Next Article in Journal
Mapping the Growth of the Nones in Spain: Dynamics, Diversity, and the Porous Boundaries of Non-Religion in the Postsecular Age
Next Article in Special Issue
Thinking Differently: Wittgenstein on Religious Forms of Life
Previous Article in Journal
The Crisis of Culture: Recovering Shared Meaning
Previous Article in Special Issue
Against Quasi-Fideism
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Wittgenstein, Religion and Deep Epistemic Injustice

by
Robert Vinten
Faculty of Social Sciences and Humanities, Universidade Nova de Lisboa, 1099-085 Lisbon, Portugal
Religions 2025, 16(4), 418; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040418
Submission received: 16 January 2025 / Revised: 19 March 2025 / Accepted: 21 March 2025 / Published: 25 March 2025
(This article belongs to the Special Issue New Work on Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Religion)

Abstract

:
In his article ‘Epistemic Injustice and Religion’, Ian James Kidd raises the possibility that some epistemic injustices might be deep. To spell out exactly what might be involved in deep epistemic injustices, especially those involving religious worldviews, an obvious place to look is Wittgenstein’s work on religion. Careful reflection on Wittgenstein’s remarks in the ‘Lectures on Religious Belief’ and his late work collected in On Certainty will have implications for how we are to understand the relationships between belief and evidence and for the ways in which we might enrich our hermeneutical sensitivities, and so Wittgenstein’s remarks are helpful for understanding epistemic injustices more generally. This paper will focus on epistemic injustices involving Islamophobia since Islamophobia has, so far, been given little attention in the literature on epistemic injustice.

1. Religion and Epistemic Injustice

The literature on epistemic injustice since the time of Miranda Fricker’s book Epistemic Injustice has had relatively little to say about discrimination on the basis of religion, despite the fact that religion is an arena of identity power (See Fricker 2007, p. 14). As Ian James Kidd notes, “the literature…is modest and mostly represented by the work of the eminent feminist philosopher of religion, Pamela Sue Anderson”.1 In her book, Re-visioning Gender in Philosophy of Religion, Anderson’s focus is on the ways in which the Christian religion unjustly silences women and downgrades their credibility, as well as upon academics in the philosophy of religion whose discussions of Christianity treat women unjustly. For example, she points to passages in the Bible that depict women as being at the bottom of a patriarchal hierarchy (e.g., Corinthians 11:3 “…the head of every man is Christ; and then head of the woman is the man; and the head of Christ is God” and Corinthians 11:7 “For a man indeed ought not to cover his head, forasmuch as he is the image and glory of God: but the woman is the glory of the man”) and she discusses how sexist passages in the Bible have been used to suppress the voices of Christian women (Anderson [2012] 2017, p. 14). Both Anderson and Kidd have noted that the abstract ways in which theodicies are formulated within the philosophy of religion can lead to injustices (ibid., p. 41). For example, John Hick has argued that there is a deep problem of evil which is the upshot of evils being “distributed in random and meaningless ways” (Hick 2010, p. 333) but, as Kidd observes, if we look at the way that terrible events and suffering are distributed in reality, we see that it is “socially and materially conditioned”, such that “certain groups of people—women and the poor, say—suffer more intensely and extensively from evils…its distribution is not ‘random’”(Kidd 2017, p. 391).2 The abstraction away from the reality of suffering and its connection to social identities is a source of epistemic injustice because it disregards the testimonies of those who suffer and distorts our understanding of evil.
While Anderson has focused on the ways in which religion and philosophers of religion have perpetrated injustices I want to particularly focus on the ways in which followers of a religion might be treated unjustly as followers of the religion in question. My focus will be on Islamophobia, which is arguably being promoted by leading figures in the most populous and powerful nations on the planet,3 and yet discussions of epistemic injustice have rarely mentioned it. I will start by briefly clarifying the notion of Islamophobia in Section 2 before going on to look at how it is implicated in various forms of epistemic injustice in Section 3. I will then begin to explore how we might understand deep epistemic injustice by looking at ways to understand deep disagreement (in particular, deep religious disagreement) in Section 4. This discussion of deep disagreement will suggest that the standard picture of testimonial injustice, where a speaker presents a piece of information or an item of knowledge and the hearer makes a credibility judgment concerning what is said, will not apply in any straightforward way to cases where the disagreement between speaker and hearer is deep. In Section 5, I will contrast testimonial injustice with deep epistemic injustice and provide some examples of deep epistemic injustice.

2. What Is Islamophobia?

Before moving on to look at how Islamophobia is implicated in epistemic injustices, let us first of all get a bit clearer about what Islamophobia is. To this end, it is helpful to compare it with antisemitism. Islamophobia no more refers to a fear of a religion than antisemitism refers to opposition to (‘anti’) Semites. The social philosopher Brian Klug draws upon Wittgenstein in order to drive this point home. It is not the etymology of a word that determines its meaning but its use.4 The meaning of ‘antisemitism’ is not fixed by its etymology. It is used to refer to “hostile attitudes and acts directed at Jews whether those acts and attitudes are based in biological racism or not” (Klug 2014, p. 449), and its meaning has changed since the nineteenth century when the term was introduced (when it was tied much more closely to biological racism).5 Similarly, ‘Islamophobia’ refers to hostile attitudes and acts directed towards a racialized minority, Muslims, as Muslims. Neither etymology nor provenance tells us the meaning of ‘antisemitism’ or ‘Islamophobia’. It is their use that we must attend to, and their use has changed over time. Klug notes that Wittgenstein famously said that there was no one thing in common between the various things we call ‘games’,6 and he suggests that something similar might be said about the meaning of ‘antisemitism’ or the meaning of ‘Islamophobia’ as they change over time. There are “similarities overlapping and criss-crossing” between the uses of ‘antisemitism’ and ‘Islamophobia’ as the negative qualities that are ascribed to Jewish people or to Muslims over time by racists change.

