4.1. Fanaticism in the Zhuangzi
The
Zhuangzi—one of the foundational texts of philosophical Daoism—takes an approach to behavior characteristic of fanaticism that is markedly different from the more conventional classical literature of its time. Examples of what Hushi 胡適 (d. 1962) described as “concern for the times” (youshi 憂時), or Xu Fuguan 徐復觀 (d. 1982) called “concerned consciousness” (youhuan yishi 憂患意識) (
Xu 2001), are generally portrayed with approbation in classical Chinese literature as the burden of duty felt by the ideal minister serving the state. The
Zhuangzi, however, turns this trope on its head and links anxiety to the sort of pathologically destructive and politically deleterious phenomena found in narratives like those of King Zhou. Indeed, the anxieties associated with fanaticism, both on the level of the individual and the wider political community, are a central theme of the text, and “the celebration of [madness] and the elevation of the [mad] person is a particular feature of the
Zhuangzi” (
McLeod 2021, p. 24). Characters within the text are described as being overcome with neuroses and fears injurious to body, mind, and spirit, even leading to gruesome deaths. Elsewhere, interrelated anxieties blindly impel others to behavior more traditionally associated with fanaticism, like ideologically entrenched dogmatism, the persecution of “deviant” or “heretic” members of the in-group, or violent crusades against out-group communities.
One of the common characteristics traditionally associated with fanaticism is a collective fervor targeting individuals that deviate from in-group orthodoxy and transgress sacred values that define in-group identity. Fanatical certainty (or need for certainty) belies fragile individual and group identities (
Katsafanas 2022, p. 191), and these insecurities have been directed against, for example, heretics during the Spanish Inquisition, counter-revolutionaries during Mao’s Cultural Revolution, and apostates within modern Jihadism. Examples of intolerant demonization and even violent persecution of deviant members of in-group “heretics” appear in consecutive passages in the fifth chapter. In one passage, Confucius, paragon of the dominant socio-political ethos of the Spring and Autumn period, self-righteously admonishes Shushan, a pariah whose punitive foot amputation served as a “scarlet letter,” stigmatizing him as a social reprobate. Consistent with the
Zhuangzi’s critical strategy, this character, who has been violently ostracized from civil society, possesses a perspicacity lacking in the sages of the Zhou tradition, and thus serves as a “barbarian sage” (
Sarafinas 2020, p. 101). Conversely, Confucius reflects an ideological blindness, unable to interpret Shushan’s brutal punishment as anything but a justified moral consequence of “the ugliness of his past behavior” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 48). Despite Shushan describing his punishment as the result of “not understanding affairs of the socio-political world” (
Cao 2023, p. 94), Confucius re-affirms his dogmatic insistence that, whereas his students “still have [their] intrinsic virtuosities whole and intact,” Shushan’s incomplete body equates to a corrupted virtue. Trying to reason with the ideologically dogmatic Confucius is futile, as “Heaven itself has inflicted this punishment” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 48). Contributing to the image of Confucius as intransigent and “dialectically invulnerable” (
Katsafanas 2022, p. 77), Tang dynasty commentator Cheng Xuanying 成玄英 pointed out his hypocrisy insofar as the historical Confucius, like Shushan, was himself politically disgraced when he “suffered hardship in Chen and Cai, was besieged in Shang and Zhou… thus, punishment by Heaven is inescapable” (
Cheng 2011, p.109). Adversarial dogmatism masquerading as self-righteousness emerges when a fanatical over-commitment to in-group identity confronts deviants from orthodoxy like Shushan. Similar to the sort of “dialectically invulnerable” belief perseverance exhibited by Confucius confronting in-group heretics, anxiety and unease is likewise generated when confronted with the out-group “barbarian”.
