From Virtue to Duty: Xunzi’s Gong-Yi 公義 and the Institutionalization of Public Obligation in Early Confucianism
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Yi 義—Duty as Institutionalized Virtue
Those men with whom he collaborates in conducting the government are all men of yi. The punishments and laws he sets out for state and clan are all laws in accordance with yi. Those things which the ruler is extremely vigorous in leading his various ministers to turn their heads to are all yi intentions. When it is like this, then those below will look up to those above for being yi.
3. Yi 義 and Li* 利—Reciprocal Not Traded
- Trade-off: Hobbes argues the social contract benefits all people. Avoiding a vicious all-versus-all state of nature, people can thrive in the structured security of sovereign authority.
- Compulsion: Hobbes grants the sovereign full legal authority to compel people to do their duties.
- Consent: Hobbes argues that people implicitly consent to civil duties in the social contract and thus must accept sovereign coercion.
Both superiors and subordinates were enriched, and the commoners all felt affection for their superiors. The fact that people turned to their leaders like water flowing down, loved them with the same kind of delight they had for their own parents, and happily marched out to die for them (為之出死斷亡而愉者) was for no other reason than that the superiors had achieved the ultimate in loyalty, trustworthiness, harmoniousness, and evenhandedness.”
4. Gong 公 vs. Si 私—A Public Body
The Documents says: “Do not create new likes. Follow the kings’ way. Do not create new dislikes. On the kings’ path stay. This is saying that through gong-yi, gentlemen overcome capricious selfish desires.
The second mention is in Jundao君道:Make clear people’s allotments, their responsibilities, assign to people proper works, arrange activities, use those having talents, grant office for abilities, so none are not well ordered, nor have improprieties, then gong ways (dao) will enjoy success, and selfish (si) approaches make no progress. Gong-yi will shine bright and clear, and selfish (si) pursuits wholly disappear.
- As a collective, Xunzi’s gong is a body serviced by public duties gong-yi. Through gong-yi, the gong-body receives public interest gong-li*. Xunzi’s aim is for the collective to exert effort with unified force and praised rulers who were able to make people “exert force as if one person” 若使一人.35 The “public” here resembles Rousseau’s “general will” in that the common good is not a collection of individual interests. Like Hobbes’s bodily analogy, Xunzi’s gong is a collective body that acts in unity. Gong-body as a constructed person has been incepted.
- As a moral attitude, being gong means participating individuals must be publicly spirited, eliminate selfishness and direct moral obligations towards gong and not si. Gong-yi in this sense is the publicly spirited practice of yi-duties. Xunzi writes that shame compels avoidance of si because it aligns with normative reciprocity.36 For those who have no shame or reciprocity, legal punishments can be used.37 The chapter Yibing議兵 is the clearest example of how Xunzi understood that military service, a public duty involving considerable risk, can only be effectively motivated by yi-duties.38 Echoing Locke, Xunzi thinks that if people are only motivated by rewards and punishments, people would desist any risky public duty. Soldiers would flee at first sight of danger. Through normative reciprocity, however, people are joined in collective action even at considerable personal risk. Gong-yi describes the yi-duties that benefit the collective but present significant private sacrifice. According to Xunzi, great public work is only possible when exceptional kings master the art of leveraging yi, threatening punishments or offering li* should only supplement yi institutions.39
5. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Gong-yi may remind us of the modern Chinese usages of public duty gongong-yiwu公共義務. Despite appearing similar, the two terms may not have etymological or semantic connections. Here, we must be careful not to jump to conclusions based on the two’s similarities otherwise we may fall into the trap of attributing them as false cognates—words that appear similar but are unrelated in meaning and etymology. The modern Chinese “public duty—gongong-yiwu” can be traced to the May Fourth New Cultural Movement in the 20th century. This is when the Western concepts of “public” and “duty” were imported into China and adapted through calquing (loan translation). To better grasp the philosophical meaning of Xunzi’s gong-yi, and appreciate it within the ancient context, we should distinguish it from modern Chinese gonggong-yiwu. Thus, the “public duty” and “public obligation” used to describe gong-yi should be understood as a decontextualized abstraction from existing contemporary cultural associations. This paper does not attempt to reveal any explicit connections from this reading with the modern Chinese term gonggong-yiwu. |
2 | Sociologists Peter Berger and Thomas Luckmann (1966) define institutionalization as the process where social practices become habitual routines. Berger and Luckmann maintain that these habituated actions retain meaningfulness for individuals, but the change is that the meaning becomes embedded in routines and “a general stock of knowledge”. In philosophy, John Searle (1995) also contended that institutionalization represents a social reality that explains collective actions through constitutive rules. The modern definitions capture the two-ended yi-duty as an individually meaningful virtue and an externalized duty embedded in social routines, governed by rules. |
3 | The full passage of this phrase is “入孝出弟,人之小行也。上順下篤,人之中行也;從道不從君,從義不從父,人之大行也。” (Xunzi 29.1). Xunzi thinks that filial duties are important, but in comparison, dao and yi is more important. |
4 | According to Sima Qian’s 史記:太史公 Shiji:Taishigong, state power became a matter of survival in late Spring-Autumn, where each dukedom and kingdom had to fend for itself. This marked centralization of authority was a precursor to the Warring States reforms that saw greater expansion of public institutional power (Liu 2003). The latter period is what historians have called “the ruler-centred state” (Lewis 1999), with reforms including limitations on hereditary office, official salaries, and county-official system. This gave rise to a new class of shi that profoundly changed Classical China’s political landscape. This is the background to Xunzi’s institutionalism in that it replaces hereditary aristocracy with an educated bureaucracy. |
5 | For all Confucians, yi is: 1. Relational duties, and obligations; 2. Justness, rightness. For both Xunzi and Mengzi, it is the trait that distinguishes humans from animals because it specifically refers to the capacity for humans to function within our social arrangements (Tan 2005) and can be distinguished from ren humaneness as a personal trait or characteristic (Lau 1979). |
6 | As Donald Munro (1969) explained, Chinese ethics uses emotions rather than being opposed to them. |
7 | Mengzi 1A1. |
8 | John Knoblock explains Wangba within the historical context of the Warring States when the quality of stateman varied greatly. The ideal leaders were those like the ancient Kings like Tang and Wu, but Kongzi’s exceptional performance in political stewardship was also included. |
9 | Incidentally, Aristotle thought justice was the most important virtue for a city because fairness and even-handedness in governance ensure all are given their due. The Hobbesian institutionalization of state “justice” under the “sovereign” marks the most radical challenge to Classical theories in that Hobbes believes the term needs to be strictly defined and rigidly regulated by the “sovereign” to avoid conflict and confusion. For Hobbes, justice is an artificial virtue merely necessary for an orderly society and a product of the social contract. Xunzi proposes a far less radical move on yi but its institutionalization “demystifies” the virtue in a similar sense by anchoring it to state institutions. |
10 | In Fuguo (Xunzi 10.1), Xunzi claims that desires are many and resources are few: “欲多而物寡”. For Dongfang (2023), this proposition is an admittance of the chaotic state of “nature” in positing conflict is inevitable if resources cannot satisfy everyone’s desires. This reminds us that Xunzi deeply resonates with Hobbesian natural law and the deep mistrust of humans. Given the natural scarcity of resources and the insatiable nature of human desires, without artificial constraints, both Xunzi and Hobbes agree that conflict and chaos are inevitable. |
