The Middle Path of Rational Faith: Jaspers and Kant
Abstract
1. Introduction
2. Kant: I Will That There Be a God…
3. The Faith of Needy Reason
4. The Moral Core of Religion
5. Jaspers: To Live from the Encompassing
6. Deadly Claim to Exclusivity
7. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
Abbreviations
AA | Kant’s gesammelte Schriften. Edited by the Royal Prussian, later German, then Berlin-Brandenburg Academy of Sciences, Berlin. Akadamie Ausgabe. |
GMS | Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten. English version: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Cambridge University Press, 2012. |
KpV | Kritik der praktischen Vernunft. English version: Critique of Practical Reason. In: Immanuel Kant, Practical Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, 1996. |
KU | Kritik der Urteilskraft. English version: Critique of the Power of Judgment. Cambridge University Press, 2002. |
KrV | Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Citations refer to the pagination in the second edition (B). English version: Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge University Press, 1998. |
RGV | Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der bloßen Vernunft. English version: Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, Cambridge University Press, 2018. |
WDO | Was heisst: sich im Denken orientieren? English version: What Does It Mean to Orient Oneself In Thinking? In I. Kant, Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason (pp. 1–16). Cambridge University Press, 2018. |
1 | The Kantian passage of this letter continues: “With him, all ‘ontology’ comes to an end.” Ibid. Regarding the problem of ontology in the context of Jaspers/Heidegger relation, see the following eloquent words questioning Heidegger’s concept of the History of Being: “History of Being—what is it? Why are Being and Divinity not identical?” (“Geschichte des Seins—was ist das? Warum Sein und Gottheit nicht identisch?” Jaspers (2013, p. 60)). All translations from Jaspers are my own. |
2 | Although Kantian motifs in Jaspers’ philosophy are regularly reflected, studies explicitly focused on the theme of rational faith are scarce. For an exception see Holz (1977, pp. 404–19). The author sees the constellation of the two as follows: “The relevance of Jaspers’ philosophy, at least for our topic, does not lie primarily in what he has to offer that is ‘original’, but precisely in the fact that his thinking has provided a special, original way of interpreting Kant [eine originelle Art der Kantauslegung].” Holz (1977, p. 410). In what follows I show that regarding the philosophical faith, the talk of a “Kantauslegung” cannot be justified. |
3 | Wernicki (2018, p. 82), following Corrington, is trying to read Jaspers “through naturalistic lens” (where “naturalism” is simply taken as the assumption that “nature is all that there is”), which, with Jaspers‘ insistence on the transcendent Being, doesn’t seem a promising attempt. There doesn’t seem to be much sense in identifying Jaspers’ notion of Being with “natural reality” (Wernicki 2018, p. 90). |
4 | See e.g., phrases like “Here it is necessary to remember the great teaching of Kant, which has its antecedents in the Western and Asian history of philosophy. Its basic idea must have emerged wherever philosophy was practiced at all, and yet as a self-conscious and methodically elaborated idea it became only in Kant … It is the idea of the phenomenal nature of our being in the split between subject and object, bound to space and time as forms of perception, to categories as forms of thought” (Jaspers 2017, p. 14). On the consistent development of Jaspers’ high rating of Kant, see Jaspers (1957). On Jaspers’ ambivalent evaluation of Classical German Philosophy see Czakó (2020). |
5 | For the abbreviations and editions used to cite Kant, see the list at the end of the paper. |
6 | See Kant’s assurance regarding philosophy: “That which mingles these pure principles with the empirical does not deserve the name of philosophy” (GMS, AA 04:390). |
7 | The primarily theoretical-epistemological closeness of Jaspers and Kant is dealt with by Olson (1979). One can agree with the claim that “adapting the critical epistemological insights of Kant to the language of Existenz, Jaspers recovers what he believes to be the essential intent and purpose of Kantian Kritik, namely a disclosure of the limits of objectifying thinking which does not put an end to thinking but permits transcending or true metaphysical thinking to begin at a critical level” (Olson 1979, p. 73). The starting point for transcendent thinking rests on theoretically grasped ideas, which become “the cracks through which the Supersensible comes to be known” (ibid., p. 81). Thanks to this, the author notes, “transcending for Kant, as for Jaspers, is always cognitive transcending, a transcending through thinking” (ibid., p. 83). This statement is not correct, because for Kant the experience of freedom is inseparable from the situated moral action, for which theoretical considerations do not play the vital role. |
8 | „Vernunft … ist selbst der totale Kommunikationswille” (Jaspers 2017, p. 39). |