The
Zhuangzi explores the psychological insecurity caused by the other and the potential for fanatical violence and destruction it might instigate in a passage featuring Emperors Yao and Shun, mythical sages vaunted for their wisdom. The
Zhuangzi satirizes Yao as being overcome with anxiety because of the mere presence of political communities over which he does not rule, telling Shun “I want to attack Zong, Kuai, and Xu’ao, for though I sit facing south on the throne, still I am not at ease. Why is this?” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 18). “Not at ease” is one of the many expressions of anxiety used throughout the
Zhuangzi, interpreted by Chen Guying 陳鼓應 as “a seething mood obstructing his heart” (
Chen 2016, p. 96), and further described by Wang Bo:
Perhaps Yao felt that with his sagely virtue there should not be any place that is not transformed by his virtue in tianxia, but there are those outside [of tianxia]. This is something that the “self” cannot accept, and thus he wants to attack them.
Yao’s interlocutor, Shun, responds to his monomaniacal fixation on unifying all communities under one form of rule by referencing the mythical Archer Yi, who shot nine of the ten suns out of the sky. Shun urges him to consider “how much better are multiple virtuosities than multiple suns” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 18). Shun’s advice does not seem to have much traction with Yao, and in chapter four Confucius tells his disciple Yan Hui that “Yao attacked Cong Zhi and Xun Ao, and Yu invaded You Hu. Their nations were laid to waste and their bodies slaughtered. They were incessant in their use of force and insatiable in their quest for substantial goods” (
Ziporyn 2020, p.35).
Examples of fanatical zeal directed toward both in-group “heretics” and out-group “barbarians” include the epistemic, psychological, and moral dimensions that frame Western discourse on fanaticism. Confucius might be said to exhibit “epistemic overconfidence” (
Reginster 2024, p. 180), and Yao’s unease may be the product of resentment toward the out-group, a resentment according to which “it makes sense to demonize them, to hate them, even in the extreme case to destroy them” (
Katsafanas 2024, p. 10). What prevents a simplistic interpretation of the
Zhuangzi through this framework, however, is that these epistemic, psychological, and moral maladies are not presented as the causes of fanaticism, but as symptoms of it. The
Zhuangzi identifies a distinct root cause that might contribute to expanding contemporary discourse on the philosophy of fanaticism, that is, the linguistic and discursive causes of fanaticism.
One of the primary objects of the
Zhuangzi’s critical gaze is the fundamentally problematic nature of language itself and the destructive consequences it can lead to when not carefully attended. A form of speech frequently taken as an object of critique is
shifei 是非 discourse, a type of political speech problematic insofar as it has the tendency to ossify responses to political problems in a constantly transforming world and moralize them such that they evoke strong emotional responses.
Shifei carries many semantic implications in classical Chinese literature, reflected in the variety of its English translations, including right–wrong, true–false, and that is it–that is not it (
Ma and Van Brakel 2019, p. 31). As contrasted with more conventional classical literature, the term in the
Zhuangzi is overwhelmingly used critically in reference to the battles incited by moral discourse, such as those of the “Confucian and Mohist
shifei” or debates over what constitutes “humaneness and righteousness,” and thus is more accurately understood as “right and wrong.” The role that language and
shifei discourse plays in representing the world, naturalizing socio-political norms, and sacralizing ideologies is depicted as a condition for fanaticism, including but not limited to it various problematic psychological, epistemic, and behavioral symptoms.
The following addresses the Zhuangzi’s three primary critiques of the structure of language and discourse, particularly how they contribute to fanatical neuroses and pathologies within the individual and extremism and decay within the state. These critiques focus on the following: (1) the interdependence of binary linguistic terms that constitute shifei discourse; (2) the semiotic chains of cascading distinctions that confound attempts to ground shifei judgements; and (3) the relationship between unhealthy forms of language, thought, and anxieties, insofar as they are the products of a discursively conditioned fanaticism. The Qiwu Lun (齊物論 Equalizing Assessments of Things) chapter provides the most comprehensive critique of the structure of shifei language and discourse, and as such, will serve as the primary content of analysis.