11 | Rituals (禮li) here is used in a general sense to refer to the social norms that govern social behaviour according to hierarchy and status. According to Xunzi, this social institution distributes resources because it introduces an ordinal way for each to receive their due and avoids the all-versus-all competition for limited resources. Explaining this in Fuguo, Xunzi (Xunzi 10.1–10.2) claims that competition leads to poverty and rituals portions resources (jie 節) according to rank and status, noble and petty (gui-jian 貴賤). Xunzi elaborates further in Lilun (Xunzi 19.1 and 19.3) that rituals avoid conflict by satisfying desires in an orderly manner. He affirms that these desires are immutable, therefore the only solution to the conflict is social institutions. Rituals and yi 禮義 appear together roughly over half of the total times yi is mentioned 115 out of 315 times and warrant lengthy discussion that will be beyond the scope of the argument here. |
12 | Writing Dalüe Xunzi (27.21) tells us that yi is treating people according to their social rank and status. But this is far from a satisfying answer because it just pushes the functional question further down and raises the question: how does hierarchy produce orderliness and morality? However, it is indeed useful that this statement tells us that Xunzi’s yi must also be sensitive to hierarchy, and thus social-political leveraging. |
13 | Note here that the modern distinction between guilt and shame does not hold in the Classical writings of Aristotle or Xunzi. In the modern socio-psychological nomenclature, guilt is the inner emotion, and shame is concerned with the opinions of the community. But in both Aristotle and Xunzi, shame has been associated with both inner reflection and community opinion (Zhao 2024, p. 106). Thus, it is not useful to understand shame in this context as external, community-driven. |
14 | |
15 | Another way Mengzi uses yi in the term 義憤填膺 yi righteous indignant (although yi does not always induce rage) also captures this sentiment of yi being some internal sentiment that bursts out into action. |
16 | Kongzi’s view on li* is slightly more nuanced than Mengzi’s. Analects 4:16: 君子喻與義,小人喻與利。Stating that a junzi knows the yi and the petty person knows li*, placing the two in opposition. At the same time, Analects 20:2: 因民之所利而利之,斯不亦惠而不費乎。Saying that a person in authority can benefit the people, a view closer to Xunzi. Overall, I placed Kongzi here together with Mengzi to demonstrate Kong’s deep commitment to virtues in contrast to Xunzi. |
17 | Leo Strauss famously contends that Hobbes’s political focus on self-preservation at the foundations of political legitimacy incepted the modern, liberal discourse of rights versus duties and spawned the powerful legal institutions that enabled our orderly societies today. As Western “legal rights” are not even a concept in Classical China, it does not come close to Xunzi’s public duty and I will not pursue this comparison. |
18 | Hobbes (1640) reconstructs the Medieval natural law theory and posits in Leviathan that natural law is derived from reasons based upon the basic instinct of self-preservation. Xunzi shares the sentiment that people are naturally chaotic and that people cannot be allowed to pursue their own goals. In contrast to Hobbes, the general rule that rescues humans from chaos is not derived from reason as such. Instead, morality is cultivated by transforming the heart-mind (心 xin) to seek the right types of desires (Xunzi 22: 14, Xunzi 1.18). Herein lies a major difference between Xunzi and social contract theorists in that Xunzi posits morality qua civility whereas Western contract theories posit civility as rational-legal constraints. |
19 | “今以夫先王之道,仁義之統,以相群居,以相持養。” (Xunzi 4:10), “故人生不能無群,群而無分則爭,爭則亂,亂則離,離則弱,弱則不能勝物。” (Xunzi 9.20) |
20 | It is sometimes hard to distinguish how they are different. Defoort mentions that emotive and descriptive definitions of li* 利 are that: 1. Used to mean selfishness and profitability that is bad for aristocrats to discuss; 2. To describe how to derive benefits. |