9 | “Everyone must admit that if a law is to have moral force, i.e., to be the basis of an obligation, it must carry with it absolute necessity” (GMS, AA 04:389). |
10 | The fact that Kant’s elaboration of his ethics is based on the facticity of the ethical phenomenon, that his approach cannot be overburdened with popular problems like the “justification of morality”, is properly emphasized in the last commentary on the Groundwork by Ludwig (2020, pp. 8–25). |
11 | In his commentary on the second Critique, Beck (1960, p. 247) qualifies the antinomy in the concept of the highest good as “devised and artificial”. |
12 | From extensive literature on the question of persuasiveness of Kantian rational faith we can point to the sceptical position of Habermas (2019) in his latest book Auch eine Geschichte der Philosophie. Vernünftige Freiheit. Spuren des Diskurses über Glauben und Wissen. Habermas speaks of a “vain rational faith” (“dürrer Vernunftglaube”, p. 301), of “emaciated postulates of rational faith” (“abgemagerte Postulate eines Vernunftglaubens”, p. 310). Habermas believes that Kant’s characterization of reason—especially in relation to man’s highest purpose—is essentially a blank check: it cannot deliver what it promises. He concludes that Kant’s rational morality fails to satisfy the need of finite rational beings to orient themselves in the world (Habermas 2019, p. 354). |
13 | An unequivocal summary is provided by Höffe (2010, p. 7): “All three critiques culminate in a philosophical religion, admittedly a purely natural religion, not inspired by any sacred scriptures.” As for the Critique of Judgment, compare, e.g., this explication from the note to § 86, exactly coinciding with the Critique of Practical Reason: “It is therefore at least possible and grounded too in our moral disposition to represent a pure moral need of the existence of a Being, by which our morality gains strength or even … more scope, that is, a new object for its exercise. That is, [there is a need] to assume a morally-legislating Being outside the world, without any reference to theoretical proofs, still less to self-interest, from pure moral grounds free from all foreign influence (and consequently only subjective), on the mere recommendation of a pure practical reason legislating by itself alone” (KU, AA 05:446). |
14 | For a clear summary of the “Pantheismusstreit” see Wood (1996, pp. 3–6). |
15 | Kant intensively thought about the problem of orientation eighteen years earlier in his smaller pre-critical work Concerning the Ultimate Ground of the Differentiation of Directions in Space (Von dem ersten Grunde des Unterschiedes der Gegenden im Raume, AA 02:377–383). |
16 | “On the other hand, rational belief, which is based on the need to use reason in a practical sense, might be called a postulate of reason; not because it is an insight that satisfies all the logical requirements necessary for certainty, but because this holding something to be true (if only everything is morally rightly ordered in man) is not behind any knowledge in degree, though it is quite different in kind from it” (WDO, AA 08:141). |
17 | “…since humans can’t bring about happiness in the world proportionate to worthiness to be happy, an omnipotent moral being must be postulated as ruler of the world, under whose care this proportion is achieved. That is, morality leads inevitably to religion.” For equating moral commands and divine commands see Hare (2000, p. 471), who opposes “creative anti-realism” typical of “Rawlsians such as Christine Korsgaard and J.B. Schneewind” and claims that “Autonomous submission, I want to say, is recapitulating in our wills what God has willed for our willing”. On “ineluctable link between morality and theism”, contrasted to Kant’s pre-critical attitude towards God’s existence, see Perrier (2021). |
18 | |
19 | |
20 | “The aim of those who at the end of life have a cleric summoned is usually that they want to have a comforter in him, not because of the physical sufferings that the last illness—or indeed even just the natural fear of death—carries with it (for, concerning these, death itself, which ends them, can be the comforter), but because of the moral sufferings, namely the reproaches of conscience. Now, here conscience should rather be stirred up and sharpened, in order by no means to neglect what good is still to be done, or what evil—in terms of its remaining consequences—is still to be annihilated (repaired for). … But to give to the person, in place of this, opium for his conscience, as it were, is to incur guiltiness against this person himself and against others surviving him entirely contrary to the final aim for which, at the end of life, such support of conscience may be held to be needed” (RGV, AA 06:78). |
21 | Kant repeatedly formulates this connection as the primacy of the ethical “ought” (Sollen), founding the concrete-practical “can” (Können): “He judges, therefore, that he can do a certain thing because he is conscious that he ought, and he recognizes that he is free- a fact which but for the moral law he would never have known” (KpV, AA 05:30). Or in the Religion: “This idea’s reality is, in a practical point of view, contained completely in itself, for it has its rise and spring from our morally legislative Reason. We ought to conform ourselves to it; consequently we can” (RGV, AA 06:62). |