3. Testimonial Injustice, Hermeneutical Injustice, and Epistemic Violence

Having clarified the meaning of ‘Islamophobia’, we can now examine how Islamophobia might be implicated in various forms of epistemic injustice. Miranda Fricker’s book Epistemic Injustice has generated a huge discussion of injustices done to people in their capacities as knowers.7 The central cases of epistemic injustice that she identified in that book were ones involving identity prejudices that track people through different aspects of their lives, i.e., prejudices like racism, sexism, homophobia, transphobia, and discrimination on the basis of religion. In these cases, people are not just suffering injustices done to them in their capacities as knowers (given deflated credibility or denied the hermeneutical resources that would help make sense of their oppression), but they are also discriminated against in the job market, in the legal system, in education, and are subject to violence and abuse from people holding the relevant prejudices. The central case of testimonial injustice is what Fricker calls systematic testimonial injustice (Fricker 2007, p. 27). We can see that epistemic injustices that are committed against people on the basis of Islamophobia will be of this nature. For example, there is evidence that Muslims in the United Kingdom face discrimination in employment,8 in the legal system and the prison system,9 and that they face far greater levels of violence and abuse in the UK than other religious communities.10
In Epistemic Injustice, Fricker distinguishes two main forms of epistemic injustice: testimonial injustice and hermeneutical injustice. In introducing these concepts at the beginning of her book, she says that testimonial injustice “occurs when prejudice causes a hearer to give a deflated level of credibility to a speaker’s word” (Fricker 2007, p. 1) and, as we have seen above, she regards the central case of testimonial injustice to be systematic testimonial injustice involving identity prejudices. In making credibility judgments of other people, Fricker thinks that we must avail ourselves of social generalizations or stereotypes in gauging how likely it is that what a person has said is true. This becomes problematic when identity prejudice is at work in the stereotype; that is, when the stereotype is unreliable and is “made or maintained without proper regard to the evidence” (ibid., pp. 31–34). If Muslims are discriminated against in the job market, the legal system, and in politics, then we can say that Muslims are victims of identity prejudice, as Fricker describes it, and a Muslim (or a group of Muslims) who suffers deflated credibility due to this form of identity prejudice is the victim of systematic testimonial injustice.
An example of testimonial injustice involving Islamophobia is the way that the testimonies of Muslims were ignored when the French government banned face veiling.11 Many French Muslim women view the hijab in positive terms, as a way of asserting their identity as both French and Muslim, as something that makes them feel safe from objectifying gazes and probing from outsiders, as an empowering assertion of control over “body, mind, and soul”, and as a symbol of unity or solidarity in the face of state repression of Muslims (see Croucher 2008, p. 201 and also Statista Research Department 2024). However, this testimony has been disregarded by French lawmakers, who have instead tended to present veiling as a “mark of submission” or as being imposed by men (see Rosman 2020). This is an epistemic injustice because many French lawmakers have chosen to remain ignorant of Muslim women’s reasons for wearing veils. They have presented the position that many Muslim women adhere to as lacking in credibility, and so they have denied themselves and others knowledge of the reasons Muslim women give for wearing the veil.12 The irony of presenting their measures against Muslim women as being in aid of tackling sexism while they try to control what Muslim women wear and impose fines on them for disobeying seems to be lost on them.13
The other form of epistemic injustice that Fricker focuses upon is hermeneutical injustice, which she initially says occurs “when a gap in collective interpretive resources puts someone at an unfair disadvantage when it comes to making sense of their social experiences” (Fricker 2007, p. 1). Later in her book, she specifically ties hermeneutical injustice to “structural identity prejudice”, which, she notes, helps to convey the discriminatory nature of hermeneutical injustice, and so she gives a revised definition of the term, describing hermeneutical injustice as “the injustice of having some significant area of one’s social experience obscured from collective understanding owing to a structural identity prejudice in the collective hermeneutical resource”.14 Hermeneutical injustice, she notes, is closely tied up with matters of power and influence. Those who are influential in fields like journalism, politics, and law hold more sway when it comes to the hermeneutical resources available to a society. Looking again at the example of Islamophobia in France, we can see that there have been a series of attacks on the collective interpretive resources available to understand racism and Islamophobia in particular. In 2012, the French President, François Hollande, declared that “there is no place for race in the Republic” (Bessone 2020, p. 818). In 2013, the National Assembly voted to remove the word ‘race’ from French legislation. In 2017, the Minister of Education, Jean-Michel Blanquer, said that the word ‘racialized’ was “among the most appalling words of the political vocabulary” (Bessone 2020, p. 826). In 2018, the French magazine Le Point published a letter from eighty public figures occupying influential positions, calling for terms like ‘racialized groups’, ‘structural racism’, ‘white domination’, ‘racial power’, ‘black feminism’, and ‘decolonialism’ to be removed from academic discourse. In 2020, the French government shut down the Collectif contre l’Islamophobie en France (CCIF), which collected data on Islamophobic discrimination (Wolfreys 2023, p. 174), and in 2021, Macron pressured Imams to sign a Charter of Islamic Principles, under threat of repression if they did not sign, which included articles declaring that ‘state racism does not exist’ and that mosques cannot have any political agenda (ibid., p. 166). French government ministers and cultural figures claim an anti-racist motive for trying to eliminate discussion of race and racism; that the notion of ‘race’ is one that has been decisively discredited by science as referring to a biological category and so has no referent and any attempt to revive the term is encouraging racism. However, this argument relies on an understanding of race that is clearly a very impoverished one. It has long been understood that racism combines biology and culture to various degrees and that ‘race’ is socially constructed (ibid., p. 167; see also Rattansi 2020, pp. 80–86; Bessone 2020, pp. 817, 822–24). Moreover, the task of tackling racism is made more difficult if we are not able to use terms like ‘racialized’, ‘race’, and ‘racism’ to comprehend and challenge it. Eradicating organizations dedicated to gathering information on Islamophobia, refusing to gather data relevant to racial discrimination in the census, and trying to eradicate the language used to understand racism clearly has a deleterious effect on trying to understand racism in French society. This is a kind of epistemic injustice because it is an attack on the means that oppressed groups in French society have for understanding and interpreting racism—a hermeneutical injustice.15
Since the publication of Epistemic Injustice, a number of forms of epistemic injustice that were not discussed in that book have come into view. For example, in thinking about hermeneutical injustice we might note that it does not always take the form of oppressed people being denied the means to make sense of their experiences of oppression. Oppressed people are often in a particularly good position, relative to other people, to understand their own oppression. If we want to understand racism, we would do well not to ignore the understanding of those who have suffered it. If we want to understand sexism, we would do well to listen to what women have to say about it. Those who experience oppression thereby have a source of knowledge about that oppression and the ways in which it manifests itself that is denied to others, and they are also motivated to overcome that oppression. However, oppressed people who understand their own oppression might be treated unjustly by others dismissing, ignoring, or distorting their understanding of their oppression. Oppressors have a motivation to try to ensure that understanding of oppression do not become more widespread, and so they ignore the frameworks that oppressed people develop to understand their oppression and propose alternative frameworks that try to justify the oppressed positions of the oppressed. The powerful, at least sometimes, remain willfully ignorant of the ways in which oppressed people understand their lives, preferring the narratives of the powerful in their place. This is what Gayle Pohlhaus (2012) refers to as ‘wilful hermeneutical ignorance’. Gayatri Spivak (1998), Kristie Dotson (2011), and José Medina (2023), amongst others, have developed accounts of what they call ‘epistemic violence’ which is “the violence one suffers when one is harmed as a subject of knowledge and understanding, as it happens when people are silenced, systematically misrepresented, or rendered invisible or inaudible” (Medina 2023, p. 62).
An example that serves to illustrate both willful hermeneutical ignorance and epistemic violence is the way in which much of the Western media misrepresents jihad. There have been countless headlines in the UK press (and internationally) that have presented jihad as nothing but irrational violence driven by mistaken religious beliefs. For example, the UK newspaper The Times carried a headline on 22 August 2014 saying that ‘Hundreds more UK Muslims choose jihad than army’ (Haynes and Hamilton 2014), based on claims of a Member of Parliament that 1500 Muslims had gone to fight in Iraq and Syria and that there were only 600 Muslims in the UK Armed Forces. However, according to Ministry of Defence figures, there were 640 Muslims in the UK Armed Forces at that time,16 and according to the Foreign Office, 400 UK citizens had gone to fight in Iraq or Syria independently of the army (of which half had returned). Moreover, we have no good reason to think that all of those who went to fight in Iraq and Syria went to ‘wage jihad’ if what is meant by that is irrational violence driven by mistaken religious beliefs.
According to CAGE International, an organization set up to represent people who had been unjustly imprisoned during the ‘war on terror’, many of those who went to fight in Syria had quite reasonable political motivations. Their researchers interviewed a UK citizen fighting in Syria who said, “I don’t have any plan for waging jihad or any kind of fighting in the UK… we’ve just come for one purpose, to save the oppressed people of Syria from the evil of the terror of Bashar al-Asad” (Qureshi 2014, p. 8) and they say that this interviewee is representative of commonly held views among those fighting in Syria (ibid., p. 9).
If we look to The Qur’an, to collections of Hadith, and to legal works in the Islamic tradition for an understanding of jihad, we find that the term’s basic meaning is ‘struggle’, ‘striving’, or ‘exertion’ and that a different term, qital, is used to refer specifically to fighting (Afsaruddin 2020, p. 448). The Qur’an has quite strict rules regarding the initiation of hostilities and concerning conduct in war. Killing women and children, brigandage, highway robbery, sedition, and what we now call ‘terrorism’ are all deemed illegitimate violence in The Qur’an and Islamic juridical literature (Afsaruddin 2020, pp. 466–67). So, the concept of ‘jihad’ found in the Western press is very distant from that found in Islamic religious texts and juridical literature. The Western media largely ignores the frameworks used by Muslims themselves to understand jihad (they remain willfully ignorant), and so they do a hermeneutical injustice to Muslims. Moreover, according to Medina’s understanding of epistemic violence, the systematic misrepresentation of Muslims and of jihad amounts to epistemic violence.
What I want to focus on in the following sections is the possibility, raised by Kidd (2017), that there might be deep epistemic injustices committed against religious believers by people holding a different worldview.

