itself. For Reiff, all of this follows from the unshackling of sets of communal and social expectations like religion, tradition, accepted mores or norms, and so on.
Independently of Rieff’s work, wellbeing has indeed become a watchword for approaching ‘meaning’ in contemporary Western culture (See
Williams 2024). He thus seems almost prophetic in having diagnosed this development early on, although he charts his scheme much farther back in the past. He gives particular importance to the emergence of psychological man in Jean-Jacques Rousseau, who held that people ‘must free themselves from finding attachments to communal purposes in order to express more fully their individualities’, and also Marx, who, along with Freud, so critiqued existing social norms that psychological man operates with a marked hermeneutic of suspicion toward them (
Zondervan 2005, p. 78). The upshot of this is a marked distrust of what were once held to be authorities, like religion or the polis, so that the individual ‘chooses for himself…his exemplary authority figures’ (Ibid., p. 49). Indeed, the ‘highest authority’ is then the solitary individual’s own ‘power of judgement’ (Ibid.), the untrammelled exercise of which is thought to guarantee wellbeing itself.
Psychological man is so-called not only because of the ego-centred and therefore psychological frame of reference, but because the very praxis of psychoanalysis is emblematic of its primary characteristics. Rieff argues that ‘the psychotherapeutic situation’ aptly demonstrates this, involving the separation of the individual from the social dimension insofar as, in the consulting room, ‘the individual is temporarily exempted from social demands’ (Ibid., p. 77). If the supreme authority is the polis or a religion, by contrast, the loci of transformative moments would surely be communal gathering places, be they legislative or liturgical. It is also important that Rieff describes psychological man as not merely indifferent to religion, but as evincing a consistently ‘anti-metaphysical character’ as a ‘basic motif’. The founding myths of our epoch, says Rieff, are ‘scientific myths’, which are ‘myths of revolt against transcendence … designed to free individuals from their psychological thraldom to primal forms’ (
Rieff 1979, p. 205).
2.2. Rieff’s Theory of Culture
I now want to touch on how Rieff presents a distinctive theory of culture, developing directly out of his diagnosis of psychological man. As put by Zondervan, Rieff considers that ‘psychoanalysis is not only a thing and a technique, but also a cultural phenomenon with tremendous influence’, because ‘psychological modes of explanation have become so vastly influential and penetrating that we have been witness to the emergence of a new ideology that now dominates Western culture’ (
Zondervan 2005, p. 42). While the preoccupation with Freud and Marx is symptomatic of Rieff’s situation as a sociologist writing in the mid- to late 20th century, Rieff’s presentation of psychological man has clear resonances with Western culture in the 2020s, as seen by the prior discussion of ‘wellbeing’. Rieff has proved influential for various cultural commentators in recent years, for whom he has prophetic import for claiming early on that the place once held by revering the social order of human life is now replaced by celebrating ‘an exploration of man’s erotic capabilities’, through cultivating the apparently ‘infinite possibilities of the self’ (Ibid., p. 9).
3The point for his cultural theory is that making the unbridling of Eros into the central coordinate of human identity and meaning is seen by Rieff as an unravelling of culture itself. This can be elucidated by drawing attention to the nuances of Rieff’s reading of Freud, especially as regards tensions inherent to the Freudian corpus. Rieff distinguishes Freud the therapist from Freud the theorist, observing a difference when it comes to the unbridling of Eros. As a therapist, Rieff considers Freud to have felt the solution to ‘neurosis is for the individual to replace traditional, cultural, religiously based mechanisms of repression’ (Ibid., p. 39). This is the modus operandi of psychological man. As a theorist, Rieff notes that Freud concedes, however, ‘that the maintenance of social order and culture demands a degree of repression of instinctual energies’ (Ibid.). This second, apparently neglected element of Freud offers the basis for Rieff’s theory. He understands culture to be that which maintains social order through fostering the adaptation of instinctive desires into communal goods. Culture is defined by Rieff as ‘a design of motives directing the self outward, toward those purposes in which alone the self can be realized and satisfied’ (
Rieff 1987, p. 4).