21 | This change is partly traced to a debate between the idea that li* diminishes when shared and li* is enhanced when shared, captured in the saying “以義生利, 利以豐民。” (Guoyu, Jinyu 國語·晉語一) An important contribution also came from the text Guanzi (管子), where it was argued that sharing li* enhances its benefits, a text that Xunzi was likely influenced by (Sato 2003). |
22 | There is some controversy over the translation of the phrase 志愛公利 zhi-ai-gong-li, literal translation: will to-love-public-profit in Fu (Xunzi 26.11). T. Wang’s (2005) compilation of past annotations contrasts Zhu Xi’s (Song Dynasty) reading, which suggests taking this as a criticism meaning “profit from public office” with Yang Liang’s (Tang Dynasty) interpretation to mean “use public office to benefit the people”. Eric Hutton (2014, p. 514) provides a good summary of the problem, as the confusion arises from the format of the poem where it juxtaposes a line of “good deeds” with the next line’s “bad deeds”. I will not delve into the literary side of this interpretation, but I find Yang Liang’s reading more convincing as it is too much of a stretch to extend ai in this phrase to mean “My will (zhi) love (ai) profit so much, I am willing to exploit others”. Suppose Yang Liang is right, we could further say that profiting is permissible if it benefits the common people. |
23 | Defoort identifies three levels of public profiting in Xunzi’s writings ranked in three levels of desirability: 1st—“One who benefits them and does not benefit from them, who cares for them but does not use them, will get the realm. 利而不利也, 愛而不用也者, 天下矣。”; 2nd—“One who benefits from them only after benefiting them, who uses them only after caring for them, will protect the altars of soil and grain. 利而後利之, 愛而後用之者, 保社稷矣。”; 3rd—“One who benefits from them while not benefiting them, who uses them while not caring for them, will endanger his state (and family). 不利而利之, 不愛而用之者, 危國家也。” (Defoort 178). Quotations taken from Fuguo (Xunzi 10). Furthermore, Xunzi accepts that a junzi can cautiously seek li*利: “In seeking profit, the gentleman acts with restraint.” |
24 | “先義而後利者榮,先利而後義者辱。” (Xunzi 4.7). |
25 | The Chinese concept of affection and care should not be confused with the Christian notion of agape love or romantic love. On this topic, Chengyang Li (2023, p. 63) writes that Confucian care encompasses a broad range of sentiments such as the impulse to care for another and affection towards another. |
26 | Xunzi’s refutations of Songzi and Mozi clearly show his understanding of desires yu as an immutable force. He argues that Songzi is mistaken to believe people have little desires (Xunzi 18. 40–43). He further refutes Mozi’s frugal state and rejects the idea that people would be satisfied with basic life-sustaining food and water. For Xunzi, rituals and social institutions such as music and rituals are not extravagant wastes because without them life would be needlessly bitter (Xunzi 10.10). Xunzi raises a thought experiment against Mozi and Songzi’s position, even if people are living minimally as Mozi wishes, would there truly be no competition? (Xunzi 18.43) Taken together, Xunzi has a coherent position on human desires: it is a powerful and numerous force that must be accommodated. |
27 | Again, returning to Mengzi’s argument in Mengzi 1A1, he treats the very idea of li* pejoratively. A brute comparison with Mengzi will show that he mentions profit li* 利 much more: 201 times as opposed to 39. This is a very coarse comparison as the character sometimes can mean “sharp” and “harsh” and not just “profit”, but we do get the sense that the difference in total times mentioned is quite large. |
28 | This contrasts with Hobbes, who thinks sacrificing one’s life is not a public duty. This further complicates our comparison, but usefully shows the extent of Xunzi’s moral obligation extending beyond Hobbesian right-to-preservation. There are some senses in which Locke’s moral obligation argument is similar, but this is still not normative reciprocity. Locke carefully registers this exchange, taking the familiar Liberal line which is that duties should be matched to protected fundamental rights and held that the requirements of obeying the civil government under a social contract are conditioned on the protection of natural rights. |