4. What Is a Deep Disagreement?

In order to get to grips with deep epistemic injustice, we should first look at how we should understand deep disagreement. In a recent paper, Chris Ranalli and Thirza Lagewaard have identified two mainstream ‘theories’ of deep disagreement (Ranalli and Lagewaard 2022): the Wittgensteinian account and the Fundamental Epistemic Principle account. I will not discuss the fundamental epistemic principle account here because I take it that the hinge account can accommodate the kind of ‘fundamental epistemic principles’ that Lynch discusses, and moreover, as Ranalli and Lagewaard argue, the fundamental epistemic principles account has the disadvantage of being too narrow in scope (Lynch 2010; Ranalli and Lagewaard 2022, p. 12). My focus will be on Wittgensteinian understanding of deep disagreement.
The locus classicus for discussion of deep disagreement, and one that is influenced by Wittgenstein, is Robert Fogelin’s paper ‘The Logic of Deep Disagreements’ (Fogelin 1985), in which he notes that the kinds of arguments that we have in everyday life take place against a shared background of beliefs and preferences.
A disagreement is deep if a shared background is lacking in some way. What Fogelin has in mind in the case of deep disagreement is a disagreement in deep commitments, which Wittgenstein sometimes described as analogous to hinges. It should be noted here that although Fogelin cites passages §§341–344 of Wittgenstein’s On Certainty, where Wittgenstein talks about hinges, he does not generally talk about these deep commitments as being hinges in the manner of modern-day hinge-epistemologists. Fogelin prefers to talk of a disagreement in ‘framework propositions’ or ‘rules’.
What are these ‘hinges’ or ‘framework propositions’? In §341 of On Certainty, Wittgenstein famously says that “the questions we raise and our doubts depend on the fact that some propositions are exempt from doubt, are as it were like hinges on which those turn”. The ‘hinges’, he says, “must stay put” (§343). In other places in On Certainty, Wittgenstein uses other metaphors for these propositions that are exempt from doubt. He describes them as “fixed…removed from the traffic…shunted onto an unused siding” (§210) or as “foundation walls” (in contrast with the “whole house”) (§248), or as a “riverbed” (in contrast with “the movement of the waters” of the river) (§96–99). Interestingly, in the case of the riverbed metaphor, Wittgenstein speaks of the riverbed shifting and of there not being a sharp division between the bed and the waters that flow over it. So, in each case, there is something ‘hard’ or ‘fixed’, which “stands fast” (§116) or which “stand unshakeably fast” (§144) on the one hand, and there is the moving, fluid, shifting (door/traffic/water/parts of the riverbed) element on the other.
For a clearer understanding of what ‘hinges’ are, we should look at some examples of propositions that Wittgenstein uses and say something about why they might be considered ‘fixed’ or ‘hard’. Examples of hinges include, “Here is one hand (accompanied by a gesture of presenting one’s hand)” (§1), “I have two hands” (§§23, 125), “I am writing in English” (§§70, 158), “I am a man” (§79), “This → o color is called blue” (§§126, 522), “I have just had lunch” (§659), “The earth exists” (§§208–10), and interestingly, for our purposes here, he also includes cases of ‘religious hinges’ where different people hold to quite different hinges, such as “belief in a God, or that none exists” (§107) or the belief that “every human being has two human parents” in contrast with the Catholic belief that “Jesus only had a human mother” (§239–40), and Wittgenstein talks about missionaries converting ‘natives’ to their worldview (made up of various religious hinges and other hinges).
One feature that these (hinge) propositions have in common is that it is, at the very least, peculiar for someone to ask how one knows them. If you told someone that you have two hands and they asked you, ‘How do you know?’, you would likely be baffled as to why they were asking such a strange question. It is also worth noting that it would be strange to offer up many of these propositions in the first place, although we can imagine situations in which we might. Propositions like ‘here is a hand’ and ‘the earth exists’ are very rarely articulated except in philosophical discussions. Some of them (“This → o color is called blue”, “I have two hands”) might be used in training young children in basic color concepts, in counting, or in naming parts of their body. We can get a better sense of why it is odd to articulate them and why it is odd to ask how we know them by thinking about how we might try to investigate them, produce evidence for them, or justify them.
In remark §125 of On Certainty, Wittgenstein says that “If a blind man were to ask me ‘Have you got two hands?’ I should not make sure by looking. If I were to have any doubt of it, then I don’t know why I should trust my eyes. For why shouldn’t I test my eyes by looking to find out whether I have two hands? What is to be tested by what?” His point is that one cannot provide justification for the claim ‘I have two hands’ with the claim that ‘I can see that I have two hands’ because the second claim is no more certain than the claim it is supposed to support and so it does not provide support. The claim that ‘I have two hands’, we might say, is absolutely certain. There is nothing that we could be more certain of that would provide justification for it. We do not, of course, in ordinary circumstances look to check whether we have two hands. That would strike us as ridiculous. However, we can imagine circumstances in which we might look to check (upon waking up injured in hospital from a massive car crash, for example). The ‘claim’ that ‘I have two hands’ is not something that we arrive at through investigation or through discovering evidence. It is not something that we can justify, nor is it unjustified, and the same can be said of the other examples listed above. There is no investigation that I could perform to discover that I am writing in English when I am writing in English, and I could not be said to have evidence that that is what I am doing. The same can be said for ‘God exists’. People who believe in God do not arrive at belief in God through conducting an empirical investigation. They are generally raised in households where religious language is imparted to them as they engage in religious practices, like praying and religious worship, and come to believe in God in that way.
In Wittgenstein’s picture, the ‘foundational’ propositions, the hinges, are neither justified nor unjustified, and they are not arrived at through investigation, so they cannot be said to be items of knowledge. The hinges are not supported by evidence, and neither are they self-evident (they are not “intrinsically obvious or convincing” (§144)); they are ‘swallowed down’ (§143) with our training in concepts and with the acquisition of beliefs.17 The beliefs that I hold fast to form a ‘nest’ (§225); they are not held in isolation from one another, and the beliefs that stand fast are held fast by what lies around them (a vast system of beliefs) (§144). When it comes to ordinary empirical matters, we might be said to know things and might also have doubts about things, but in the case of hinges, doubt is excluded (logically) (§88). It must be that certain propositions are not doubted if the game of doubting (and justifying, enquiring, and knowing) is to get off the ground. When Wittgenstein characterizes the distinction between hinges and other kinds of belief in less metaphorical terms, he sometimes characterizes it in terms of something that might be tested by experience (ordinary empirical beliefs) and rules of testing (hinges) (§§98, 309, 319) or in terms of empirical beliefs and norms of description (§§167, 321). This rule or norm-like nature can perhaps be seen most clearly in something like the proposition ‘This → o color is called blue’ which might be used to instruct someone in how to use the term ‘blue’, whereas an empirical proposition involves using the term ‘blue’ to attribute the color to some object (e.g., ‘the cover of my notebook is blue’).
One final thing to note about hinges is that they are diverse. Trying to doubt some of them would be incoherent because it would bring everything into doubt (and therefore, the game of doubting could not get off the ground at all). So, doubting whether ‘this → is my hand’ would be to “stand before the abyss” (§370), according to Wittgenstein. Doubting that “this person here [sat opposite me] is [my old friend] N. N.” would “drag everything with it and plunge it into chaos”18 but doubting whether “the water in the kettle on the gas flame will not freeze but boil” would not (§613). Particularly relevant to our considerations here is that it seems that coming to doubt one’s religious beliefs would not “drag everything with it”, although it may well be a highly disconcerting experience, shaking up many elements of one’s worldview.19
Does the foregoing discussion of deep disagreements and hinges mean that we should understand deep disagreements over religious issues in terms of hinges? I think the fact that ‘deep disagreement’ is a term of art20 and that it was introduced by Robert Fogelin in an influential paper only forty years ago in roughly these terms means that we should take seriously the possibility that at least some deep religious disagreements will take this form. Moreover, as I will argue a bit later, I think Duncan Pritchard provides good reasons for thinking that religion is a particularly promising area to find deep disagreements over hinges.