Rieff considers culture the distinctively ‘human
habitus’, because ‘it is typically human to create particular symbolic worlds in our striving for a meaningful life’ (
Zondervan 2005, p. 6). To approach a meaningful life as the expression of one’s ‘authentic core’ of identity, unshackled by social or collective expectations, cannot constitute ‘culture’, not only because culture by definition fosters the adaptation of the instincts to those expectations, but also due to the difficulty of establishing a shared ‘symbolic world’ for our contemporary context. Since Rieff was writing, multiculturalism, globalisation, and digital technologies have arguably exacerbated a state of collective ‘symbolic impoverishment’ (Ibid., p. 74), where the symbolic systems available are not widely shared within societies, and those on offer are often fragmented, niche, ‘recombinational’, self-chosen, and self-constructed.
4 The contemporary individual therefore ‘has tremendous difficulty in identifying the credible ideals and ideal figures that help give direction to life’ (Ibid., p. 7).
Interestingly, Rieff closely links religion and culture. He holds that premodern cultural processes posited a ‘sacred order’ that ‘structured, organised, and maintained the psychological and social order’ (Ibid., pp. 68–69). Collective or social expectations were grounded in shared suppositions toward a transcendent ordering. From that primordial ordering, with its ‘unseen processes’, came forth a ‘character ideal’ (
Rieff 1987, p. 246). For religious man, this was a ‘soteriological character ideal’: ‘the ultimate incarnation of the divine, in Jesus the Saviour, expressed itself time and again as an ideal in the lives of those…identifying with Jesus’ (
Zondervan 2005, p. 70). The primal character ideal was made concrete by the ‘cultus’, the religious practices by which individuals ‘were trained, through ritual action, to express fixed wants, without receiving commensurate gratification’ (Ibid., p. 70). Cultus is thus central to culture, properly construed. It makes concrete, available, and efficacious the ultimate character ideal that shows forth a ‘sacred order’. Through participation in the cultus, premodern humanity ‘internalised a symbolic representation of salvation, which was the basis for emotional stability and social integration’ (Ibid., p. 72). There is no such cultus for psychological man. The consulting room has taken its place. Yet, for Rieff, ‘[c]ulture without cultus’ is ‘a contradiction in terms’ (
Rieff 1987, p. 14).
2.3. Identity and Meaning in ‘Expressive Individualism’
My second interlocutor is Carl R. Trueman, whose use of the concept of ‘expressive individualism’ I want to focus on. Expressive individualism describes a tendency very similar to the behaviours of Rieff’s psychological man, which Trueman also draws on directly. He takes expressive individualism from Charles Taylor’s
Sources of the Self (
Taylor 1989). To begin by describing how identity is understood within this tendency, it is necessary to focus first on its individualism. For Taylor, one of the defining features of the changes in human self-understanding in modernity was the emergence of what he calls ‘inwardness’, or rather, the connection of inwardness with identity, from whence ‘the inner psychological life’ is seen ‘as decisive for who we think we are’ (
Trueman 2020, p. 22). Identity is individual because it is found ‘within’ the individual’s sense of self. The notion of human identity in expressive individualism thus relates to Rieff’s description of an ‘authentic core’, although for Trueman, it is not so much about the unconscious, and less directly Freudian thereby; being related to our general ‘feelings and desires’ (Ibid., p. 45).
Rousseau proves as important for Trueman as he did for Rieff. The former’s
Confessions takes as its subject matter precisely what Taylor calls inwardness, for Rousseau himself describes the ‘particular object’ of the book as ‘my inner self, exactly as it was in every circumstance of my life’ (
Rousseau 2000, p. 270). Rousseau’s basic contention is thus that ‘the heart of what constitutes a person is the inner psychological life’ (
Trueman 2020, p. 105). It almost goes without saying that typical premodern understandings of ‘the heart of what constitutes a person’ would be located in things like religious belonging, family, or kinship, and therefore inwardness is, in a certain sense, a literal turning within to locate identity, whereas once people turned without. Indeed, Trueman argues that this turning away from others is what constitutes human dignity for Rousseau, individuals ‘having an integrity and a value that derives from their inward self-consciousness and not from the society in which they exist’ (Ibid., p. 122).
By asking what sort of identity emerges from this inward focus, certain distinctive emphases of Trueman come to light. Trueman’s work is concerned with understanding the sexual revolution, from its earliest origins in people like Rousseau and the Romantics all the way to its distinctive expression in the controversies around sex, gender, and sexuality in the identity politics of the 2020s. A focus on ‘inward desires’ leads, for Trueman, to an understanding of ‘identity itself’ as ‘strongly sexual in nature’ (Ibid., p. 52). The key interlocutor for this development is Percy Bysshe Shelley, who ‘equates’ happiness with the satisfaction of ‘sexual love’ (Ibid., p. 153). For Trueman’s reading of Shelley, the meaning of life is to achieve personal happiness, or ‘pleasurable sensation’. This amounts to acquiring ‘an inner sense of psychological wellbeing’ inextricable from the satisfaction of sexual desire (Ibid., p. 153).