4.2. Binary Terms of Dialectical Opposition
One of the fundamental characteristics of
shifei discourse subject to the
Zhuangzi’s critique is its valuation of terms within binary relationships of dialectical opposition, elevating one and condemning the other. This critique draws on similar insights from the
Laozi, a text with which the
Zhuangzi shares many themes, approaches, and language. The first chapter of the
Laozi establishes the theme of oppositional terms in the form of presence and non-presence, and the second chapter conceptually explores the relationship between these pairs as one characterized by “interdependence and mutual generation” (
Liu 2006, p. 382). Moreover, terms like “beautiful” and “good” are also moral evaluations, and thus not only necessarily imply their conceptual opposites “ugly” and “not good,” but frame these pairs such that one is socially, politically, and morally affirmed while the other is demonized.
The first chapter of the
Zhuangzi likewise establishes the theme of binary opposite terms, using the giant Peng and smaller creatures below him, and further extending it to “large” and “small” consciousness (zhi 知). The large–small distinction is repeated throughout the text, and while some have interpreted it as conveying a spiritual hierarchy of different daos or levels of wisdom (
Van Norden 1996, p. 258), it can be, and in the commentarial tradition has been read much like chapter two of the
Laozi, as a critique of the hierarchical structure of binaries. A non-hierarchical interpretation of the text’s treatment of these opposites is supported by the text’s first commentator, Guo Xiang:
Everything is sufficient to its nature. The giant Peng does not take himself to be more noble than the small birds and the small birds do not envy going to the Heavenly Pool, but are thriving in abundance. The small and the great each have their own particularity, and this is Wandering.
Dissolving any perceived value-laden distinction between large and small, Guo Xiang exhibits a recognition of differences devoid of a hierarchical evaluation, not preferentially weighing either side of the binary. Guo’s interpretation is consistent throughout the passage, with the line “what do these two creatures know” in reference to the large Peng and small Cicada, thus emphasizing that both large and small are equally ignorant, eradicating any perceived hierarchy.
The critique of binary relationships between large and small is fully developed in the second chapter, Qiwu Lun, expanding from consciousness (zhi 知) to language (yan 言). The application of this critique to language in chapter two is foreshadowed in the first sentence. Nan Guozi “releases his breath into the heavens above” and describes to his disciple the piping of heaven, earth, and man. Breath is here both symbolic of and literally a condition for speech, and the piping of earth is described as “tempered attunements, all their cunning contentions” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 12), representing the “arguments over
shifei by the mundane people. The producer of the noises has already left, but all the people emotionally grasp onto their own
shifei perspective.” (Shi Deqing in
Chen 2016, p. 49). Following this metaphorical illustration of speech and contentious discourse, the topic of language and discourse is made explicit, with large and small consciousness described as “idle and spacey” and “cramped and circumspect,” followed by large and small talk described as “bland and flavorless” and “detailed and fragmented.”
The semantics describing “large” and “small” language reaffirms the first chapter’s critique of hierarchically ranking large over small. Chen Guying interprets large and small talk as the speech of “arrogant people” and “those who ceaselessly argue” (
Chen 2016, pp. 53–54), respectively. Cao Chuji 曹礎基 describes the tone the text takes towards
shifei discourse along similar lines, arguing that
Large and small consciousness, large and small talk, and large and small fears in this section refer to the things said by people in argumentative debate about shifei, and thus should be considered derogatory… These two sentences mean: Those clever folk who think they are correct and fundamentally will not listen to the opinions of others, as well as those people with low and shallow intelligence and ability who are only able to haggle with others over minor peripheral problems.
The foolish arrogance and shallow intelligence of those who ceaselessly argue refers to the way in which people often speak past one another when engaged in various forms of emotionally charged debate. The Zhuangzi suggests that this is a result of shi and fei being binary opposites and thus are “interdependent and mutually generating” in the same way that the beautiful and ugly are described in the Laozi.