However, I think it is doubtful that all deep religious disagreements are disagreements over hinges, and we also have good reason to doubt that all disagreements over hinges are deep disagreements. Victoria Lavorerio has pointed out that paradigmatic examples of deep disagreements, such as disagreement over intelligent design, are not (or at least not always) disagreements over hinges. She argues that the parties in the disagreement over intelligent design, the evolutionists and the proponents of intelligent design, might have different hinge commitments (proponents of intelligent design are Christians, and so believe that ‘God exists’, for example) but that those hinge commitments need not enter into the debate (the debate is an empirical one over whether certain organisms are ‘irreducibly complex’ (Behe 1996, p. 39) and the claim that some are has no scientific merit) but the disagreement might nonetheless be considered deep if, with Lavorerio, we define deep disagreements as “persistent conflicts of opinions about matters that can be said to be worldview defining” (Lavorerio 2021b, p. 416).
It seems, then, that at least according to one definition of ‘deep disagreement’, there are cases of deep disagreement that are not cases of disagreement in hinges or disagreement in fundamental epistemic principles. However, that does not mean that there are not at least some deep disagreements that are disagreements over hinges, and Lavorerio accepts this. Pritchard agrees with Lavoreiro that not all deep disagreements are disagreements over hinges, and he also argues that not all disagreements over hinges are deep disagreements, though at least some are.21
We can see that not all deep disagreements are disagreements over hinges if we think about ‘quotidian hinges’ such as ‘I have two hands’ and ‘My name is R. V.’. It is difficult, if not impossible, to imagine a genuine dispute arising over these hinges. Pritchard argues that the Wittgensteinian position is that we could make no sense of someone who doubts these commonsense hinge commitments—that we would treat someone as lacking sanity if they doubted them. Pritchard also argues that purely philosophical disputes are not good candidates for being deep disagreements because even though philosophers do present arguments in opposition to claims like ‘there are physical objects’ and ‘the future resembles the past’ their actions “reveal that the underlying certainty in these [the relevant] hinges is unaffected” (Pritchard 2023, p. 311).22 Here, I will agree with Pritchard that disagreements that concern issues of existential importance are the most plausible candidates for cases of deep disagreement, and these disagreements, at least sometimes, are disagreements over hinges.23 In addition to being a good account of deep disagreement I also understand Pritchard’s position to be very much in tune with the way that Wittgenstein treated philosophical problems and religious problems. Though Wittgenstein spoke of philosophical problems as having “the character of depth” (Wittgenstein 2009, §111), he very often criticized past philosophical positions as being nonsensical (Wittgenstein 2009, §§119, 246, 252, PPF§328) and in the Investigations said that he wanted to teach people “to pass from unobvious nonsense to obvious nonsense” (§464) in philosophy. However, in the case of disagreements between people with different worldviews (perhaps with differing religious hinges), he did not accuse religious believers of speaking nonsense (though, of course, language can “go on holiday” (§38) in the case of religious believers just as it can for anyone else). There might be difficulties in understanding when people with different worldviews meet, but this does not mean that either party is speaking nonsense. Here, there really is potential for people to sincerely disagree over issues of existential importance.
Religion, unlike philosophy, then, seems to be a field particularly suited to deep disagreements. It is a field in which people genuinely disagree in some sense but also a field in which people might not share a common background. As was already noted above, in giving examples of hinge propositions, Wittgenstein sometimes gives examples where people with different hinges come into conflict, and several of those examples are religious ones. There is the disagreement between the person who believes in God and the one who does not (§107), there is the disagreement between the person who believes that every human being has two human parents and the person who believes that Jesus only had a human mother (§239), there is the disagreement between Moore, who says that “I know that this is wine and not blood” and the Catholic who contradicts him (§239), and there is the disagreement between (Christian) missionaries and the people they set out to convert (§612).24
I say that the people disagree in some sense because disagreements over religion are not like cases where someone asserts an empirical proposition and another person asserts the opposite, contradicting them (e.g., someone says ‘there is water on Mars’ and another person says ‘there is no water on Mars’). In his ‘Lectures on Religious Belief’, Wittgenstein gives the example of a believer who says, “I believe in a Last Judgement”, and they are met with the response: “Well, I am not so sure. Possibly”. In this case, Wittgenstein says, “[y]ou would say that there is an enormous gulf between us”. On the other hand, if someone said, “There is a German airplane overhead”, and another responded, “Possibly, I’m not so sure”, then you would not say that there is an enormous gulf between the two disputants (Wittgenstein 1966, p. 53). In the German airplane disagreement, the two people have a shared background of empirical beliefs about planes and about Germany and agree about the means for settling the dispute. One might offer the other binoculars and say, “Look—you can see that it says Deutsche Aircraft on the side of it, and that is a German make of plane”, and that may well settle the argument. However, in the case of the disagreement over a Last Judgement, the dispute cannot be settled in a similar manner. The two parties to the dispute cannot do something like pull out binoculars or cite some piece of evidence. For the believer in the Last Judgement it is not a matter of evidence or of possibility. Wittgenstein calls the belief in a Last Judgement an ’unshakeable belief’ (54) and says that “it will show…by regulating for all in his life”—the disagreement is a disagreement in form of life25 or way of life, we might say. The fact that Wittgenstein describes the belief in the Last Judgement as ‘unshakeable’ suggests that he is thinking of it as being like the fixed beliefs, beyond all doubt, that he describes as being like hinges or a riverbed in On Certainty. So, the conflict between the two disputants is a conflict between one who has a religious hinge (or something hinge-like) and one who is thinking about a Last Judgement as being something possible, as an empirical belief might be. The believer’s belief in the Last Judgement is part of a worldview (it is one element in a nest of hinges and religious beliefs) that their interlocutor does not share, and that worldview is associated with a form of life that the interlocutor does not participate in. So, although the non-believer understands the component words in what is said to him (‘God’, ‘Last Judgement’ etc.), they do not, as Genia Schönbaumsfeld says, “understand how a life with such a concept is possible, or how one would go about acquiring the qualities of heart that would make it so” (Schönbaumsfeld 2023, p. 35).26
Before moving on to look at the possibility of deep epistemic injustice, let us first look at one more example of deep disagreement involving religious hinges. If we think about what the fundamental beliefs of Islam are, we may well conclude that the oneness of Allah (or God) is absolutely central.27 In sura (chapter) 112 of The Qur’an, it says, “Say, ‘He is God the One, God the eternal. He begot no one nor was He begotten. No one is comparable to Him’” and the Prophet Muhammed, commenting on this sura said that, although it was short it was equal to one-third of The Qur’an owing to its importance (The Qur’an 2015, p. 444 (sura 112, 1–4)). The centrality of this belief in Islam and the importance given to it already suggest that it might have a hinge-like nature for many Muslims. Muslims do not think that the oneness of God is a merely contingent feature of God, they take it to be of God’s essence that ‘God is the One and begot no one’ and as Wittgenstein said, “Essence is expressed in grammar” (Wittgenstein 2009, §371). It seems that Wittgenstein, when he was working on Philosophical Investigations, thought that the central religious beliefs of religions like Christianity and Islam are quite unlike ordinary empirical beliefs. Instead, he thought of them as being grammatical (Wittgenstein 2009, §373) and, therefore, rule-like, in the manner of hinges. Now, this central belief of Islam places Muslims in disagreement not only with non-believers but also with polytheists, as well as Trinitarian Christians. In this latter case, it seems plausible that what we are talking about is a disagreement in hinges. Whereas for Muslims, it is a hinge that “Allah is God the One” and that “He begot no one”, for many Christians, it is a hinge that “God is three persons: the Father (begets), the Son (is begotten), and the Holy Ghost (proceeds)” and that “Jesus is the son of God” (see, for example, Luke, 4:41). Where Muslims and Christians sincerely disagree over these deeply held beliefs we may well have a case of deep disagreement.