29 | The potential of care ethics being compatible with Confucianism was first raised by Chenyang Li (1994). In Confucianism this ideal political state is called the ‘Great Community’, while in care ethics it has been called the ‘Caring State’.” |
30 | Hobbes writes: “A person, is he, whose words or actions are considered, either as his own, or as representing the words or actions of another man, or of any other thing to whom they are attributed.” Xunzi does not fully align with Hobbes’ idea that private individuals are subsumed under a collective body. This body has a will and requires service from these individuals in a way not dissimilar to this covenant. But I think the similarities end here, and risks becoming too superficial if extended further. |
31 | Yan Hui was asked by Confucius to reflect on his private life si (Analects 2.9) and Mengzi uses si to refer to private affairs without prejudice (Mengzi 3A3). |
32 | The public fields are likely referring to the well-field system井田制. Each family would own their private land and a central field in the middle would be collectively operated by families of the surrounding fields as a form of physical labour tax. |
33 | The other instances are in Rongru, Xunzi claims that lou 陋 “boorishness” is of public threat. In Jiebi he claims that fixating on this is a common problem. |
34 | Indeed, Yang Liang annotates Xunzi’s use of gong-yi with Mozi’s line on how to select capable ministers 舉公義 辟私怨, “uplift public-yi, punish private grudges”. For Mozi, we just need to know that he thought that people should love each other equally. He calls this jian-ai兼愛. Mozi does think yi and li* 利 are opposites, stating that public dutifulness will bring about mutual benefit jiaoxiang-li* 交相利 (Liu 2023). This was far from Xunzi’s position so I will not delve into this topic any further. |
35 | “推禮義之統,分是非之分,總天下之要,治海內之眾,若使一人。” Xunzi (3.10), which Hutton (2014, p. 21) interprets as the influence of rituals and yi allowing the mass (zhong 衆) to be ordered: “as though employing one person”. Knoblock also explains this passage in this vein but (171) pains to trace the idea of a gentleman/ruler’s (junzi君子) capacity for such a move to the belief that virtues and genuine nature (cheng 誠) move people by moral exemplification. T. Wang (2005) summarized the Sinophone annotations and suggested that a junzi uses succinct (yue 約) moral principles to achieve the grand effect of the employment of a mass. Core ideas of these interpretations centre on the collective unity and the ability of this body to act in unison. |
36 | Xunzi 2.12. |
37 | “政令以定,風俗以一,有離俗不順其上,則百姓莫不敦惡,莫不毒孽,若祓不祥;然後刑於是起矣。是大刑之所加也,辱孰大焉!將以為利邪?則大刑加焉,身苟不狂惑戇陋,誰睹是而不改也哉。” (Xunzi 15.25) |
38 | See note 37, Xunzi’s Yibing argues that yi is the primary motivator for fighters because of the shame of failure. |
39 | See note 33, Xunzi 3.10. |
40 | I agree that there is a significant distance between Xunzi and Han Feizi. My minor contention with Erik L. Harris’s (2013, pp. 105–9) assessment is his claim that Xunzi represents a defence of virtue politics in believing rulers could become virtuous. In my view, Xunzi accepts this only as a remote possibility and holds moral standards as an aspirational goal rather than an immediately actionable possibility. In Wangba, he is sanguine about the dire state of governance. Although he thinks virtues are the ultimate solution, Xunzi seems to me as saying that virtues alone are necessary but not sufficient. This is also why I think the institutional elements of Xunzi’s moral argument ought to receive attention. |
41 | Harris (2016, p. 111) argues that fen is the descriptive allotment of roles and the success of this allotment depends on yi as the types of conduct that expresses a person’s character. I am very sympathetic to this argument and agree that yi is conduct-based. I may further my explanation may show that fen-allotments are roles by which yi-duties are assigned. In the same way, the division of labour creates productivity and mutual dependence, the allotment and assignment of roles and duties allow people to be normatively dependent. We need our teachers, parents, children, and students to perform their yi-duties so that schools and families can function. On the scale of the gong-public, we could further speculate that Xunzi may have thought public duties helped similarly state productivity and normative reciprocity. |