Extending this insight to the realm of language and discourse, the text shifts to the use of indexical pronouns, “this and that” (bishi 彼是). Within such a linguistic relationship, either side not only always refers to its opposite, but is entirely predicated on it for any meaning whatsoever, and thus “‘thatness’ emerges from ‘thisness,’ and ‘thisness’ follows from ‘thatness.’ This is its theory of the simultaneous generation of the ‘this’ and the ‘that.’” (14). Wang Fuzhi 王夫之 likewise notes the linguistic absurdities that result when hierarchically prioritizing one side of interdependent binaries, particularly when applied to the antagonistic realm of moral discourse and debate:
The small is not independently small- it appears small only in contrast to the large. But likewise, the large cannot be large on its own- it appears large only when set against the small. So the idle and spacey is also cramped and circumspect; the bland and flavorless is also detailed and fragmented. The idle and spacey is used to criticize the small consciousness, ridiculing its narrowness. Conversely, the cramped and circumspect is used to interrogate the vast consciousness, exposing how much it leaves out. The bland and flavorless is used to catch what small speech fails to grasp. Conversely, the detailed and fragmented is used to accentuate the insubstantiality of large talk. Thus, words arise competitively on all sides, taking shape as theories.
With a critical awareness that any affirmation of the large implies, is conditioned upon, and even generates the small, it becomes obvious that “ridiculing its narrowness” and “exposing how much it leaves out” are equally absurd. This is no mere accident or the product of an unhealthy culture particular to shifei discourse, but is a function of the very structure of a language and discourse predicated on binaries.
4.3. Semiotic Chains of Cascading Distinctions
According to the first level of the Qiwu Lun’s critique of language,
shifei discourse is informed by a preconditioned linguistic structure of oppositional binaries, like right and wrong or acceptable and unacceptable. The inflammatory, yet fundamentally paradoxical language is such that “one side is acceptable and the other side is unacceptable, one side is unacceptable and the other side is acceptable. The cause for [believing] something is right is the cause for [believing] something is wrong. The cause for [believing] something is wrong is the cause for [believing] something is right” (
Chen 2016, p. 70). The
Zhuangzi’s critique builds on this insight, further problematizing the arbitrary nature of standards by which
shifei judgements are made in the first place, a complexity exacerbated by the strong emotional dispositions they evoke. The text introduces this line of argument with Nan Guozi expressing uncertainty about the origins of the perpetually transforming emotional states of “joy and anger, sorrow and happiness, plans and regrets, transformations and stagnations, unguarded abandonment and deliberate posturing” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 12). These mercurial moods, “the emotional responses of those engaged in debate” (
Chen 2016, p. 56), both serve as the objects of
shifei debates and are the byproduct of this discursive wrangling.
Beyond causing emotional distress, the text further complicates matters, describing these emotional transformations as
something that is always very close to me indeed, and yet still I can never know what is doing the causing here. If there is in fact something in control of causing all this to happen, it is peculiarly devoid of any sign that could identify what it is.
What is hypothetically raised as that which is “in control” (zhenzai 真宰) is interpreted as a “natural ruler” (
Cao 2023, p. 24) or one’s “genuine heart-mind” (
Chen 2016, p. 58). The uncertainty surrounding a final and ultimate “ruler,” or a standard according to which these emotional states and realities (qing 情) might be judged as either shi or fei is continued in the next few lines:
The hundred bones, the nine openings, the six internal organs are all present here as my body. Which one is most dear to me?... If there is a genuine ruler among them, its genuineness would have to be of some kind that is the same whether any definite reality could ever be found for it or not.
Proposing and then problematizing the notion of an organ in the body being a “genuine ruler” puts this description in dialogue with one of the mainstream ideas from the Warring States period regarding the origins of moral predispositions, and thus a dependable standard according to which
shifei judgements can be made. The most well-known representative of the idea that human beings have an innate emotional predisposition that develops out of the heart is Mencius. Utilizing a number of rhetorical techniques, the
Zhuangzi “challenges Mencius’ assumption that one organ naturally deserves to rule the others” (
Hansen 1992, p. 278). The most damning and far-reaching critique of
shifei disputes, however, revolves around the notion of a “completed mind,” or
chengxin 成心.