5. Deep Epistemic Justice

Let us now consider whether there might be cases where deep disagreement exists, and one of the disputants is done an injustice in the course of the dispute—a deep epistemic injustice. The first thing that we might reflect on is that these cases are going to look very different from typical cases of testimonial injustice, where somebody tries to convey a piece of information or knowledge, and another person tries to weigh up how likely it is that what has been said is true. In cases of deep disagreement over religious belief, where the belief in question is a hinge or hinge-like, we should notice that:
  • A religious hinge is not a piece of information or knowledge (as a hinge, it is neither justified nor unjustified, it does not rest on evidence, it is beyond doubt for the person committed to it).
  • There are no shared criteria by which a person might evaluate what the other person has said as true or false. The normal means of determining whether something is true—by gathering evidence, having a look—are not available to us in this case (we can gather evidence or have a closer look to determine whether a plane is a German one flying overhead, but we cannot gather evidence or have a closer look when what is under dispute is whether there will be a Last Judgement).
So, these cases do not fit Fricker’s model for testimonial injustice. However, we surely want to say that people might be treated unjustly in the uptake of what they say about their fundamental religious beliefs, given that these beliefs are deeply tied up with a person’s identity.
Thinking about the kind of cases discussed above, of newspapers printing misleading headlines about Muslims and governments failing to listen to the testimony of Muslims, I think we should first of all note that cases of Islamophobia are not necessarily deep disagreements. Muslims might disagree with non-Muslims in some of their hinges, but they are bound to agree in many others, and the religious hinges of Muslims are likely to have considerable overlap with those of other people who believe in an Abrahamic religion (most will agree, for instance, that ‘God exists’ and that this is a vital component of their religious outlook).
In thinking about possible examples of deep epistemic injustice in the area of religion, one way in which we might think about it is in terms of prejudices (such as Islamophobia or antisemitism) being hinges, or at least hinge-like.28 In that case, a disagreement between an Islamophobe, who presupposes that ‘Islam is evil’ and a non-prejudiced person who says that ‘Islam is not evil’ might be characterized as a deep one (because it involves a disagreement in something hinge-like) and the Muslim who is not believed when characterizing their religion as a religion of peace and love due to this prejudice might be characterized as suffering a deep epistemic injustice. I use the term ‘epistemic’ here because, although I think that prejudices are hinge-like in the ways that Anna Boncompagni has recently suggested (they are resistant to counterevidence (Boncompagni 2024, p. 289), often implicit (Boncompagni 2024, p. 290), swallowed down in childhood (Boncompagni 2024, p. 295)), I do not think that they can be described as neither justified nor unjustified (as Wittgenstein describes hinges). Prejudices are unwarranted or unjustified prejudgements (See (Allport 1979, p. 8) and (Fricker 2007, p. 34)). I follow Fogelin in thinking that an accusation of prejudice, like an accusation of pig-headedness or an accusation of bias, “only makes sense in a normal (or near normal) argumentative context (Fogelin 1985, p. 7). Perhaps some disagreements between Islamophobes and Muslims could be characterized as deep since prejudices are sometimes deep-seated and hinge-like (and we have already seen that not all deep disagreements are disagreements over hinges).
A rich source of disagreements involving religion that might be characterized as deep epistemic injustices is Elizabeth Anscombe’s paper ‘Paganism, Superstition and Philosophy’ (Anscombe 2008a). There, she discusses the way in which the (pagan) Tacitus describes Jewish people in extremely unflattering terms as “hateful to the gods”, “contrary to the rest of mankind”, as allowing ‘incest’, with ‘sinister’ customs “validated by their filthiness” (2008a, pp. 49–50). Here, you have a case of people with very different worldviews (pagan and Jewish) coming into conflict where what one regards as sacred, the other regards as profane. Tacitus is undoubtedly unjust to the Jewish people. He presents a distorted and inaccurate picture of the followers of Moses, but some of the disagreement is simply a disagreement in form of life. Anscombe also discusses the way in which followers of one religion have viewed themselves as superior to the followers of other religions by not accepting that the religion in question is a religion at all: “Christians at a much later date [than Tacitus] called Islam superstition and paganism superstition and rabbinical (i.e., post-Christian) Judaism superstition. Protestants called Catholic Christianity superstition, and also Russian Orthodoxy…” (Anscombe 2008a, p. 57). In fact, Anscombe herself might be accused of doing the same thing, since she characterizes Christianity as “the true religion” (2008a, p. 58) and portrays Hinduism as a kind of paganism (Anscombe 2008a, p. 55). In another paper, she makes clear her disapproval of Hinduism on the basis that it violates the Christian prohibition on idolatry. The prohibition on idolatry, she says, “is becoming rather more relevant now: with present fashions, some of our young people are being drawn into spiritual cults which include the worship of Shiva and Krishna and other deities of the Hindu pantheon…but in any case it is clear that these are (false) gods” (Anscombe 2008b, p. 231).29
A further potential site for deep epistemic injustice is in disagreements between naturalistic worldviews and religious ones (Kidd 2017, p. 393). A particularly crude form of scientistic naturalism can be found in the work of Richard Dawkins, who claims that ‘God exists’ is a scientific hypothesis about the universe (Dawkins 2016, p. 24) and that the question of whether Jesus had a human father is a “strictly scientific question” (Dawkins 2016, p. 83). However, as Wittgenstein has shown, it is plausible that ‘God exists’ and ‘Jesus only had a human mother’ might take on a hinge-like (or grammatical) role in the lives of Christian believers, whose practices are very unlike those of scientists. Moreover, Dawkins is clearly not alone in subscribing to such scientistic views. His work has been hugely influential (The God Delusion has sold millions of copies, and Dawkins has a TV series, ‘The Root of All Evil?’ based on it). This kind of scientism, portraying religion as a crude form of empirical belief in competition with science, has a long history. Wittgenstein criticized James George Frazer for presenting ritual behaviors as “pieces of stupidity” (Wittgenstein 1993, p. 119), and Frazer’s The Golden Bough was first published in 1890. This kind of scientism, which is often accompanied by describing religious beliefs in highly unflattering terms, clearly has the potential to undergird discrimination on the basis of religion. Indeed, in Dawkins’ case, it has been combined with a particular animosity toward Islam and Muslims.30

6. Conclusions

In this paper, my aim was to give an account of what deep epistemic injustice might look like. In order to do that, I first looked at standard kinds of cases of epistemic injustice so that we might contrast the ‘deep’ case with more ordinary cases. I then proceeded to present a Wittgensteinian account of deep disagreement and argued that deep disagreements between believers and non-believers (or between adherents of different religions) might take the form of disagreements over hinges but that this was not inevitably the case. Lavorerio (2021b) and Pritchard (2021, 2023, 2024) have made a convincing case that deep disagreements might involve a clash of worldviews and yet not involve a dispute over hinges (and that clashes over hinges need not count as deep disagreements). Then, in Section 5, I explained how cases of deep epistemic injustice differ from ordinary cases. Where a dispute is over a hinge or something hinge-like, we might question whether the person offering testimony is saying something true or offering up a piece of knowledge, and the depth of the disagreement will produce corresponding difficulties in assessing the truth of what the person offering testimony says, as well as difficulties in assessing the credibility of the person offering testimony. I suggested that a disagreement between an Islamophobe and a Muslim might involve a deep epistemic injustice because prejudices are hinge-like and also suggested that Anscombe’s work provides us with many examples that are plausible examples of deep injustices. Furthermore, disagreements between scientistic and naturalistic worldviews provide a further potential site of injustice.
Throughout the paper, I used examples of Islamophobia since it has received little attention in the literature on epistemic injustice and because discrimination on the basis of religion (as well as racist discrimination) seems like a plausible area in which we might find deep epistemic injustices of the sort Kidd has described.

Funding

Fundação para a Ciência e a Tecnologia (2022.01699.CEECIND/CP1725/CT0037).

Data Availability Statement

No new data were created or analyzed in this study. Data sharing is not applicable to this article.

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the Fundação para a Ciência e a Tecnologia for their support while I was writing this paper. They are funding my current project, ‘Power, Prejudice, and Perception’ (2022.01699.CEECIND/CP1725/CT0037). I would also like to thank André Kfouri for pointing me in the direction of Anscombe as a possible source of examples of deep epistemic injustice and Nuno Venturinha for his suggestions regarding examples of Wittgenstein’s opposition to prejudice. Both attended a presentation of an earlier version of this paper at Universidade Nova in Lisbon. I would also like to thank Sebastian Sunday Grève for his incredibly conscientious editorial work. He has given me a number of very helpful comments that have much improved the structure and argumentation of the paper.