This leads to understanding the function of the word ‘expressive’ in expressive individualism, and indeed toward the notion of meaning synonymous with it. Expressive individualism is described by Trueman as the contention that ‘each of us finds our meaning by giving expression to our own feelings and desires’ (Ibid., p. 45). The key point is not just that identity is found inwardly, then, but that meaning is found by expressing the inner sense of self. As put originally by Taylor, this is the endemic assumption that ‘each of us has his/her own way of realising our humanity’, and, ‘it is important to find and live out one’s own, as against surrendering to conformity with a model imposed on us from outside’ (
Taylor 2007, p. 475). Enacting the ‘public performance of inward desires’ thus renders life meaningful (
Trueman 2020, p. 52). Trueman further describes this mindset as one in which ‘the individual is most authentic when acting out in public those desires and feelings that characterise his inner psychological life’ (Ibid., p. 122). With Shelley, particularly, sexual liberation becomes linked to political liberation, that is, tackling traditional restraints on an individual’s sexual expression as things obstructive of individual happiness. Again, thereby, we can see Trueman’s concern with the identity politics of the 2020s at work, insofar as attitudes to sex and sexuality are in contemporary culture broadly indistinguishable from political commitments and allegiances.
2.4. Trueman’s Responses
It is to Trueman’s credit that he engages in the difficult task of thinking prescriptively, and not just descriptively or diagnostically, about the problems he outlines with expressive individualism. On this front, he makes the salient point that the sheer depth and ubiquity of expressive individualism is such that it is unrealistic and naïve to consider that people today might somehow reinhabit premodern suppositions about identity and meaning. As he puts it, ‘we are all expressive individuals now, and there is no way we can escape from this fact’; ‘[i]t is the essence of the world in which we have to live and of which we are a part’ (Ibid., p. 386). Trueman argues from a Christian perspective throughout the book, yet he is candid about how even today’s Christianity is expressively individualistic, insofar as anyone living in the West has at least some measure of choice where and with whom they worship, or indeed whether they worship at all. A religious community is highly unlikely to have the assumed, unreflective authority it once did for many. It is therefore difficult to imagine a religion being a locus of identity and meaning without some dimension of individualistic expression being caught up with it (Ibid.).
In responding to this state of affairs, Trueman suggests that expressive individualism is not, in and of itself, an ‘unmitigated evil’ (Ibid.). This enables him to make a sort-of apologetic move which looks for a point of contact in cultural settings exterior to Christian faith with a view to presenting the faith through that point of contact—making the faith thereby more understandable, or perhaps even seeking the redemption or sanctification of that setting.
5 The point of contact in the case of expressive individualism is for Trueman ‘the emphasis it places on the inherent dignity of the individual’. Trueman even goes as far as to suggest that this ‘marks a significant improvement on that which it replaced’, mentioning ‘medieval’ and other ‘hierarchical’ societies in which some human beings were thought to be ‘worth more than others because of their position within the social hierarchy’ (Ibid., pp. 386–87).
It is at this juncture that Trueman seems to decide that expressive individualism is nonetheless unsuited to offer a point of contact with Christianity. Here, ‘one of the problems with the modern political project becomes clear’, we read, for expressive individualism might assume our equal worth, but it does not root that contention in the ‘idea that all human beings are made in the image of God’ (Ibid., p. 387). The imago Dei is thus presented as a corrective to expressive individualism. The image promises to correct the foundational error of that individualism, which locates personal identity in the inner sense of the self and not in the human mirroring of God. An implication attendant to this contention is that meaning is then something encountered on the basis of the imago Dei—presumably suggesting that it is the realisation of God’s image ‘in’ ourselves that renders life meaningful, not the expression of one’s inward identity or ego-centred sense of self. If human dignity is the truthful element of expressive individualism, then, Trueman suggests giving that element a proper footing by focusing on our being made in the image of God.