The usage of
chengxin within the
Zhuangzi subverts the conventional understanding of cheng 成, an important concept within Confucian moral and political cultivation. The term is conventionally used to mean people or events being accomplished or brought to completion, or as the Analects records, “an exemplary person helps others to accomplish what is good and does not help them to accomplish what is bad.” (
Ni 2017, p. 292). The
Zhuangzi plays upon the internal paradoxes of this notion to problematize the presumption of any ultimate standard for
shifei judgement, the heart–mind in this case:
if we just follow whatever completed form of our minds (chengxin 成心) has so far taken shape, making that our master and teacher, who could ever be without a teacher? That is something even the most ignorant are always doing without fail. It is not as if the mind is first required to know all the alternating states and then actively selects for itself from among them the one to be taken as master and teacher. For the mind to be able to do that before any completed form has already taken shape in it, to make such an affirmation or negation about which form it will regard as right and which as wrong without already having taken some shape-that would be like leaving for Yue today and arriving there yesterday.
A
chengxin may very well provide a standard for judgement, but the
Zhuangzi brings attention to the paradoxical relationship between that which it judges and that on which it is predicated. A “completed mind” is employed to make distinctions between shi and fei, right and wrong, but being “completed” implies already having made a
shifei judgement, and thus any
chengxin is contingent on prior
shifei distinctions. Consequently, the very condition for establishing a standard for
shifei distinctions is yet another
shifei distinction, and thus “attempting to resolve disagreements over
shifei by judging them only introduces new issues of
shifei” (
Yang 2020, p. 57). Attachment to one amongst many equally arbitrary distinctions suggests that
chengxin entails “one who clings to the prejudice of a single view” (
Cheng 2011, p. 31) and “a biased mind” (
Chen 2016, p. 63). With any
shifei distinction being predicated upon prior
shifei distinctions, this process gives rise to semiotic chains of cascading distinctions—biased distinctions all the way down—or what the text refers to as the “peculiarly unfixed” (
te weiding 特未定) nature of language.
While the text does reference epistemic and psychological dimensions, the “biased minds” of debaters, and “peculiarly unfixed” language, the resulting dogmatic and violent struggles within
shifei debate are not primarily attributed to psychological defects, epistemic flaws, or moral failures. The
Zhuangzi, and the Qiwu Lun chapter in particular, directly relates a biased mind to discourse and language. Language is affirmed as having “something of which it speaks,” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 13); yet, without a solid foundational standard on which these endless semiotic chains of cascading distinctions can be anchored, language remains “peculiarly unfixed.” Based on the relativistic insight that “there are no objective criteria for right and wrong” (
Feng 2024, p. 82), individual partiality obscures dialogue, such that the words of others sound like “the chirping of baby birds” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 13). The issues that arise from the very structure inherent to discourse are not limited to mere linguistic paradoxes and miscommunications, however. Rather, the Qiwu Lun chapter describes the enthusiastic and fanatical consequences of
shifei debate resulting from the problematic nature of discourse and language itself.
4.4. Discourse and Fanaticism
The dogmatism with which the
Zhuangzi characterizes
shifei discourse is associated with more than mere dialectical intransigence, and its moralistic and political connotations can lead to individually, socially, and politically destructive tendencies. As discussed above, arguing for any particular proposition as “right” simultaneously defines that which conflicts with it as “wrong,” paradoxically creating precisely that which one negates, and “hence we have the rights and wrongs of the Confucians and Mohists, each affirming what the other denies and denying what the other affirms” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 14). Compounding the problematic nature of
shifei discourse, those affirmations and negations are conveyed with moralistic political language, and thus one not only creates that which they negate, but must also regard it as loathsome, detestable, and an imminent threat to moral and political order. Moral discourse becomes saddled with strong negative emotional attachments that can foster hostile, aggressive, and emotionally charged rhetoric. This element of language reinforces a stubborn allegiance to one’s own position and provokes reactionary opposition toward one’s adversary insofar as “moral language is combative and it serves to justify one’s self, condemn others, or both. It is always rhetorical and acts as a semantics that exploits facts or deeds in order to put oneself in a better light” (
Moeller 2009, p. 35). Moralistic
shifei discourse, moreover, served a political function in pre-Qin China, informing socio-political norms and state policy, and thus was an arena for officials to advance their reputation and career, or to win the “garlands of honor it itself brings on” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 14). Practical and professional concerns motivated moral posturing and the weaponization of righteousness to defeat one’s enemies and benefit oneself, exacerbating dogmatic intransigence in discourse. As a result of the paradoxical nature of language, and the strong emotional prejudices engendered through moralistic political speech and its socio-political institutionalization, the
Zhuangzi presents the contentions over
shifei as resulting in a range of psychological maladies that undermine the very socio-political commitments it purports to defend, harming the individual, community, and state.