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

Notes

1
(Kidd 2017, p. 386). However we should note that feminist and liberation movements in theology both before Fricker’s book and since have discussed epistemic injustice without using that term (Kidd 2017, p. 387).
2
Kidd cites Morny Joy’s work (Joy 2010) in connection with this.
3
See, for example, Vol. 4, Issue 2 of Islamophobia Studies Journal (2018), which contains several papers on Islamophobia in India, Nussbaum (2012), Vinten (2023), Hodson (2020) on Islamophobia in the United States, Wolfreys (2023) on Islamophobia in France.
4
5
Biological racism divides human beings into ‘races’ according to biological features such as skin colour, blood, shape of nose or lips, and brain size. It is now widely viewed as being discredited (see (Rattansi 2020) on the distinction between biological racism and cultural racism).
6
ibid., §66. Discussed on page 451 of (Klug 2014). See also Gakis (2025) for a good recent paper on political concepts and family resemblances.
7
Rachel McKinnon notes that prior to Fricker’s work “there’s a long history in black feminist thought, and other feminists of color, that should be seen as also working on issues of epistemic injustice” (McKinnon 2016, pp. 438–39). She cites work by Davis (1981), Moraga and Anzaldúa (1981), Carby (1982), Hull et al. (1982), Lorde (1984), Hooks (1992), Ladner (1995), Alcoff (1996), Ikuenobe (1998), Alcoff (2000) and Collins (2000). Gaile Pohlhaus Jr. looks back further, to work by Anna Julia Cooper in 1892, highlighting the way in which black women’s ideas have been suppressed through epistemic violence, and Sojourner Truth’s speech from 1867 in which she “highlighted the denial of black women as knowers” (Pohlhaus 2017, pp. 13–15).
8
They are about double as likely to be unemployed as Christians and Jewish people in the UK (see Mohdin and García 2023) and they face discrimination in trying to find work (see Adesina and Marocico 2017).
9
The Muslim prison population has more than doubled since 2002 and they are the only religious group in the UK where there is a large discrepancy between the percentage in prison (18%) and the percentage of Muslims in the general population (7% in England and Wales) (see Sturge 2024, p. 16). For a discussion of the prison experiences of Muslims see (Slawson 2017).
10
According to a survey in 2022 42% of mosques and Islamic institutions had experienced an attack in the past three years, with 35% of mosques experiencing at least one attack per year (Asad and Uddin 2022). Moreover these are attacks on a racialized minority. People who are attacked in Islamophobic attacks are very often not Muslim at all (see, for example, Lewin 2001; Roberts 2015; Mann 2016) but are attacked due to their appearance.
11
Jeffrey Epstein, describes the French ban on face veiling as a case of testimonial injustice (Epstein 2014, p. 433). He also argues that Muslims suffered hermeneutical injustice at this point.
12
Given that the testimonial injustice is committed against a group and that Muslim women have resisted the injustice collectively this also counts as an example of what José Medina calls ‘group testimonial injustice’ (Medina 2023, pp. 222–28).
13
Jennifer Lackey has recently made a powerful case that testimonial injustices need not involve a hearer giving deflated credibility to a speaker’s testimony. Sometimes people are victims of testimonial injustice when they are given an unwarranted excess of credibility (Lackey 2023, pp. 57–58; see also Fricker 2023a, 2023b). It is easy to see how we could give examples of such cases where Islamophobia is in play (e.g., in cases where prisoners at Guantanamo Bay have given confessions after being tortured or subjected to lengthy interrogations).
14
ibid., p. 155. The collective hermeneutical resource includes the concepts that we have available to us in our society, the ways of framing things that we have available to us, and more generally the tools we have for understanding things.
15
Moreover it is a form of group hermeneutical injustice as discussed by Medina (2023, pp. 229–34).
16
17
I take this understanding of the acquisition of hinges like ‘I have two hands’ to be in tension with Annalisa Coliva’s account where they come to be excluded from empirical investigation and play a hinge role because they have “been verified endless times” (Coliva 2025, p. 10). We do not verify that we have hands at all in ordinary circumstances. We are trained to count, we come by the name of body parts as our parents physically engage with us, console us, read us stories, and so on—we are trained in the grammar of our language and hinges like ‘I have two hands’ are swallowed down with this. So, they are not different to religious hinges in the way that Coliva suggests.
18
Elsewhere Wittgenstein talks about a formerly certain belief being shown to be false resulting in the “ground on which I stand” being knocked “from under my feet…the annihilation of all yardsticks” (§492) and of being thrown “entirely off the rails” (517)
19
Here, I am largely in agreement with Annalisa Coliva who, in this issue of Religions, says that “in the non-religious case, if it turned out that we cannot hold on to our hinges, this would…drag with them all our epistemic methods by means of which we form epistemically rational beliefs. By contrast, in the religious case, we would certainly receive an existential blow, but nothing detrimental to our rational faculties” (Coliva 2025, p. 4). However, I do not draw the conclusions that she does about this undermining Pritchard’s parity argument. I agree with Pritchard that empirical belief, no less than religious belief, stands against a background of arational hinges (for a defense of quasi-fideism see Pritchard 2011, 2015, 2017, 2018, 2022; Vinten 2022). Coliva uses ‘There are physical objects’ as an example of a hinge that would ‘drag everything with it’ but I don’t take ‘There are physical objects’ to be an example of a hinge at all. I interpret Wittgenstein as saying that this is nonsense (Wittgenstein 1969, §§35–37; 1960, §§48–49) that at a stretch it might be interpreted as a sensical grammatical proposition saying ‘it is legitimate to speak of physical objects’ but then idealists, like Berkeley, could happily accept it (it is the notion of ‘matter’ that Berkeley takes to be ‘contradictory’ (Berkeley 1998, Part I, 9, p. 106)). However, Coliva and Doulas take it to be equivalent to ‘there is an external world’ and present it as if it is in tension with idealism and phenomenalism (Coliva and Doulas 2024, pp. 46–47).
20
As Duncan Pritchard says “the notion of deep disagreement is a term of art, and hence it is to a certain extent up to us how we wish to employ it” (Pritchard 2023, p. 301); see also (Pritchard 2024, p. 51).
21
Lagewaard also argues that not all cases of deep disagreement are disagreements over fundamental principles and claims that “the depth of disagreements is best understood as a matter of degree” (Lagewaard 2021, p. 178).
22
Pritchard argues that ‘There are physical objects’ and ‘There is an external world’ are nonsense ((Pritchard 2023, p. 311) and in part 2 of his Epistemic Angst (Pritchard 2016)).
23
This places my view (and of course Pritchard’s view) in tension with the view of Annalisa Coliva and Michele Palmira. Coliva has argued that there are substantial debates to be had in philosophy (in Coliva and Doulas 2024, p. 46) but that the rationality of religious hinges cannot be defended (Coliva 2025, p. 10).
24
A reviewer has pointed out that most of Wittgenstein’s examples concern ‘disagreement’ between a religious believer and non-believer and suggests that Wittgenstein’s views on religion are therefore irrelevant to interfaith disagreement. In my view Wittgenstein’s hinge epistemology is fairly straightforwardly applicable to cases of interfaith disagreement in that different religions might be seen as constituting significant elements in people’s worldviews involving at least some different fundamental commitments (i.e., hinges). The grammar of each religion is going to differ in at least some respects. There is a rich recent literature on interreligious relations and intercultural understanding from Wittgensteinians (see, e.g., Andrejč and Weiss 2019; Carmona et al. 2023; Carroll 2025).
25
Sebastian Sunday Grève has recently given an account of deep disagreement in terms of forms of life (Sunday Grève 2025) and Victoria Lavorerio has characterized deep disagreements in terms of another Wittgensteinian notion—pictures (Lavorerio 2021a). I do not see the characterization of deep disagreements in terms of hinges as being in tension with either of these views. The belief in a Last Judgement, which Wittgenstein characterizes in the kind of terms he would later characterize hinges is interwoven with other elements in a worldview and an accompanying form of life.
26
Alois Pichler and Sebastian Sunday Grève have recently argued that “Wittgenstein’s mature philosophy… clearly favours cognitivism over non-cognitivism” (Pichler and Sunday Grève 2025, p. 61) and a cognitivist interpretation of Wittgenstein would clearly be in conflict with the view I present here. They argue that the non-revisionism of the Philosophical Investigations (that it ‘leaves everything as it is’ (Wittgenstein 2009, §124) means that Wittgenstein should have acknowledged that theologians and ordinary members of Christian communities very often talk in cognitive terms—in terms of ‘truth’ and ‘argument’—when talking about their religious beliefs. However, they also note that Wittgenstein himself never actually drew these cognitivist conclusions himself unequivocally but they say that he “should eventually have criticized his earlier self for having neglected the truth game in his account of religious belief statements” (Pichler and Sunday Grève 2025, p. 66).
I am inclined to agree with them that we should “look and see” (Wittgenstein 2009, §66) what theologians and Christians say and the use that they make of their religious language and think that they are correct that religious language is likely to play a great variety of different roles in different circumstances (despite my focus on ‘hinges’ here I certainly don’t think that every religious utterance is a hinge).
(Note: Pichler also has a piece in this issue where he looks in greater depth at the case for partial cognitivism in the work of Wittgenstein (Pichler 2025)).
27
I would like to thank Fahad Zafar Janjua for his helpful conversations about Islam and for the advice he has given me about readings concerning Islam. I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for pressing me to develop an example of deep disagreement involving a ‘hinge’ from Islam.
28
Anna Boncompagni has recently offered an interpretation of prejudices along these lines (Boncompagni 2019, 2024).
29
It is clear that although Anscombe was influenced by Wittgenstein she was not particularly sympathetic to his views on religion and she had quite a different understanding of religion to Wittgenstein himself (see Richter 2025, in this issue for more on this). In his ‘Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough’ Wittgenstein criticizes Frazer for making magical and religious views “look like errors” and asks “Was Augustine in error, then, when he called upon God on every page of the Confessions? But—one might say—if he was not in error, surely the Buddhist holy man was—or anyone else—whose religion gives expression to completely different views. But none of them was in error, except when he set forth a theory” (Wittgenstein 1993, p. 119) and in conversation with O. K. Bouwsma Wittgenstein said “there is no sense talking about religious truth in general” (Bouwsma 1986, p. 54). These comments clearly conflict with Anscombe’s adherence to (Catholic) Christianity as the “one true religion”.
30
He has claimed that “Islam is the greatest force for evil in the world today” (on X https://x.com/RichardDawkins/status/307366714105032704 (accessed on 2 March 2025) and has compared Islam to cancer (Fearnow 2019).