22 | See this passage contrasting historical and moral belief in relation to the question of miracles: “this faith could only be historical, whereas the belief in the practical validity of that idea, as seated in reason, alone possesses moral worth; and this idea it is, that must first accredit miracles as signs from on high, not the idea, that from them, is to receive its confirmation” (RGV, AA 06:63). |
23 | According to Wernicki (2018, p. 88), “revelational faith and philosophical faith can never engage in productive dialogue”, which, in my reading presented here, goes against the motif of mutual inspiration and the need of communication, so much stressed by Jaspers. |
24 | “The genuine religious person can become a theologian, but not a philosopher without a break, and the philosopher as such cannot become a religious person without a break” (Jaspers 1994, p. 294). |
25 | The lectures Der philosophische Glaube were given in Basel in 1947 and published in 1948. An extensive elaboration under the title Der philosophische Glaube angesichts der Offenbarung was published in 1962, not long before Jaspers’ eightieth birthday, and is now found, together with the preparatory title Der philosophische Glaube angesichts der christlichen Offenbarung, in volume 13 of the monumental edition of Jaspers’ work (Jaspers 2016a). |
26 | “Fragen wir, woraus und wohin wir Leben sollen…” (Jaspers 2017, p. 9). |
27 | The words “stricter” and “looser” refer to the philosophical basis of faith. The question of what consequences they have for the concrete practical life of faith is certainly important, but it does not fall within the scope of this study. |
28 | “Seinsinnewerden aus dem Ursprung durch Vermittlung der Geschichte und des Denkens” (Jaspers 2017, p. 15). |
29 | Cf. “The Encompassing that I am is in every form the polarity of subject and object: My being is to be seen as abiding: as an inner world and its surroundings, as consciousness per se: consciousness and [its] object… The Encompassing that I am as it were embraces the Encompassing, which is Being itself, and is at the same time embraced by it” (Jaspers 2017, p. 19). |
30 | “Als Existenz bin ich, indem ich mich durch Transzendenz mir geschenkt weiß” (Jaspers 2017, p. 20). The path of clarification leads to transcendence understood as “the Encompassing of all Encompassing”, “das Umgreifende alles Umgreifenden” (Jaspers 2016a, p. 34). This path of clarification and assurance leads so to say to both sides: self and being: “Selbstvergewisserung ist zugleich Seinsvergewisserung” (Jaspers 2016a, p. 40). |
31 | In relation to the “ciphers”, Jaspers makes interesting use of the motif of the language and hearing (“hear the language of transcendence”) as opposed to the visual plane, which would more readily lend itself (deciphering seems to be more connected with sight; on the other hand, the best-known form of cypher in Jaspers‘ time, the morse code, is usually decoded acoustically. Conf.: “The ideas, images, thoughts in the medium of consciousness in general, in which I hear a language of transcendence as a possible existence, we call ciphers of transcendence” (Jaspers 2016b, p. 157). |
32 | For Jaspers, his Basel colleague H. Barth was a typical representative of Christian philosophy. On the relationship of Jaspers and H. Barth see (Wildermuth 2007). |
33 | See the unequivocal statement from a later treatise on rational faith: “The incarnate God Christ is philosophically impossible, while Jesus as the unique cipher can talk to us” (Jaspers 2016b, p. 226). Or, in other words: “Jesus as chiffer or Jesus Christus as the living God, this is to be decided” (Jaspers 2016b, p. 227). |
34 | “The richness of the world of the cipher, which is present in great poetry, art, speculative philosophy, myths and revelations” (Jaspers 2016b, p. 155). |
35 | “If revelation is no longer regarded as reality, but as a chiffer itself, then it is no longer qualitatively singled out from the chiffer world as a whole. It would be the chiffer that would allow man’s boundless longing for God himself to be actually present to be considered fulfilled for a moment, only to immediately recede into the harshness and greatness of his created freedom, for which God remains inexorably hidden” (Jaspers 2016a, p. 69). |
36 | “The subject of thought could also originate from matter” (Henrich 1960, p. 111). |
37 | “The fact that there is the unconditioned claim as the ground of action is not the matter of knowledge but the matter of faith” (Jaspers 2017, p. 31). |
38 | “The depth of death means that its strangeness falls, that I can return to it as my foundation and that I find consummation in it in an incomprehensible way. Death was less than life and required bravery. Now it is more than life and provides refuge” (Jaspers 1994, p. 58). |
39 | “Kommunikation von Mensch zu Mensch in liebendem Kampfe wagen…” (Jaspers 2015, p. 14). |