The intimate relationship between consciousness 知 and talk 言 is expanded beyond the epistemic limitations of discursive structures to a third category, psychologically harmful anxieties, or “fears” (kong 恐). Like consciousness and talk, the text describes them according to a large–small binary, such that “the small fears leave us nervous and depleted, the large fears leave us stunned and blank.” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 12). Small and large fears have been interpreted by contemporary scholars as “the condition of being apprehensive” and “lost in the haze without spirit, driven to distraction” (
Chen 2016, p. 54), respectively, or as “terrified and on edge” and “dejected, down and out” (
Cao 2023, p. 22). Following the text’s initial characterization of small and large fears, they are further described as having an effect quite different from the apprehension and ennui associated with a “concerned consciousness.” The anxieties that emerge from a language of oppositional binaries and “peculiarly unfixed” standards derived from a biased mind likewise give rise to behaviors more traditionally associated with fanaticism:
Shooting forth like an arrow from a bowstring: thus is our presumption as we arbitrate right and wrong. Holding fast as if to sworn oaths: thus is our defense of our victories. Worn away as if by autumn and winter: such is our daily dwindle.
Anxiety underpins the passive despondency of the timid and hopeless, but it also animates the daring of the zealot and obstinacy of the dogmatist, resulting in individually destructive and socially disruptive uncritical over-commitments. The pathological anxiety expressed here parallels the enthusiasm and fanaticism critiqued by European Enlightenment thinkers. In contrast to Hobbes, Hume, and Kant, the Zhuangzi subordinates the epistemic and psychological dimensions—represented by small and large consciousness (zhi 知) and fears (kong 恐)—to the domain of language and discourse, problematizing the discursively conditioned nature of dogmatic pathologies found within the contentions over shifei.
Rather than sourcing fanaticism in epistemic, psychological, or moral failings, they are contextualized in the
Zhuangzi as originating from
shifei language and discourse. Cheng Xuanying, for example, commented on the three clauses above: “words arise as the mind follows external circumstances, swift as an arrow … words manipulate intentions of right and wrong, like oaths and vows… The ignorant only fight over the empty falsehoods of shi and fei” (
Cheng 2011, p. 26). The emphasis is not on language directing us to make the wrong distinction, as this would simply be an argument for an alternative standard for right–wrong, but on the harmful pathologies that inevitably emerge from a fanatical over-commitment to any moralistic/political form of discourse. Linguistically conditioned fanaticism can undermine those very moral and political commitments
shifei judgements are meant to affirm, or, as Liu Xiaogan wrote,
Confucianism and other religions or political factions emphasize the distinction between right and wrong, good and evil. This can inspire people to elevate their moral standards and maintain social harmony. However, overemphasizing the principles of right and wrong, good and evil may lead to the suppression of dissent, intensification of conflicts, division of communities, and the destructive consequences of hostility—sometimes even resulting in religious wars and international conflicts.