References

  1. Adesina, Zack, and Oana Marocico. 2017. Is It Easier to Get a Job If You’re Adam or Mohamed? BBC, February 6. Available online: https://www.bbc.com/news/uk-england-london-38751307 (accessed on 26 November 2024).
  2. Afsaruddin, Asma. 2020. Jihad in Islamic Thought. In The Cambridge History of World Violence: Vol. 2. Edited by Matthew S. Gordon, Richard W. Kaeuper and Harriet Zurndorfer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 448–69. [Google Scholar]
  3. Alcoff, Linda Martín. 1996. The problem of speaking for others. In Who Can Speak? Authority and Critical Identity. Edited by Judith Roof and Robyn Wiegman. Champaign: University of Illinois Press. [Google Scholar]
  4. Alcoff, Linda Martín. 2000. On judging epistemic credibility: Is social identity relevant? In Women of Color and Philosophy. Edited by Naomi Zack. Malden: Blackwell Publishers. [Google Scholar]
  5. Allport, Gordon. 1979. The Nature of Prejudice: 25th Anniversary Edition. New York: Basic Books. [Google Scholar]
  6. Anderson, Pamela Sue. 2017. Revisioning Gender in Philosophy of Religion: Reason, Love and Epistemic Locatedness. London: Routledge. First published 2012. [Google Scholar]
  7. Andrejč, Gorazd, and Daniel Weiss. 2019. Interpreting Interreligious Relations with Wittgenstein: Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
  8. Anscombe, Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret. 2008a. Paganism, Superstition and Philosophy. In Faith in Hard Ground: Essays on Religion, Philosophy and Ethics by G. E. M. Anscombe. Edited by Mary Geach and Luke Gormally. Exeter: Imprint Academic, pp. 49–60. [Google Scholar]
  9. Anscombe, Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret. 2008b. The Moral Environment of the Child. In Faith in Hard Ground: Essays on Religion, Philosophy and Ethics by G. E. M. Anscombe. Edited by Mary Geach and Luke Gormally. Exeter: Imprint Academic, pp. 224–33. [Google Scholar]
  10. Asad, Zaynah, and Nazim Uddin. 2022. Attacks Upon Mosques and Islamic Institutions in the U. K. Muslim Census and MEND. Available online: https://muslimcensus.co.uk/wp-content/uploads/MuslimCensus-x-MEND.pdf (accessed on 2 March 2025).
  11. Behe, Michael. 1996. Darwin’s Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution. New York: Free Press. [Google Scholar]
  12. Berkeley, George. 1998. A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge. Edited by Jonathan Dancy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  13. Bessone, Magali. 2020. Racism and Epistemologies of Ignorance: Framing the French Case. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 23: 815–19. [Google Scholar]
  14. Boncompagni, Anna. 2019. Hinges, Prejudices, and Radical Doubters. Wittgenstein-Studien 10: 165–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  15. Boncompagni, Anna. 2024. Prejudice in Testimonial Justification: A Hinge Account. Episteme 21: 286–303. [Google Scholar]
  16. Bouwsma, Oets Kolk. 1986. Wittgenstein: Conversations 1949–1951. Edited by Jimmy Lee Craft and Ronald E. Hustwit. Indianapolis: Hackett. [Google Scholar]
  17. Carby, Hazel. 1982. White women listen! Black feminism and the boundaries of sisterhood. In The Empire Strikes Back: Race and Racism in the 70s in Britain. Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  18. Carmona, Carla, David Pérez-Chico, and Chon Tejedor. 2023. Intercultural Understanding After Wittgenstein. London: Anthem Press. [Google Scholar]
  19. Carroll, Thomas. 2025. Rethinking Philosophy of Religion with Wittgenstein: Religious Diversities and Racism. London: Bloomsbury Academic. [Google Scholar]
  20. Coliva, Annalisa. 2025. Against Quasi-Fideism. Religions 16: 365. [Google Scholar]
  21. Coliva, Annalisa, and Louis Doulas. 2024. Philosophical Progress, Skepticism, and Disagreement. In The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Disagreement. Edited by Maria Baghramian, J. Adam Carter and Rach Cosker-Rowland. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  22. Collins, Patricia Hill. 2000. Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of Empowerment. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  23. Croucher, Stephen M. 2008. French-Muslims and the Hijab: An Analysis of Identity and the Islamic Veil in France. Journal of Intercultural Communication Research 37: 199–213. [Google Scholar]
  24. Davis, Angela Yvonne. 1981. Race, Women, and Class. New York: Random House. [Google Scholar]
  25. Dawkins, Richard. 2016. The God Delusion: 10th Anniversary Edition. London: Transworld Publishers. [Google Scholar]
  26. Dotson, Kristie. 2011. Tracking Epistemic Violence, Tracking Practices of Silencing. Hypatia 26: 236–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  27. Epstein, Jeffrey. 2014. Habermas, Virtue Epistemology, and Religious Justifications in the Public Sphere. Hypatia 29: 422–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  28. Fearnow, Benjamin. 2019. Atheist Richard Dawkins Compares Islam to Cancer, Ridicules Pro-Muslim Liberal Critics. Newsweek, March 27. Available online: https://www.newsweek.com/richard-dawkins-islam-cancer-sharia-law-muslim-brunei-homosexuality-1377226 (accessed on 16 March 2025).
  29. Fogelin, Robert. 1985. The Logic of Deep Disagreements. Informal Logic 7: 1–8, Reprinted in Informal Logic 25: 3–11. [Google Scholar]
  30. Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power & the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  31. Fricker, Miranda. 2023a. Diagnosing Institutionalized “Disttustworthiness”. The Philosophical Quarterly 73: 722–42. [Google Scholar]
  32. Fricker, Miranda. 2023b. Institutionalized Testimonial Injustices: The Construction of a Confession Myth. Journal of Dialectics of Nature 45: 1–12. [Google Scholar]
  33. Gakis, Dimitris. 2025. Wittgenstein’s “Family Resemblances” and Their Political Potential. In Wittgenstein and Democratic Politics: Language, Dialogue and Political Forms of Life. Edited by L. Lotar Rasiński, Anat Biletzki, Leszek Koczanowicz, Alois Pichler and Thomas Wallgren. London: Routledge, pp. 192–202. [Google Scholar]
  34. Haynes, Deborah, and Fiona Hamilton. 2014. Hundreds More UK Muslims Choose Jihad Than Army. The Times. August 22. Available online: https://www.thetimes.com/article/hundreds-more-uk-muslims-choose-jihad-than-army-l38256qqxx3 (accessed on 27 November 2024).
  35. Hick, John. 2010. Evil and the God of Love, 2nd ed. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan. [Google Scholar]
  36. Hodson, Margaret. 2020. “Modern Day Trojan Horse?” Analyzing the Nexus between Islamophobia and Anti-Refugee Sentiment in the United States. Islamophobia Studies Journal 5: 267–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  37. Hooks, Bell. 1992. Black Looks: Race and Representation. Brooklyn: South End Press. [Google Scholar]
  38. Hull, Akasha Gloria, Patricia Bell-Scott, and Barbara Smith. 1982. All the Women are White, All the Blacks are Men: But Some of Us Are Brave: Black Women’s Studies. New York: Feminist Press at CUNY. [Google Scholar]
  39. Ikuenobe, Polycarp. 1998. A defense of epistemic authoritarianism in traditional African cultures. Journal of Philosophical Research 23: 417–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  40. Joy, Morny. 2010. Rethinking the “Problem of Evil” with Hannah Arendt and Grace Jantzen. In New Topics in the Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Pamela Sue Anderson. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 17–32. [Google Scholar]
  41. Kidd, Ian James. 2017. Epistemic Injustice and Religion. In The Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice. Edited by Ian James Kidd, José Medina and Gaile Pohlhaus, Jr. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  42. Klug, Brian. 2014. The limits of analogy: Comparing Islamophobia and antisemitism. Patterns of Prejudice 48: 442–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  43. Lackey, Jennifer. 2023. Criminal Testimonial Injustice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  44. Ladner, Joyce. 1995. Tomorrow’s Tomorrow: The Black Woman. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press. [Google Scholar]
  45. Lagewaard, Thirza J. 2021. Epistemic injustice and deepened disagreement. Philosophical Studies 178: 1571–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  46. Lavorerio, Victoria. 2021a. Lectures on Religious Belief and the epistemology of disagreements. Wittgenstein Studien 12: 217–35. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  47. Lavorerio, Victoria. 2021b. The fundamental model of deep disagreements. Metaphilosophy 52: 416–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  48. Lewin, Tamar. 2001. Sikh Owner of Gas Station is Fatally Shot In Rampage. New York Times, September 17. Available online: https://www.nytimes.com/2001/09/17/us/sikh-owner-of-gas-station-is-fatally-shot-in-rampage.html (accessed on 16 March 2025).