42 | “法勝私” Xunzi 2.12, “行法至堅,不以私欲亂所聞 如是,則可謂勁士矣。” (Xunzi 8.11) See also note 36. |
43 | The willingness to use the law against a private impulse suggests that Xunzi’s gong resembles Rousseau’s view of the “legislator”. However, Xunzi does not base his arguments on natural freedoms nor attempt to ground gong legal coercion through anything like being “forced to be free”; frankly admitting the public needs to be protected from private duties. |
44 | Yang Liang’s annotation also supports this reading: 以公滅私, 故賞罰得中也, “using the public to eliminate the private, reward and punish fairly”. |
45 | 吕氏春秋·上农: “古先圣王之所以导其民者,先务于农。民农非徒为地利也,贵其志也。民农则朴,朴则易用,易用则边境安,主位尊。民农则重,重则少私义,少私义则公法立,力专一。民农则其产复,其产复则重徙,重徙则死处而无二虑。” |
46 | 商君書: “國亂者,民多私義”. 韓非子: “私義行則亂,公義行則治。” |
47 | For how Xunzi’s view of filial relationships progressed, we may refer to Li’s (2023, pp. 108–9) chapter on “Filial Care” in Reshaping Confucianism. |
48 | Although I would caution against excessively drawing on historical concepts to explain phenomena in modern Chinese public spheres, as they may not be related. See note 1. |
49 | It is perhaps telling that many organized crimes and underground societies use yi-qi (義氣) to label the sense of duty owed to one another in their collective anti-social behaviour. In colloquial Chinese, this is sometimes called 江湖義氣 (brotherhood yi, underworld yi). |
References
Primary Sources
Hanfeizi 韓非子. Chinese Text Project, Pre-Qin and Han, Legalism. Available online: https://ctext.org/hanfeizi (accessed on 18 February 2025)Lunyu 論語. Chinese Text project, Pre-Qin and Han, Confucianism. Available online: http://ctext.org/analects (accessed on 18 February 2025)Lü Shi Chun Qiu 呂氏春秋. Chinese Text Project, Pre-Qin and Han, Miscellaneous Schools. https://ctext.org/lv-shi-chun-qiu (accessed on 18 February 2025)Mengzi 孟子. Chinese Text Project, Pre-Qin and Han, Confucianism. Available online: https://ctext.org/mengzi (accessed on 18 February 2025)Shang Jun Shu 商君書. Chinese Text Project, Pre-Qin and Han, Legalism. Available online: https://ctext.org/shang-jun-shu (accessed on 18 February 2025)Shijing 詩經. Chinese Text Project, Pre-Qin and Han, Ancient Classics. Available online: https://ctext.org/book-of-poetry (accessed on 18 February 2025)Xunzi 荀子. Chinese Text Project, Pre-Qin and Han, Confucianism. Available online: https://ctext.org/mengzi (accessed on 18 February 2025)Secondary Sources
- Angle, Stephen C., and Michael Slote, eds. 2013. Virtue Ethics and Confucianism. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Arendt, Hannah. 1970. On Violence. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1981. The Politics. Translated by Trevor Saunders, and T. A. Sinclair. London: Penguin Classics. [Google Scholar]
- Berger, Peter L., and Thomas Luckmann. 1966. The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. New York: Anchor Books. [Google Scholar]
- Crisp, Roger. 2019. Sacrifice Regained: Morality and Self-Interest in British Moral Philosophy from Hobbes to Bentham. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Cua, Antonio. 2003. The Ethical Significance of Shame: Insights of Aristotle and Xunzi. Philosophy East and West 53: 147–202. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Defoort, Carine. 2008. The Profit That Does Not Profit: Paradoxes with ‘Li’ in Early Chinese Texts. Asia Major 21: 153–81. [Google Scholar]
- Dongfang, Shuo 东方朔. 2011. Helixing Zhi Xunqiu: Xunzi Sixiang Yanjiu Lunji 合理性之尋求: 荀子思想研究論集 The Quest for Rationality: Collected Research on the Thought of Xunzi. Taipei: National Taiwan University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dongfang, Shuo 东方朔. 2023. Quanwei Yu Zhixu: Xunzi Zhengzhi Zhexue Yanjiu 权威与秩序: 荀子政治哲学研究 Authority and Order: Research on Xunzi’s Political Philosophy. Beijing: Sanlian Shudian. [Google Scholar]