The
Zhuangzi’s problematization of an uncritical relationship with language indicates that it is not necessarily notions of right and wrong that lead to fanaticism, but an “overemphasis” on these distinctions. Yang Lihua 楊立華 likewise clarified that the “Zhuangzi wants to eliminate the contentions over
shifei, not
shifei itself” (
Yang 2022). Those who fail to recognize the mutually generating nature of
shifei binaries, the arbitrary and biased
chengxin on which
shifei judgements are made, and the dogmatic and overzealous tendencies produced by such contentions over
shifei, exhibit the sort of dogmatic and pathological characteristics commonly associated with fanaticism. Such examples of blind and chauvinistic dogmatism, as well as its noxious effects on both individuals and the political community, are exhibited throughout the
Zhuangzi.
4.5. Examples of Discursively Conditioned Fanaticism
The
Zhuangzi is replete with stories depicting pathological anxieties elicited by paradoxical and problematic forms of discourse. These discursively conditioned anxieties do not merely cause intense emotional stress for the individual, but also lead to untimely deaths, intractable political conflicts, and even genocidal tendencies. A direct association between language, anxious pathologies, and their fanatical consequences is articulated in chapter four by Confucius instructing Zigao, who, after having been tasked with acting as an envoy to the state of Qi, is riddled with anxiety and “sucking on ice chunks this evening, as if my insides were on fire!” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 38) Confucius warns Zigao of the reckless misuse of language, using imagery resembling that of Nan Guozi’s piping of earth metaphor for
shifei debate:
Words are like winds and waves… the rage comes forth for no apparent reason and the cunning words fly off on a tangent like the panicked cries of a dying animal with no time to choose. The breath and vital energy come to a boil and with that everyone becomes bloody-minded. As the feeling of being threatened reaches its zenith, the more unlovely states of mind come with it and nobody even notices it-and if they don’t realize what is happening to them, there is no saying where it will all end!
Communication between states, conveyed through envoys like Zigao, can lead to a destructive frenzy described according to characteristics commonly associated with fanaticism, like fragility of self, violent tendencies, and “another notable aspect of fanaticism: it seems to be contagious” (
Katsafanas 2024, p. 10). This last characteristic of fanaticism, its contagious nature, is also illustrated in the passages preceding and following the passage featuring Zigao.
Like Zigao, Yan Hui and Yan He are scholar-officials seeking guidance on advising rulers with violently fanatical tendencies. Yan Hui is preparing to serve the ruler of Wei, who “thinks nothing of the death of his people-nationfuls of corpses fill the marshes, clumped in piles like bunches of plantains” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 34). Yan He similarly describes the prince of Wei as one whose “virtue has been made murderous by Heaven.” These passages encapsulate the dilemma for officials trying to mitigate the destructive consequences of fanaticism: “if I find no way to contain him, he will endanger my state, but if I do try to contain him, he will endanger my life.” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 40). Regarding the danger to their lives, their mentors both warn that the logomachy of moralistic
shifei is “a way for people to one-up each other” and “a weapon of war” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 35). Yet, avoiding conflict through appeasement is equally dangerous as it risks ideological capture due to the contagious nature of discourse, thereby committing them to the very fanaticism destroying their state. They are cautioned: “if you let the external compromise get inside you, it will topple you, destroy you, collapse you, cripple you” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 40) until “finally your heart and mind will be completely formed by it” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 35). Ancient and contemporary scholars have recognized the danger of becoming entangled within a contagiously fanatical court. Guo Xiang commented that “if it gets inside you, you will be like all the others” (
Guo 2011, p. 87), and Wang Bo wrote “if going along turns into ‘entering inside’ then you will be wallowing in the mire with him” (
B. Wang 2004, p. 35). Wang Fuzhi similarly used language applicable to mass fanaticism:
The mind is singular, what disturbs it is shifei… the ignorant refuse to yield to the equally ignorant, leading to resentment and inflamed qi. One offends another’s mind and provokes another’s qi… The turmoil escalates until both sides bring disaster upon themselves, leading to death of the self and destruction of states, yet they still claim that their righteous indignation has been vindicated for eternity.
Thus, Yan Hui’s “anxiety cannot save” him (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 34). Rather than freeing the court from its ideological frenzy, he risks either his own death or becoming a fanatic himself and contributing to the destruction of Wei.