2.5. Observations
I will now present three observations arising from my discussion of Rieff and Trueman, focusing on what the implications of that discussion are for responding theologically to these commentators’ diagnoses of contemporary culture. Firstly, we might ask whether ‘equal worth’ or ‘inherent dignity’ is the primary feature of expressive individualism and psychological man. For the former, Trueman considers the controversies of contemporary identity politics as emblematic of it, yet some argue that this politics directly undermines the notion of equal dignity, especially if compared to classical liberalism (
Pluckrose and Lindsay 2020). For the latter, psychological man appears rather amoral and deterministic; it is not that instinctive desires are seen as essentially good or dignified, it is that ‘wellbeing’ is achieved by satisfying them, and self-satisfaction is the only route to wellbeing, regardless of any moral consideration.
It appears that it is not the value of one’s inwardness and/or instinctive desires that constitute the primary mark of these elements of contemporary culture, but rather the contention that each human being has a distinctly personal, and indeed unique, identity that pertains to him or her exclusively. While notions of ‘autonomy’, ‘inwardness’, and extricating the self from community are of course problematic for Christian theology, it is also the case that the notion of an acutely personal individual identity has Scriptural warrant, and indeed this warrant could be seen as neglected in exclusively socially orientated approaches to identity, focused only on family or kinship and so on. Most obviously, there is the Psalmist’s declaration that ‘it was you who formed my inward parts/you knit me together in my mother’s womb’, and that ‘My frame was not hidden from you/when I was being made in secret/intricately woven in the depths of the earth/Your eyes beheld my unformed substance’ (Ps 139:13, 15–6). There is Isaiah’s contention that ‘The Lord called me before I was born/while I was in my mother’s womb he named me’ (Is 49:1), and his references to God calling human beings ‘by name’ (e.g., Is 43.1). There is also the New Testament linking of individual identity with Christ, most obviously in the Apostle’s statement that ‘your life is hidden with Christ in God’ (Col. 3:3) and his acutely personal soteriology of ‘the Son of God, who loved me and gave himself for me’ (Gal. 2:20).
A second observation relates to Rieff and Trueman’s presentation of the notion of meaning in contemporary culture. Psychological man is a person determined by his or her instinctual drives, and for whom the meaning of existence is to satisfy those desires. The obvious problem here is that the satisfaction of the instincts can only dubiously be considered a fully meaningful category for human life, insofar as Rieff presents those drives as something not subject to self-reflective critique. That is, he presents therapy not as the subjecting of those instincts to discernment and deliberation, but rather just an identification of them with a view to fostering their unquestioned satisfaction. This approach to meaning is, therefore, in keeping with Rieff’s definition of contemporary culture as an ‘anti-culture’, meaningless in the specific sense that the instincts are akin to mere biological impulses. What renders biological life meaningful are processes of deliberative self-reflection, the interplay of intelligent consciousness with embodied life, and indeed, for Christianity, movements of the heart, especially love. Such considerations are, if not precluded by psychological man, at least not intrinsic to his or her pursuit of meaning. What is required by way of a Christian theological response is an approach to meaning that therefore incorporates the centrality of wisdom and love into what renders significance in human lives.
With Trueman, the same observation applies, although the accent in Trueman’s diagnosis is less on our being determined by the instincts and more on the application of individual will in the pursuit of meaning. That is, the expression of desire, the human being acting out his or her desires according to his or her own personal choices, is primary. Despite this difference of accent, however, the net result is more or less the same—an approach to meaning which threatens meaninglessness, insofar as the only directing criterion for the expression of one’s will is whether it pertains to oneself or not, with little or no prudential reflection on whether it should be expressed at all. Similarly, the untethering of sexuality from its intertwining with considerations of love presents a markedly arbitrary approach to meaning, where each will can simply be expressed as each person sees fit, with no overarching criteria for discerning the good or the true. Again, therefore, what is required in response to this is an approach to meaning that incorporates the centrality of wisdom and love into what renders significance in human lives.
A third observation centres on the place of religion in Rieff and Trueman. Starting with Rieff, there are many things in his diagnosis of the contemporary scene that are potentially fruitful for formulating a Christian theological response. Foremost among these is the centrality he gives to religion within his theory of culture, and one of the most interesting and innovative elements of his thought is how he places ‘a sacred order’ at the heart of any culture that is properly so-called. Rieff was indeed radical for having advocated for ‘the inclusion of transcendence in modern social theory’ (
Zondervan 2005, p. 72), being a sociologist writing in the mid-20th century. Yet, from a theological perspective, it is that sociological purview that presents certain challenges. That is, for a sociologist, ‘religion’ is a category for describing particular types of human behaviour across different cultures. For a theologian, there are always questions of the veracity and effectiveness of some specific religion’s suppositions about God, the world, and humanity.