- Feng, Youlan 馮友蘭. 1931. Zhong Guo Zhe Xue Shi 中國哲學史 History of Chinese Philosophy. Shanghai: Shenzhou Guoguangshe, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Harris, Eirik Lang. 2013. The Role of Virtue in Xunzi’s 荀子 Political Philosophy. Dao 12: 93–110. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Harris, Eirik Lang. 2016. Xunzi’s Political Philosophy. In Dao’s Companion to the Philosophy of Xunzi. Edited by Eric Hutton. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer, pp. 95–138. [Google Scholar]
- Hobbes, Thomas. 1640. The Elements of Law. In The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic. Edited by J. C. A. Gaskin. Oxford: Oxford University Press, p. 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Hobbes, Thomas. 1651. Leviathan. In Leviathan. Edited by J. C. A. Gaskin. Oxford: Oxford University Press, p. 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Huang, Yong. 2020. Justice as a Personal Virtue and Justice as an Institutional Virtue: Mencius’s Confucian Virtue Politics. Yearbook for Eastern and Western Philosophy 2020: 277–94. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hutton, Eric. 2002. Moral reasoning in Aristotle and Xunzi. Journal of Chinese Philosophy 29: 355–84. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hutton, Eric. 2014. Xunzi: The Complete Text. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ivanhoe, Philip J. 1994. Human Nature and Moral Understanding in Xunzi. International Philosophical Quarterly 34: 167–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2025. Morality as an Artifact: The Nature of Moral Norms in Xunzi’s Philosophy. In Oxford Handbook of Chinese Philosophy. Edited by Justin Tiwald. New York: Oxford University Press, forthcoming. [Google Scholar]
- Kim, Sungmoon. 2019. Theorizing Confucian Virtue Politics: The Political Philosophy of Mencius and Xunzi. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kline, T. C., III. 2000. Moral Agency and Motivation in the Xunzi. In Virtue, Nature, and Moral Agency in the Xunzi. Edited by T. C. Kline, III and Philip J. Ivanhoe. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, pp. 155–75. [Google Scholar]
- Knoblock, John. 1988. Xunzi: A Translation and Study of the Complete Works, Volume 1: Books 1–6. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Knoblock, John. 1990. Xunzi: A Translation and Study of the Complete Works, Volume II: Books 7–16. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lau, D. C. 1979. The Analects by Confucius. London: Penguin Classics. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, Mark. 1999. Warring States: Political History. In The Cambridge History of Ancient China. Edited by Michael Loewe and Edward L. Shaughnessy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 587–650. [Google Scholar]
- Li, Chenyang. 1994. The Confucian Concept of Jen and the Feminist Ethics of Care: A Comparative Study. Hypatia 9: 70–89. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Li, Chenyang. 2011. Xunzi on the origin of goodness: A new interpretation. Journal of Chinese Philosophy 38: 46–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Li, Chenyang. 2023. Reshaping Confucianism: A Progressive Inquiry. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Leheng. 2023. Mengzi’s View on the Public and the Private. In Dao Companion to the Philosophy of Mencius. Edited by Yang Xiao and Kim-Chong Chong. New York: Springer, pp. 235–58. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Zehua 刘泽华. 2003. Chunqiu Zhanguo De Ligong Miesi Guannian Yu Shehui Zhenghe 春秋战国立公灭私观念与社会整合 of the Senses of “Li Gong Mie Si” from Period of the Spring and Autumn to the Period of the Warring States and the Conformity of Society. Beijing: China Renmin University Press, pp. 1–39. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Zehua 刘泽华, and Rongming Zhang 张荣明. 2003. Gongsi Guannian Yu Zhongguo Shehui 公私观念与中国社会 Private Concepts and Chinese Society. Beijing: China Renmin University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Locke, John. 1689. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Edited by Peter H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press, p. 1975. [Google Scholar]
- Mou, Zongsan 牟宗三. 1979. Xunzi Yu Mingjia 荀子與名家 School of Names and Xunzi. Taipei: Student Book. [Google Scholar]