A full range of the paradoxical, pathological, and otherwise problematic characteristics of fanaticism and its discursive conditions, as illustrated in the
Zhuangzi, can be found in the text’s most comprehensive critique of the conventional socio-political ethos of its time, as articulated in the twenty-ninth chapter featuring Robber Zhi and Confucius. Confucius travels to see the infamous warlord Robber Zhi with the intention of morally rehabilitating him. Rather than repent, however, he rebukes Confucius, whose “crimes are the heaviest of anyone’s” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 239), for his hypocrisy and his role in perpetuating a harmful fanaticism. The consequences of a fanatical commitment to the ethos Confucius champions includes suicides, interstate wars and genocides, and institutional disorder. A number of historical figures whose moral zeal led to their own brutal deaths are listed, according to which “it is inferred that benevolence, righteousness, and ritual teachings are not only useless but also detrimental to human life, contrary to human nature, harmful to the people, and disruptive to society” (
D. Wang 2010, p. 131). Beyond self-inflicted harm, Robber Zhi points to the wide-scale destruction and genocide caused by the very sages sanctified by the hegemonic ethos. The Yellow Emperor, for example,
went to war with Chi You in the wilds of Zhuolu, until blood was flowing for a hundred miles around. Then Yao and Shun arose, setting up their throng of ministers. Thereafter Tang banished his own lord, and King Wu murdered Zhou. From that point onward, the strong have oppressed the weak and the many have violently imposed themselves on the few. Everyone from Tang and Wu onward has been just another disrupter of the people.
This insidiously destructive fanaticism is described as penetrating the institutions of socio-political order, such that it “confuses the world’s rulers and prevents the world’s scholars from ever returning to their root” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 239). The “disease” of fanaticism, the cause of its violence, destruction, and general disorder, is not presented as belonging to those dimensions that characterize European Enlightenment or contemporary discourse on fanaticism. Rather than laying the blame on epistemically, psychologically, or morally “bad apples,” Robber Zhi describes this fanaticism as stemming directly from an uncritical and excessively moralistic use of a paradoxical form of language and discourse.
In keeping with the critique of language and discourse that runs throughout the text, Robber Zhi specifically accuses Confucius of contributing to this violent and destructive fanaticism with his instrumentalization of language, weaponization of an arbitrary
shifei discourse, and exploitation of historical narratives. Upon first hearing that Confucius has come to visit him, he refers to him as “that crafty hypocrite from Lu,” criticizing him for “making up phrases and inventing terms, absurdly singing his panegyrics to King Wu and King Wen” and his “abundance of pretty phrases and ridiculous theories” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 239). Beyond being a mere charlatan, his crimes are much more insidious insofar as he has strategically appropriated moral discourse by “flapping his lips and clicking your tongue, monopolizing the production of judgments of right and wrong” (
Ziporyn 2020, p. 239). By “ironically reversing the standard historical narrative of the great Confucian-minded sages who civilized the world into a tale of continuous warfare, slaughter and corruption” (
Moeller 2022b, p. 297), Robber Zhi exposes how Confucius molded the hegemonic narrative to not only advance his own particular
shifei perspective, but furthermore sanctify and promote a zealous, fanatical commitment to it. Within the historical context of the text, the argument put in the mouth of Robber Zhi is perhaps indicative of the “increasing dissatisfaction with the moralizers’ utilization of history” in pre-Qin texts, and thus “Zhuangzi undermines the validity of the appeals to history as a whole” (
Pines 2022, p. 350). As is consistent throughout the text, the Robber Zhi passage does not necessarily criticize devotion to values like “filiality and brotherliness.” Rather, he critiques Confucius’ “insane fixation,” his paradoxical, absurd, and otherwise problematic use of language and moral discourse, which not only represents “a mass of deceitful, crafty, vain, hypocritical hooey” (
Ziporyn 2020, pp. 242–43), but leads to the individual pathologies, genocidal wars, and social decay characteristic of fanaticism.