For Rieff, ‘[e]very culture originates in ideas which belong to a sacred order of existence’, and culture mediates the ‘shaping of profane out of sacred prototypes’ (Ibid., p. 5). The purpose of culture, and indeed therefore the purpose of religion itself, is to foster ‘emotional stability and social integration’ (Ibid., p. 70). Rieff is unconcerned with differentiating between the differently articulated goods of different religions, or indeed different groupings or denominations within those religions.
6 It is ‘premodern belief systems’ which are discussed in general terms as having been ‘formed to curb human expressiveness’ (Ibid., 72). That said, Rieff’s main points of reference are from his own Jewish background and from Christianity, seen particularly for the latter in his focus on the ‘soteriological character ideal’ symbolised by Jesus. This is described by him as ‘the highest level of controls and remissions’ that ‘experienced an historical and individualised incarnation’ (
Rieff 1987, p. 246). But the understanding
of salvation here is not that of Christian soteriology, for it aims at the ‘integration of an individual in a community through integration in a communal social order’ (
Zondervan 2005, p. 84). While not wanting to detract from the importance of ‘emotional stability and social integration’ as civic and natural goods, nor indeed to detract from the fruitfulness of Christianity for fostering such goods, they remain civic, natural, or earthly goods, and do not adequately capture the radical transformation by grace that follows from baptism’s liberating of the individual from culpability for Original Sin.
By contrast, Trueman writes from a self-consciously Christian perspective, and as such he is aware of the disciplinary orientation of Rieff’s work having certain limits when viewed from a theological perspective. He summarises the issue directly by writing that, for Rieff, religion’s ‘purpose lay not so much in its actual truth value as in its social function in providing transcendent, supernatural authoritative rationale’ for the prohibition of certain behaviours (
Trueman 2020, pp. 74–75). Trueman’s awareness of this point is aptly shown by his recourse to the imago Dei, a distinct conceptuality held to correspond to reality within one religious tradition and not a shared ‘premodern’ commitment, as such. It is noteworthy, however, that in making this recourse Trueman seems to remain within the ‘immanent frame’ of the sociologist, for whom religion is a general category referring to social behaviours and not particular revealed realities. He criticises expressive individualism for detaching ‘individual dignity’ from any ‘grounding in
a sacred order’, not the specific understanding of what is sacred that pertains to the Christian religion (Ibid., 387 my emphasis). The issue is not whether a particular understanding of the sacred corresponds to reality and is thereby an antidote to the problems of contemporary life, but rather that there isn’t
any understanding of the sacred that is widely shared. As Trueman writes, modernity ‘cuts us off from any agreed-on transcendent metaphysical order by which our culture might justify itself’ (Ibid., p. 388). A ‘sacred or metaphysical order is necessary for cultures’, we read, ‘to remain stable and coherent’ (Ibid., p. 393).
A properly Christian and indeed Catholic theological response will need to go further than this, entering into the specifics of how the transcendent God as revealed in the witness of the Church presents a distinctive understanding of human identity and meaning. This is not mere triumphalism or tribalism, but rather a highlighting of the need for a theological response to flesh out the details of how to understand the ‘sacred order’, ‘transcendence’, or the ‘metaphysical’, to present a properly theological understanding of identity and meaning. This contention is drawn from Joseph Ratzinger’s comments about how it is the ‘universal human disposition toward the truth’ that should guide intercultural encounters between Christian and other cultural settings, rather than the sidelining of difficult ‘truth claims’ as prohibitive of ‘seeking union’ (
Ratzinger 1993).
On the basis of these three observations, I will now inquire into how bringing the divine idea of the self into this discussion will move things forward. The divine idea of the self is, by definition, acutely personal, and acutely personal in a way that perhaps the imago Dei is not, at least as it is commonly approached. The divine ideas have, moreover, been considered as a vital element for understanding creatureliness as subject ultimately neither to deterministic necessity nor arbitrary choice, but rather as presupposing a centrality for wisdom and love. Finally, the doctrine of the divine ideas is inseparable from specific dogmatic commitments, including creation, but also most especially the doctrine of the Trinity, in particular the eternal generation of the Word or Logos. There are good grounds therefore for bringing the divine idea of the self into dialogue with contemporary culture.