40 | This is the standpoint of Ricoeur (1995, p. 228), who talks of “mutual embracing”. |
References
- Beck, Lewis W. 1960. A Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Czakó, István. 2020. “The Last Kantian”: Outlines of Karl Jaspers’s Ambivalent Reception of German Idealism. In The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism and Existentialism. Edited by Jon Stewart. Cham: Palgrave, pp. 305–37. [Google Scholar]
- Descartes, René. 1996. Meditations on First Philosophy with Selections from the Objections and Replies. Edited and Translated by John Cottingham. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2019. Auch eine Geschichte der Philosophie. Vernünftige Freiheit. Spuren des Diskurses über Glauben und Wissen. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. [Google Scholar]
- Hare, John. 2000. Kant on Recognizing our Duties as God‘s Commands. Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers 17: 459–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Heidegger, Martin, and Karl Jaspers. 1990. Martin Heidegger—Karl Jaspers. Briefwechsel 1920–1963. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann. [Google Scholar]
- Henrich, Dieter. 1960. Der Begriff der sittlichen Einsicht und Kants Lehre vom Faktum der Vernunft. In Die Gegenwart der Griechen im neueren Denken. Festschrift für Hans-Georg Gadamer zum 60. Geburtstag. Edited by Dieter Henrich, Walter Schulz and Karl-Heinz Volkmann-Schluck. Stuttgart: J.C.B. Mohr, pp. 77–116. [Google Scholar]
- Holz, Harald. 1977. Philosophischer Glaube und Intersubjektivität. Zum Glaubensproblem bei I. Kant und K. Jaspers. Kant-Studien 68: 404–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Höffe, Otfried. 2010. Einführung in Kants Religionsschrift. In I. Kant. Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der bloßen Vernunft. Edited by Otfried Höffe. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, pp. 1–28. [Google Scholar]
- Jaspers, Karl. 1957. Drei Gründer des Philosophierens: Plato–Augustin–Kant. München: Piper. [Google Scholar]
- Jaspers, Karl. 1991. Von der Wahrheit. München: Piper. [Google Scholar]
- Jaspers, Karl. 1994. Philosophie, I: Philosophische Weltorientierung. München: Piper. [Google Scholar]
- Jaspers, Karl. 2013. Notizen zu Martin Heidegger. München: Piper. [Google Scholar]
- Jaspers, Karl. 2015. Einführung in die Philosophie. München: Piper. [Google Scholar]
- Jaspers, Karl. 2016a. Der philosophische Glaube angesichts der Christlichen Offenbarung. In Karl Jaspers Gesamtausgabe, Band I/13. Basel: Schwabe. [Google Scholar]
- Jaspers, Karl. 2016b. Der philosophische Glaube angesichts der Offenbarung. In Karl Jaspers Gesamtausgabe, Band I/13. Basel: Schwabe. [Google Scholar]
- Jaspers, Karl. 2017. Der philosophische Glaube. München: Piper. [Google Scholar]
- Ludwig, Bernd. 2020. Aufklärung über die Sittlichkeit. Zu Kants Grundlegung einer Metaphysik der Sitten. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann. [Google Scholar]
- Olson, Alan M. 1979. Transcendence and Hermeneutics. An Interpretation of the Philosophy of Karl Jaspers. The Hague and Boston: M. Nijhoff. [Google Scholar]
- Perrier, Raymond E. 2021. Kant’s religious ethics: The ineluctable link between morality and theism. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 89: 3–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ricoeur, Paul. 1995. La critique et la conviction. Paris: Calmann-Lévy. [Google Scholar]
- Rovira, Rogelio. 2023. The two parts of Kant’s moral religion. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 94: 115–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sirovátka, Jakub. 2019. Ethik und Religion bei Immanuel Kant. Versuch einer Verhälnisbestimmung. München: Alber. [Google Scholar]
- Wautischer, Helmut, Alan M. Olson, and Gregory J. Walters, eds. 2012. Philosophical Faith and the Future of Humanity. Dordrecht: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Wernicki, Nicholas. J. 2018. Jaspers’s Philosophical Faith. In The Routledge Handbook of Religious Naturalism. Edited by Donald A. Crosby and Jerome A. Stone. London: Routledge, pp. 80–92. [Google Scholar]
- Wildermuth, Armin E. 2007. Karl Jaspers and the Concept of Philosophical Faith. Existenz: An International Journal in Philosophy, Religion, Politics, and the Arts 2: 7–18. [Google Scholar]
- Wood, Allen W. 1996. General introduction. In Immanuel Kant: Religion and Rational Theology (xi–xxiv). Edited by Allen W. Wood and George di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Sikora, O. The Middle Path of Rational Faith: Jaspers and Kant. Religions 2025, 16, 1275. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16101275
Sikora O. The Middle Path of Rational Faith: Jaspers and Kant. Religions. 2025; 16(10):1275. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16101275
Chicago/Turabian StyleSikora, Ondřej. 2025. "The Middle Path of Rational Faith: Jaspers and Kant" Religions 16, no. 10: 1275. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16101275
APA StyleSikora, O. (2025). The Middle Path of Rational Faith: Jaspers and Kant. Religions, 16(10), 1275. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16101275