- Munro, Donald J. 1969. The Concept of Man in Early China. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nivison, David S. 1996. The Ways of Confucianism: Investigations in Chinese Philosophy. La Salle: Open Court. [Google Scholar]
- Pettit, Philip. 2008. Made with Words: Hobbes on Language, Mind, and Politics. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rousseau, Jean Jacques. 1755. Un Discours sur l’Origine et les Fondemens de l’Inégalité parmi les Hommes (A Discourse on the Origin of Inequality; Second Discourse). Oxford: Oxford University Press, p. 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Sato, Masayuki. 2003. The Confucian Quest for Order: The Origin and Formation of the Political Thought of Xun Zi. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Sato, Masayuki. 2020. Xunzi Yu Lüshi Chunqiu De Gong Gainian《荀子》與《呂氏春秋》的「公」概念. A Study of the Concept of Gong (Fairness/Impartiality) in Xunzi and Mr. Lü’s Spring and Autumn Annals. Taiwanese Journal of Political Science, 1–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Searle, John. 1995. The Construction of Social Reality. New York: Free Press. [Google Scholar]
- Shun, Kwong-Loi. 2005. Zhu Xi on Gong (impartial) and Si (partial). Dao 5: 1–9. [Google Scholar]
- Sung, Winnie. 2015. Ethical transformation in the Xunzi: A partial explanation. Chinese Philosophy and Culture 13: 69–97. [Google Scholar]
- Tan, Sor-hoon. 2005. Imagining Confucius: Paradigmatic Characters and Virtue Ethics. Journal of Chinese Philosophy 32: 409–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Norden, Bryan W. 2007. Virtue Ethics and Consequentialism in Early Chinese Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Jie 王洁. 2009. Lun Xunzi De Deyu Zhexue Jianlun Xunzi Xing E Lun Zhong De Gongyi Youxian Sixiang 论荀子的“德育哲学”兼论荀子性恶论中的“公义”优先思想 Xunzi’s Philosophy of Moral Education: The Prioritization of Justice in His Theory of Evil Human Nature. Journal of Nanjing Normal University (Social Science), 89–96. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Rouzhu. 2023. For the Common Good: The Symbiosis between Individual and Community in the Philosophy of Xunzi. Religions 14: 553. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wang, Tianhai 王天海. 2005. Xunzi Jiao Shi 荀子校释 Xunzi Annotations. 2 vols. Shanghai: Shanghai Guji Chubanshe. [Google Scholar]
- Watson, Burton. 2003. Xunzi: Basic Writings. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wong, David B. 2000. Xunzi on Moral Motivation. In Virtue, Nature, and Moral Agency in the Xunzi. Edited by T. C. Kline, III and Philip J. Ivanhoe. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, pp. 135–54. [Google Scholar]
- Xu, Fuguan 徐復觀. 1969. Zhongguo Renxinglunshi: Xianqinpian 中國人性論史:先秦篇 History of Chinese theories on Human Nature: The Pre-Qin Period. Taipei: The Commercial Press. [Google Scholar]
- Yang, Soon-ja. 2021. Yi as ‘Meaning-Bestowing’ in the Xunzi. Dao 20: 115–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zhao, Jingyi Jenny. 2024. Aristotle and Xunzi on Shame, Moral Education, and the Good Life. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Zhu, Cheng 朱承. 2022. Yi Qun Guanzhi: Xunzi De Gonggongxing Sixiang 以群观之: 荀子的公共性思想 From the Perspective of “Group” (Qun 群): Xun Zi’s Thought of Publicity. Kongzi Studies, 69–81. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Huang, Y. From Virtue to Duty: Xunzi’s Gong-Yi 公義 and the Institutionalization of Public Obligation in Early Confucianism. Religions 2025, 16, 268. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16030268
Huang Y. From Virtue to Duty: Xunzi’s Gong-Yi 公義 and the Institutionalization of Public Obligation in Early Confucianism. Religions. 2025; 16(3):268. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16030268
Chicago/Turabian StyleHuang, Yijia. 2025. "From Virtue to Duty: Xunzi’s Gong-Yi 公義 and the Institutionalization of Public Obligation in Early Confucianism" Religions 16, no. 3: 268. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16030268
APA StyleHuang, Y. (2025). From Virtue to Duty: Xunzi’s Gong-Yi 公義 and the Institutionalization of Public Obligation in Early Confucianism. Religions, 16(3), 268. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16030268