  49. Lorde, Audre. 1984. Sister Outsider: Essays and Speeches. Trumansburg: Crossing Press. [Google Scholar]
  50. Lynch, Michael. 2010. Epistemic Circularity and Epistemic Incommensurabilty. In Social Epistemology. Edited by A. Haddock, A. Millar and D. Pritchard. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 262–77. [Google Scholar]
  51. Mann, Tanveer. 2016. Ex-Soldier Jailed for Racially Abusing Sikh Neighbours and Calling Them “ISIS Bitches”. Metro, September 18. Available online: https://metro.co.uk/2016/09/18/ex-soldier-jailed-for-racially-abusing-sikh-neighbours-and-calling-them-isis-bitches-6135147/ (accessed on 16 March 2025).
  52. McKinnon, Rachel. 2016. Epistemic Injustice. Philosophy Compass 11: 413–70. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  53. Medina, José. 2023. The Epistemology of Protest: Silencing, Epistemic Activism, and the Communicative Life of Resistance. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  54. Mohdin, Aamna, and Carmen Aguilar García. 2023. 68% of Muslims in England and Wales Live in Areas with High Unemployment. The Guardian, March 24. Available online: https://www.theguardian.com/world/2023/mar/24/two-thirds-muslims-england-wales-areas-high-unemployment (accessed on 26 November 2024).
  55. Moraga, Cherríe, and Gloria Anzaldúa, eds. 1981. This Bridge Called My Back: Writings by Radical Women of Color. London: Persephone Press. [Google Scholar]
  56. Nussbaum, Martha. 2012. The New Religious Intolerance: Overcoming the Politics of Fear in an Anxious Age. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
  57. Pichler, Alois. 2025. “For If There Is No Resurrection of the Dead, Then Christ Has Not Been Raised Either”: Wittgenstein and the Cognitive Status of Christian Belief Statements. Religions 16: 306. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  58. Pichler, Alois, and Sebastian Sunday Grève. 2025. Cognitivism about religious belief in later Wittgenstein. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 97: 61–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  59. Pohlhaus, Gaile. 2012. Relational Knowing and Epistemic Injustice: Toward a Theory of Willful Hermeneutical Ignorance. Hypatia 27: 715–35. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  60. Pohlhaus, Gaile. 2017. Varieties of Epistemic Injustice. In The Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice. Edited by Ian James Kidd, José Medina and Gaile Pohlhaus, Jr. London: Routledge, pp. 13–26. [Google Scholar]
  61. Pritchard, Duncan. 2011. Wittgensteinian Quasi-Fideism. Oxford Studies in the Philosophy of Religion 4: 145–59. [Google Scholar]
  62. Pritchard, Duncan. 2015. Wittgenstein on Faith and Reason: The Influence of Newman. In God, Truth, and Other Enigmas. Edited by Miroslaw Szatnowski. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 197–216. [Google Scholar]
  63. Pritchard, Duncan. 2016. Epistemic Angst: Radical Skepicism and the Groundlessness of Our Believing. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
  64. Pritchard, Duncan. 2017. Faith and Reason. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 81: 108–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  65. Pritchard, Duncan. 2018. Quasi-Fideism and Religious Conviction. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 10: 51–66. [Google Scholar]
  66. Pritchard, Duncan. 2021. Wittgensteinian Hinge Epistemology and Deep Disagreement. Topoi 40: 1117–25. [Google Scholar]
  67. Pritchard, Duncan. 2022. Exploring Quasi-Fideism. In Extending Hinge-Epistemology. Edited by Constantine Sandis and Danièle Moyal-Sharrock. London: Anthem Press. [Google Scholar]
  68. Pritchard, Duncan. 2023. Understanding Deep Disagreement. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 31: 301–17. [Google Scholar]
  69. Pritchard, Duncan. 2024. Deep Disagreement. In Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Disagreement. Edited by Maria Baghramian, J. Adam Carter and Rach Cosker-Rowland. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  70. Qureshi, Asim. 2014. Blowback: Foreign Fighters and the Threat They Pose. London: Cage Ltd. Available online: https://www.cage.ngo/articles/blowback---foreign-fighters-and-the-threat-they-pose (accessed on 4 February 2025).
  71. Ranalli, Chris, and Thirza Lagewaard. 2022. Deep Disagreement (Part 1): Theories of Deep Disagreement. Philosophy Compass 17: 1–18. [Google Scholar]
  72. Rattansi, Ali. 2020. Racism: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  73. Richter, Duncan. 2025. Sheer Poison? Wittgenstein’s Philosophy of Religion. Religions 16: 266. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  74. Roberts, Elwyn. 2015. “An act of Terror”: Sikh Family of Dentist Attacked in Tesco by Machete-Wielding Extremist Speak Out. WalesOnline, June 25. Available online: https://www.walesonline.co.uk/news/wales-news/an-act-terror-sikh-family-9528045 (accessed on 16 March 2025).
  75. Rosman, Rebecca. 2020. ‘France’s Decades-Long Feud Over the Hijab Takes Centre Stage. Al Jazeera. Available online: https://www.aljazeera.com/news/2020/9/22/frances-decades-long-feud-over-the-hijab-takes-centre-stage (accessed on 11 February 2025).
  76. Schönbaumsfeld, Genia. 2023. Wittgenstein on Religious Belief. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  77. Slawson, Nicola. 2017. Black and Muslim Prisoners Suffer Worse Treatment, Study Finds. The Guardian, October 19. Available online: https://www.theguardian.com/society/2017/oct/19/black-and-muslim-prisoners-suffer-worse-treatment-study-finds?CMP=share_btn_tw (accessed on 26 November 2024).
  78. Spivak, Gayatri. 1998. Can the Subaltern Speak? In Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture. Edited by Cary Nelson and Lawrence Grossberg. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, pp. 66–111. [Google Scholar]
  79. Statista Research Department. 2024. Reasons for Wearing Niqab, Hijab or Any Other VEIL among Muslim Women in France in 2019. Available online: https://www.statista.com/statistics/1058177/reasons-for-wearing-hijab-french-muslim-woman-france/ (accessed on 11 February 2025).
  80. Sturge, Georgina. 2024. UK Prison Population Statistics. House of Commons Library, July 8. Available online: https://researchbriefings.files.parliament.uk/documents/SN04334/SN04334.pdf (accessed on 27 November 2024).
  81. Sunday Grève, Sebastian. 2025. Method and Morality: Elenchus from Socrates to Wittgenstein. Synthese 205: 117. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  82. The Qur’an. 2015. Abdel Haleem, Muhammad A. S., trans. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  83. Vinten, Robert. 2022. Wittgenstein, Quasi-fideism, and Scepticism. Topoi 41: 967–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  84. Vinten, Robert. 2023. A grammatical investigation? In Meeting Balibar: A Discussion on Equaliberty and Differences. Edited by S. N. Sckell. Ribeirão: Edições Húmus, pp. 77–81. [Google Scholar]
  85. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1960. The Blue and Brown Books. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
  86. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1966. Lectures & Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
  87. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1969. On Certainty. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
  88. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1993. Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough. In Philosophical Occasions: 1912–1951. Edited by James Klagge and Alfred Nordmann. Indianapolis: Hackett. [Google Scholar]
  89. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2009. Philosophical Investigations, 4th ed. Edited by Peter Michael, Stephan Hacker and Joachim Schulte. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
  90. Wolfreys, Jim. 2023. “Avec Vous?” Islamophobia and the Macron presidency. Modern & Contemporary France 31: 165–82. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Vinten, R. Wittgenstein, Religion and Deep Epistemic Injustice. Religions 2025, 16, 418. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040418

AMA Style

Vinten R. Wittgenstein, Religion and Deep Epistemic Injustice. Religions. 2025; 16(4):418. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040418

Chicago/Turabian Style

Vinten, Robert. 2025. "Wittgenstein, Religion and Deep Epistemic Injustice" Religions 16, no. 4: 418. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040418

APA Style

Vinten, R. (2025). Wittgenstein, Religion and Deep Epistemic Injustice. Religions, 16(4), 418. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040418

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop