On Proofs for the Existence of God: Aristotle, Avicenna, and Thomas Aquinas
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Aristotle’s Cosmological Proof for the First Mover
3. Avicenna’s Metaphysical Proof for Necessary Existence in Itself
4. Thomas Aquinas’s Cosmological Proof for the Existence of God
5. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | |
2 | In many places (Metaph. B1, 995b13-15, 995b31-36; B2, 997a34-b3; Z2, 1028b27-32; M1, 1076a10-13), Aristotle asks whether there is a kind of substance other than sensible substance, i.e., intelligible substance. He rejects two possible answers by criticizing Plato’s ideas and classifying mathematical entities as quantities. The only intelligible substance that Aristotle truly recognizes is God. I will explain this point in due course. |
3 | Aristotle, Metaph. E1, 1026a27-29; K7, 1064b9-11; PA A1, 641a34-36. |
4 | Aristotle, Metaph. Ε1, 1026a29-31; Z11, 1037a13-17; K7, 1064b11-14; M1, 1076a8-15; Phys. B2, 194b9-15; PA A1, 641a36-b4. |
5 | Aristotle, Metaph. Λ1, 1069a36-b2; Λ10, 1075b130-14; K2, 1060a27-31. |
6 | In Metaph. Λ1, 1069a30-36, Aristotle speaks of the three kinds of substances (οὐσίαι δὲ τρεῖς, 1069a30), natural things, heavenly bodies, and God. Aristotle is precise and correct in stating that natural things such as (human beings), animals, and plants are sensible and perishable substances (1069a30-32). However, the (four) elements appear in place of the heavenly bodies, representing sensible and imperishable substances (1069a32-33), and the ideas and mathematical entities appear in place of God, representing intelligible and immovable substances (1069a33-36). According to Aristotle’s doctrine of categories, mathematical entities are not substances, but belong to the category of quantity. Aristotle sharply criticizes Plato’s ideas and does not recognize them as substances. Although they are intelligible and immovable, Plato’s ideas and mathematical entities are not substances in the Aristotelian sense, so they should not appear here. Although he recognizes the four elements as substances in On Generation and Corruption, Aristotle does not discuss them in Metaphysics Λ, so they should not appear here. In this case, one might ask why Aristotle mentions the elements in Λ1, which he does not discuss here, and speaks of Plato’s ideas and mathematical entities, which he does not consider substances. I suppose that Aristotle introduces these into his discussion of substances because he uses the doxographical method. In order to express his own doctrine, Aristotle presents the doctrine proposed by pre-Aristotelian philosophers and argues with them. To present the doctrine of the four causes, in Metaph. A, Aristotle goes through all the pre-Socratics, Socrates and Plato, who discuss the related issues. Similarly, in Metaph. Λ, Aristotle refers to the pre-Aristotelian doctrines of substances, although he disagrees with some of them, in order to present his own doctrine of substances. After introducing the three kinds of substances in Λ1, Aristotle discusses them one by one. He presents natural things as sensible and perishable substances in Λ2-5, heavenly bodies as sensible and imperishable substances in Λ6-8, and God as intelligent and immovable substance in Λ6-9. In particular, in Λ6-8 Aristotle presents God as the First Unmoved Mover by relating Him to the moved heavenly bodies, and in Λ9 he presents God as a purely intelligent entity. Finally, Aristotle summarizes the relationships among these three kinds of substances in Λ10. Thus, in terms of the overall structure and content of Book Λ, Aristotle discusses the three kinds of substances: natural things, heavenly bodies, and God. For Aristotle’s discussion of these three substances, see also Liu (2019, pp. 24–25). |
7 | |
8 | Scholars have vigorously debated whether Aristotle’s metaphysics is metaphysica generalis (i.e., ontology), metaphysica specialis (i.e., theology), or both, and I will not enter into that discussion here. Instead, I offer an alternative interpretation by suggesting that Aristotle constructs metaphysics as ousiology and aitiology. For a detailed discussion of how Aristotle constructs ousiology and aitiology and how he deals with the relationship between them, see Liu (2019, pp.1–33). |
9 | See also Aristotle, Phys. A1, 184a18-21; A5, 188b30-33, 189a4-9; APo. A1, 71b33-72a5; De An. B2, 413a11-13; Metaph. Δ11, 1018b29-34; Z3, 1029b3-12; NE A2, 1095a30-b4. See also Liu (2019, p. 26, n. 34). |
10 | Scholars disagree on the number of heavenly bodies Aristotle mentions in Metaph. Λ8, 1073b17-1074a14. Ross (1924, p. 392) thinks there are fifty-five heavenly bodies, while Cohen and Reeve (2020, p. 22) think there are ninety-four. I will not enter into this discussion here, because what is important for the cosmological proof is that there are many heavenly bodies, not one, and that there are finitely many, not infinitely many. |
11 | See also Aristotle, Phys. Θ5, 256a13-14; H1, 242a49-50. |
12 | Aristotle believes that the heavenly bodies cannot interact with each other because, in my interpretation, Aristotle sees the heavenly bodies as material entities that cannot actively move themselves or anything else without an external efficient cause. |
13 | Aristotle, Metaph. Λ7, 1072a24-26; Phys. Θ5, 256a4-21; H1, 242a49-66. |
14 | Alexander, Alexandri In Metaphysica Commentaria 686. 2–16. |
15 | Enrico (2001, p. 202): “Furthermore, says Theophrastus, if heaven is living like other living beings, its movement could be explained by the action of its soul, and would not need any unmovable mover.” |
16 | Aristotle, Metaph. Λ8, 1074a36-37; Phys. Θ5, 256a13-21; H1, 242a49-55. |
17 | For a detailed reconstruction of Aristotle’s cosmological proof and a detailed discussion of two assumptions of this proof, see Liu (2019, pp. 275–82). |
18 | See also Aristotle, Metaph. Λ7, 1072b18-30; Λ9, 1074b38-1075a10. |
19 | God constantly realizes Himself throughout eternity by driving the heavenly bodies in an eternal circular motion. The circular motion of the heavenly bodies, especially the motion of the sun around the earth, affects the creation and destruction of all natural things in the sublunar world. According to Aristotle’s “geocentric theory”, human beings, plants, and animals are created when the sun reaches its perigee; they are destroyed when the sun reaches its apogee. For a detailed discussion of how the three kinds of substances, that is, God, heavenly bodies, and natural things, are related to each other, see Aristotle, Metaph. Λ10, 1075a11-25; Liu (2019, pp. 287–91). |
20 | According to the traditional interpretation, Avicenna provides a proof of God’s existence in Ilāhīyyāt I.6-7. Some scholars question the traditional interpretation and suggest that Avicenna does not prove God’s existence until Ilāhīyyāt VIII.1-3 (Davidson 1987; Bertolacci 2007; De Haan 2013, 2016). |
21 | Some scholars see Avicenna’s proof as cosmological (Davidson 1987; Chignell and Pereboom 2020), while others see it as metaphysical (Marmura 1980; Lasica 2019). |
22 | I use the terms “metaphysical” and “ontological” as synonyms for the proof of God’s existence. While some scholars (Mayer 2001; Lasica 2019) characterize Avicenna’s proof as ontological, I prefer to present it as metaphysical, so that Avicenna’s metaphysical proof is not confused with Anselm’s ontological proof. |
23 | Avicenna, Commentaire sur le livre Lambda de la Metaphysique d’ Aristote (chapitres 6–10), (2014, pp. 48–49); Gutas (2014, p. 199). |
24 | Honnefelder (1987, p. 168): “Was Metaphysik von Gott erkennen kann, vermag sie nach Aristoteles nur im Ausgang von den Wirkungen zu erkennen. Ein solcher Leitfaden erlaubt aber nur eine Erkenntnis Gottes per accidens.” |
25 | Aristotle, APo. A6, 74b5-12, 75a12-14, 75a28-31; A7, 75a38-b6; A8, 75b21-24; A9, 76a4-15; A10, 76b11-16. |
26 | Avicenna, Ilāhīyyāt I.5, p. 22, lines 19-22. I refer to Marmura’s and Bertolacci’s translation with slight modification. |
27 | Avicenna, Ilāhīyyāt I.5, p. 22, lines 19-22; p. 23, lines 15–17; see also Bertolacci (2008, p. 36, n. 18). |
28 | Bertolacci (2006, p. 155): “As the fact of occurring at the very beginning of the Ilāhīyyāt witnesses, the articulation of Ontology constitutes, according to Avicenna, the main axis of metaphysics.” |
29 | In the proemium of his commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Aquinas defines metaphysics from three perspectives and gives it three names. Metaphysics is called first philosophy, which examines the primary causes of things; metaphysics is also called divine science or theology, which examines the intelligent being, completely separated from matter, both in reality and in the mind; and metaphysics is finally called transphysics, which examines the universal principles, being and its essential properties, such as one–many and potency–actualization (Metaphysica, inquantum considerat ens et ea quae consequuntur ipsum. Haec enim transphysica inveniuntur in via resolutionis, sicut magis communia post minus communia. [...] Unde et illa scientia maxime est intellectualis, quae circa principia maxime universalia versatur. Quae quidem sunt ens, et ea quae consequuntur ens, ut unum et multa, potentia et actus). In my opinion, Aquinas inherits the ontological conception of metaphysics from Avicenna, while he inherits the theological and aitiological conceptions of metaphysics from Aristotle. |
30 | Aristotle, APo. A4, 73b16-21; A10, 76b3-16; Avicenna, Ilāhīyyāt I.3; Bertolacci (2006, pp. 213–30; 2007, pp. 65–73). |
31 | Bertolacci (2008, pp. 48–49) does not call Avicenna’s division diairesis, and I interpret his description and summary of Avicenna’s division as diairesis. |
32 | According to the recent research, there is ample evidence that Avicenna not only recognizes cross-division but also applies it on a wide scale. Lammer has astutely noted that in the Physics of the Healing (al-Samā’al-ṭabī’ī, 2009, p. 39), Avicenna classifies power (quwwa, potentia, δύναμις) into four types (Lammer 2018, pp. 290–99, 306). I believe that Avicenna establishes the fourfold classification by means of cross-division. Avicenna constructs the cross-division by cross-combining the two pairs of attributes, i.e., single function–multiple function and without volition–with volition, with each other. The cross-combination of the two pairs of attributes results in the four pairs of combinations that characterize four kinds of things endowed with a certain power: the natural thing is single-function and acts without volition, the celestial soul is single-function and acts with volition, the vegetative soul is multifunction and acts without volition, and the animal soul is multifunction and acts with volition. I would also note that Lammer has also mentioned another cross-division made by Themistius, Philoponus, and al-Fārābī, such that the two pairs of attributes, i.e., relative–absolute and hypothesis–postulate, are cross-combined. In this way, the fourfold classification is established: relative hypotheses, relative postulates, absolute hypotheses, and absolute postulates (Lammer 2018, pp. 88–91). Moreover, I observe that in Ilāhīyyāt I.2, Avicenna uses cross-division to divide mathematics into four subdisciplines and the subject of mathematics into four kinds. The subject of mathematics, quantity, is divided into two parallel pairs, continuous–discrete and abstraction from matter–existence in matter, and the two pairs are cross-combined, thus forming a cross-division that establishes four pairs of combinations that characterize four kinds of quantity. Through this cross-division, quantity, the subject of mathematics, is divided into four kinds, and accordingly, mathematics is divided into four subdisciplines as follows. Geometry studies the quantity that is continuous and abstract from matter (i.e., lines, surfaces, and bodies); astronomy studies the quantity that is continuous and exists in matter (i.e., heavenly bodies); arithmetic studies the quantity that is discrete and abstract from matter (i.e., numbers); and music studies the quantity that is discrete and exists in matter (i.e., notes). Based on what has been said, it is reasonable to assume that in Ilāhīyyāt I.6, Avicenna uses cross-division to make a fourfold classification of existent. Notably, Avicenna did not invent cross-division. Plato and Aristotle used cross-division extensively; in his commentary on Aristotle’s Categories, Porphyry notes Aristotle’s use of cross-division and calls it chiasmus (χιαστή). See Porphyry (1887) Porphyrii Isagoge et In Aristotelis Categorias Commentarium, 78.34-79.11; Liu (2019, pp. 15–18, n. 16, n. 17, n. 18). For Plato’s and Aristotle’s use of chiasmus and a detailed discussion of the difference between chiasmus and diairesis, see Liu (2021). |
33 | Some scholars claim that Avicenna inaugurated the second beginning of metaphysics by reconstructing metaphysics, although they disagree on how Avicenna made a new beginning for metaphysics. See Verbeke (1983, p. 10, 23), Bertolacci (2007, p. 73) and Aertsen (2012, p. 75). |
34 | Bertolacci (2007, p. 64): “Avicenna defends (...) that metaphysics can have a theological goal precisely because it has an ontological starting point”. |
35 | Kenny, Shields, and Pasnau suggest that Aquinas uses movetur in both intransitive and passive senses; MacDonald, Wippel, and Pawl read movetur only in the passive sense. See Kenny (1969, pp. 8–9), MacDonald (1991, pp. 121–24), Wippel (2000, pp. 414–15, 444), Pawl (2012, pp. 116–17, 127, n. 18) and Shields and Pasnau (2016, pp. 107–14). |
36 | In Greek, however, κινεῖσθαι can also be used in the sense of a medium. Notably, Aristotle claims not that something moved must be moved by something else (ab alio) but rather that something moved must be moved by something (ὑπό τινος). Although Aristotle’s aim is to infer an external mover from the moved heavenly bodies, his formulation and the possible use of κινεῖσθαι in the sense of medium indicate that Aristotle does not completely exclude the internal efficient cause and emphasize the external efficient cause, as Aquinas does. Thus, there is a slight difference between Aquinas’s imitation and Aristotle’s original formulation, although this difference does not affect the argument. |
37 | Thanks to one of the anonymous reviewers who mentions Aristotle’s definition of motion. From this perspective, the matter is more clearly illuminated. Aristotle defines motion as the actualization of what exists potentially, insofar as it exists potentially (Phys. Γ1, 201a10-11). In other words, motion is defined as the process from potentiality to actuality. At the beginning, the thing exists in potentiality, and motion does not begin; at the end, the thing achieves its goal and exists in actuality, and motion ends. Movement is neither beginning nor end, neither potentiality nor actuality, but the process from beginning to end and from potentiality to actuality. From the perspective of movement, it is illuminating that potentiality and actuality cannot coexist simultaneously. According to Aristotle, however, not only can moving and being moved coexist, but they must operate simultaneously for movement to occur (Phys. Γ3, 202a21-b5). For example, the moving hand and the moved stick operate simultaneously to lift the stick. The same reasoning applies to the movement of animals: the moving soul and the moved body work simultaneously for a human being to act. When there is movement, the moving and the moved work together at the same time. Therefore, I think the two sets, potentiality–actuality and moving–being moved, cannot be confused with each other. |
38 | In my opinion, the argument proposed by Aquinas in the SCG I, c. 13 bears much resemblance to the argument established by Proclus in the Elements of Theology (abbreviated ET). In the seventeenth proposition, Proclus argues, “But if the mover is one part and the moved another, the whole will not in itself be self-moved, since it will be composed of parts that are not self-moved: it will have the appearance of being self-moved, but in essence it will not be so” (ET, Prop. 17. lines 5-8). I have slightly modified Dodd’s translation. |
39 | Aristotle, Metaph. Λ3, 1070a7-8; Phys. B1, 192b8-15, 27–30. |
40 | Accordingly, in explaining the four causes, Aquinas regards the material and formal causes as internal, while he treats the efficient and final causes as external; see De principii naturae c. 3 (1999, p. 60): Causas autem accipit tam pro extrinsecis quam pro intrinsecis: Materia et forma dicuntur intrinsecae rei, eo quod sunt partes constituentes rem; efficiens et finalis dicuntur extrinsecae, quia sunt extra rem. |
41 | Gilson (1957, pp. 66–68; 2002, p. 64) emphasizes that in the second way, Aquinas places the hierarchical, vertical structure among the efficient causes in order to avoid infinite regression. Gilson (2002, p. 74) further asserts that “all the proofs presume that the causes and effects appearing in them are arranged hierarchically”. Pasnau takes up this idea by claiming that in each of the five ways, Aquinas replaces the infinite horizontal series of causes going back in time with a vertical series, thus ending the infinite regression. See Shields and Pasnau (2016, p. 112) and Pasnau (2022, p. 5). |
42 | Pawl (2012, p. 122) also questions the validity of this deduction. |
43 | In explaining that the truest being is the Supreme Being, scholars carefully distinguish between logical truth and ontological truth (what Shields and Pasnau call the “ontic conception/sense of truth”), correctly noting that Aquinas uses “truth” not in the logical sense (e.g., a true proposition) but in the ontological sense (i.e., truth refers to reality). See Wippel (2000, p. 471), Pawl (2012, p. 124) and Shields and Pasnau (2016, pp. 116–17). |
44 | Pawl, Shields, and Pasnau interpret Aquinas’s dictum literally, suggesting that Aquinas is appealing to Aristotle, as he claims in the fourth way; see Pawl (2012, p. 124) and Shields and Pasnau (2016, pp. 114–15). |
45 | Plato, Soph. 254b-260a. |
46 | Plato, Resp. 595c-597e; Tim. 27c-31b, 39e-40d. |
47 | See (O’Rourke 1971) “Via causalitatis; via negationis; via eminentiae (Weg der Ursächlichkeit; Weg der Negation; Weg des Übermaßes)”, in Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, pp. 1034–38. |
48 | See also Proclus, ET, Prop. 8. lines 3-4: “If all beings desire the Good, it is evident that the First Good transcends [all] beings” (εἰ γὰρ πάντα τὰ ὄντα τοῦ ἀγαθοῦ ἐφίεται, δῆλον ὅτι τὸ πρώτως ἀγαθὸν ἐπέκεινά ἐστι τῶν ὄντων). I have slightly modified Dodds’s translation. |
49 | To track down Aquinas’s resources for constructing the fourth way, I make a strict distinction between Platonism and Neoplatonism, the distinction between via eminentiae and via negationis, and carefully emphasize that here, in the fourth way, Aquinas takes the via eminentiae by following Platonism. Influenced by Pseudo-Dionysius, Aquinas generally uses not only the positive way but also the negative way to characterize God. Thanks to the anonymous reviewer for reminding me of this point. |
50 | MacDonald (1991) focuses on the first way, Shields and Pasnau (2016) on the first and fourth ways. According to Wippel and Pawl, many scholars focus on the third way; see Wippel (2000, pp. 462–63, n. 52, 464, n. 57, 465, n. 60, n. 61, 466, n. 63, 466–67, n. 64) and Pawl (2012, p. 130, n. 49). |
51 | In the sixth and final edition and translation of Le Thomisme, Gilson (2002, p. 74) summarizes the last two features common to the five ways as one characteristic by stating that “a second characteristic is that all the proofs presume that the causes and effects appearing in them are arranged hierarchically”. In other words, the second common feature is both causality and the hierarchical order between cause and effect. Gilson (2002, pp. 74–75) emphasizes the hierarchical order between cause and effect because only the hierarchy can end the infinite regression. |
52 | Aquinas not only emphasizes causality, i.e., the causal relationship between the Creator and the creatures, in the five-way proof, he also emphasizes it from other perspectives. Since the Creator absolutely transcends and completely dominates the creatures, the causal relationship between them is asymmetrical, irreversible, and creationist. To express the causal relationship between the Creator and creatures in this sense, Aquinas uses the analogy of attribution in such a way that the same predicate “good” is said of God and creatures, such as “God is good” and “creatures are good”. The predicate “good” is not used univocally because God is essentially different from creatures; nor is it used purely equivocally because, by creating them, God is closely related to creatures. Since God is both essentially different from and causally related to creatures, the relationship between God and creatures can be adequately expressed only with the analogy of attribution, and “good” is thus used analogically. Within the analogy of attribution, Aquinas distinguishes between the analogy of many-to-one and the analogy of one-to-another, with the latter characterizing the relationship of creatures to God; e.g., the goodness of creatures is caused by and oriented toward the absolute goodness of God. Aquinas also characterizes this kind of relationship with participation, according to which creatures are good because they participate in the absolute goodness of God. Creatures can participate in any property of God because God has made it all possible. In order to accurately and properly characterize the causal relationship in the creationist sense between the Creator and creatures, Aquinas introduces participation and the analogy of attribution. Thus, as we have seen, many of Aquinas’s important metaphysical considerations, such as participation, analogy, and the five-way proof of God’s existence, revolve around causality in the creationist sense between the Creator and the creatures. On Aquinas’s analogy, see De potentia q. 7, a. 7; SCG I, c. 29-36.; ST I, q. 13, a. 5-6. For an interpretation of Aquinas’s analogy, see Montagnes ([1963] 2004), McInerny (1996), Pannenberg (2007), Wippel (2000), Aertsen (2012), Spencer (2015), and Hochschild (2019). |
References
Primary Source
(Aquinas ST I, q. 2, a. 3) Aquinas, Thomas. 1888a. Summa Theologiae I, q. 2, a. 3. Available online: https://www.corpusthomisticum.org/sth1002.html (accessed on 25 November 2023).(Aquinas ST I, q. 13, a. 5-6) Aquinas, Thomas. 1888b. Summa Theologiae I, q. 13, a. 5-6. Available online: https://www.corpusthomisticum.org/sth1003.html (accessed on 3 May 2023).(Aquinas Sententia Libri Metaphysicae) Aquinas, Thomas. 1950. Commentaria in Aristotelem: Sententia Libri Metaphysicae. Available online: http://www.corpusthomisticum.org/cmp00.html (accessed on 20 December 2023).(Aquinas De potentia q. 7, a. 7) Aquinas, Thomas. 1953. De potentia q. 7, a. 7. Available online: https://www.corpusthomisticum.org/qdp7.html (accessed on 3 May 2023).(Aquinas SCG I, c. 13) Aquinas, Thomas. 1961a. Summa Contra Gentiles I, c. 13. Available online: https://www.corpusthomisticum.org/scg1010.html (accessed on 25 November 2023).(Aquinas SCG I, c. 29-36) Aquinas, Thomas. 1961b. Summa Contra Gentiles I, c. 29-36. Available online: https://www.corpusthomisticum.org/scg1029.html (accessed on 3 May 2023).(Aquinas 1996) Aquinas, Thomas. 1996. Die Gottesbeweise in der Summe gegen die Heiden und der Summe der Theologie. Translated by Horst Seidl. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.(Aquinas 1999) Aquinas, Thomas. 1999. De Principiis Naturae. Translated by Richard Heinzmann. Stuttgart: W. Kohlhammer.(Aquinas 2014) Aquinas, Thomas. 2014. Prologe zu den Aristoteles-Kommentaren. Edited and Translated by Francis Cheneval und Ruedi Imbach. Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.(Aristotle NE) Aristotle. 1894. Ethica Nicomachea. Edited by Ingram Bywater. Oxford: Oxford University Press.(Aristotle Cat.) Aristotle. 1949. Categoriae et Liber de Interpretatione. Edited by L. Minio-Paluello. Oxford: Oxford University Press.(Aristotle Phys.) Aristotle. 1950. Physica. Edited by William David Ross. Oxford: Oxford University Press.(Aristotle PA) Aristotle. 1956a. De Partibus Animalium. Edited and Translated by Pierre Louis. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.(Aristotle De An.) Aristotle. 1956b. De Anima. Edited by William David Ross. Oxford: Oxford University Press.(Aristotle Metaph. ) Aristotle. 1957. Metaphysica. Edited by Werner Jäger. Oxford: Oxford University Press.(Aristotle APr., APo.) Aristotle. 1964. Analytica Prioria et Posterioria. Edited by William David Ross and L. Minio-Paluello. Oxford: Oxford University Press.(Aristotle De gen et corr. ) Aristotle. 2011. De Generatione et Corruptione. Edited and Translated by Thomas Buchheim. Hamburg: Meiner Verlag.(Avicenna Ilāhīyyāt) Avicenna. 2005. The Metaphysics of The Healing (al-Šifāʾ: Ilāhīyyāt). Translated by Michael E. Marmura. Provo/Utah: Brigham Young University Press.(Avicenna Al-Samā’ al-ṭabī’ī) Avicenna. 2009. The Physics of The Healing (al-Šifāʾ: Al-Samā’ al-ṭabī’ī) Books I & II. Translated by Jon McGinnis. Provo/Utah: Brigham Young University Press.(Plato Resp.) Plato. 1978. Respublica. Edited by John Burnet. Oxford: Oxford University Press.(Plato Soph.) Plato. 1995. Sophista. Edited by E. A. Duke, W. F. Hicken, W. S. M. Nicoll, D. B. Robinson and J. C. G. Strachan. Oxford: Oxford University Press.(Plato Resp.) Plato. 2011a. Politeia. Translated by Friedrich Schleiermacher. Darmstadt: WBG.(Plato Tim.) Plato. 2011b. Timaios. Translated by Hieronymus Müller and Friedrich Schleiermacher. Darmstadt: WBG.(Plotinus Enneades) Plotinus. 1977. Plotini Opera II: Enneades IV–V. Edited by Paul Henry and Hans-Rudolph Schwyzer. Oxford: Oxford University Press.(Proclus ET) Proclus. 1963. The Elements of Theology. Edited and Translated by Eric Robertson Dodds. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.Secondary Source
- Adamson, Peter. 2013. From the Necessary Existent to God. In Interpreting Avicenna Critical Essays. Edited by Peter Adamson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 170–89. [Google Scholar]
- Aertsen, Jan. 2012. Medieval Philosophy as Transcendental Thought: From Philip the Chancellor (ca.1225) to Francisco Suárez. Leiden/Boston: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Alexander, Aphrodisiensis. 1891. Alexandri Aphrodisiensis in Aristotelis Metaphysica Commentaria. Edited by Michael Hayduck. Berlin: Reimer. [Google Scholar]
- Aubenque, Pierre. 1978. Les Origines de la Doctrine de L’analogie de l’être: Sur L’histoire D’un Contresens. Les Études Philosophiques 1: 3–12. [Google Scholar]
- Aubenque, Pierre. 1986. The Origins of the Doctrine of the Analogy of Being: On the History of a Misunderstanding. Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 11: 35–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Avicenna. 2014. Commentaire sur le Livre Lambda de la Metaphysique d’ Aristote (Chapitres 6–10). Translated and Edited by Marc Geoffroy, Jules Jenssens, and Meryem Sebti. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin. [Google Scholar]
- Bertolacci, Amos. 2006. The Reception of Aristotle’s Metaphysics in Avicenna’s Kitāb al-Šifāʾ. A Milestone of Western Metaphysical Thought. Leiden/Boston: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Bertolacci, Amos. 2007. Avicenna and Averroes on the Proof of God’s Existence and the Subject-Matter of Metaphysics. Medioevo 32: 61–97. [Google Scholar]
- Bertolacci, Amos. 2008. «Necessary» as Primary Concept in Avicenna’s Metaphysics. In Conoscenza e Contingenza Nella Tradizione Aristotelica Medieval. Edited by S. Perfetti. Pisa: ETS, pp. 31–50. [Google Scholar]
- Chignell, Andrew, and Derk Pereboom. 2020. Natural Theology and Natural Religion. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/natural-theology/ (accessed on 20 December 2023).
- Cohen, S. Marc, and Charles D. C. Reeve. 2020. Aristotle’s Metaphysics. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/ (accessed on 5 November 2023).
- Davidson, Herbert Alan. 1987. Proofs for Eternity, Creation, and the Existence of God in Medieval Islamic and Jewish Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- De Haan, Daniel D. 2013. Why the Five Ways? Aquinas’s Avicennian Insight into the Problem of Unity in the Aristotelian Metaphysics and Sacra Doctrina. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 86: 141–58. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Haan, Daniel D. 2016. Where Does Avicenna Demonstrate the Existence of God? Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 26: 97–128. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Haan, Daniel D. 2020. Necessary Existence and the Doctrine of Being in Avicenna‘s Metaphysics of the Healing. Leiden/Boston: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Enrico, Berti. 2001. Unmoved Mover(s) as Efficient Cause(s) in Metaphysics Λ6. In Symposium Aristotelicum: Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda. Edited by Michael Frede and David Charles. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 181–206. [Google Scholar]
- Gilson, Etienne. 1957. The Christian Philosophy of ST. Thomas Aquinas. Translated by Laurence K. Shook. London: Victor Gollancz LTD. [Google Scholar]
- Gilson, Etienne. 2002. Thomism. The Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas. A translation of Le Thomisme, sixth and final edition by Laurence K. Shook and Armand Maurer. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies. [Google Scholar]
- Gutas, Dimitri. 2014. Avicenna and the Aristotelian Tradition. Introduction to Reading Avicenna’s Philosophical Works. Leiden/Boston: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Hochschild, Joshua P. 2019. Aquinas’s Two Concepts of Analogy and a Complex Semantics for Naming the Simple God. The Thomist: A Speculative Quarterly Review 83: 155–84. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Honnefelder, Ludger. 1987. Der Zweite Anfang der Metaphysik Voraussetzungen, Ansätze und Folgen der Wiederbegründung der Metaphysik im 13./14. Jahrhundert. In Philosophie im Mittelalter Entwicklungslinien und Paradigmen. Edited by Jan P. Beckmann, Ludger Honnefelder, Gangolf Schrimpf and Georg Wieland. Hamburg: Meiner, pp. 165–86. [Google Scholar]
- Kenny, Anthony. 1969. The Five Ways: St Thomas Aquinas’ Proofs of God’s Existence. London/New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Lammer, Andreas. 2018. The Elements of Avicenna’s Physics: Greek Sources and Arabic Innovation. Boston/Berlin: De Gruyter. [Google Scholar]
- Lasica, Vladimir. 2019. Avicenna’s Proof for God’s Existence: The Proof from Ontological Considerations. Revista Española de Filosofía Medieval 26: 25–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Liu, Xin. 2019. Sein, Logos und Veränderung—Eine systematische Untersuchung zu Aristoteles’ Metaphysik. Berlin/Boston: De Gruyter. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Xin. 2021. On Diairesis, Parallel Division, and Chiasmus: Plato’s and Aristotle’s Methods of Division. Plato Journal 22: 27–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- MacDonald, Scott. 1991. Aquinas’s Parasitic Cosmological Argument. Journal of Nietzsche Studies 1: 119–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Marmura, Michael E. 1980. Avicenna’s Proof from Contingency for God’s Existence in the Metaphysics of the Shifā’. Mediaeval Studies 42: 337–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Martin, Christopher F. J. 1997. Thomas Aquinas God and Explanations. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mayer, Toby. 2001. Ibn Sina’s ‘Burhan Al-Siddiqin’. Journal of Islamic Studies 12: 18–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McInerny, Ralph. 1996. Aquinas and Analogy. Washington: Universidad de Navarra. [Google Scholar]
- Menn, Stephen. 2013. Avicenna’s Metaphysics. In Interpreting Avicenna Critical Essays. Edited by Peter Adamson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 143–69. [Google Scholar]
- Montagnes, Bernard. 2004. The Doctrine of the Analogy of Being According to Thomas Aquinas. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. First published 1963. [Google Scholar]
- O’Rourke, F. 1971. Via causalitatis; via negationis; via eminentiae. In Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie 1971–2007. Edited by Joachim Ritter, Karlfried Gründer and Gottfried Gabriel. Basel: Schwabe Verlag, pp. 1034–38. [Google Scholar]
- Owen, Gwilym Ellis Lane. 1986. Logic and Metaphysics in some Earlier Works of Aristotle. In Logic, Science, and Dialectic. Edited by Martha Craven Nussbaum. Ithaca/New York: Cornell University Press, pp. 180–99. [Google Scholar]
- Pannenberg, Wolfhart. 2007. Analogie und Offenbarung. Eine kritische Untersuchung zur Geschichte des Analogiebegriffs in der Lehre von der Gotteserkenntnis. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. [Google Scholar]
- Pasnau, Robert. 2022. Thomas Aquinas. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aquinas/ (accessed on 15 December 2023).
- Pawl, Timothy. 2012. Chapter 9: The Five Ways. In The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Edited by Brian Davies and Eleonore Stump. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 115–32. [Google Scholar]
- Porphyry. 1887. Porphyrii Isagoge et In Aristotelis Categorias Commentarium. Edited by Adolf Busse. Berlin: Reimer. [Google Scholar]
- Ross, William David. 1924. Aristotle’s Metaphysics. A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary. Volumes I and II. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Shields, Christopher, and Robert Pasnau. 2016. God’s Existence and Nature. In The Philosophy of Aquinas. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 100–50. [Google Scholar]
- Spencer, Archie J. 2015. The Analogy of Faith. The Quest for God’s Speakability. Downers Gorve/Illinois: Inter Varsity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Verbeke, Gerard. 1983. Avicenna, Grundleger einer neuen Metaphysik. Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften. [Google Scholar]
- Wippel, John Francis. 2000. The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas. From Finite Being to Uncreated Being. Washington: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wisnovsky, Robert. 2003. Avicenna’s Metaphysics in Context. New York: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Liu, X. On Proofs for the Existence of God: Aristotle, Avicenna, and Thomas Aquinas. Religions 2024, 15, 235. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15020235
Liu X. On Proofs for the Existence of God: Aristotle, Avicenna, and Thomas Aquinas. Religions. 2024; 15(2):235. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15020235
Chicago/Turabian StyleLiu, Xin. 2024. "On Proofs for the Existence of God: Aristotle, Avicenna, and Thomas Aquinas" Religions 15, no. 2: 235. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15020235
APA StyleLiu, X. (2024). On Proofs for the Existence of God: Aristotle, Avicenna, and Thomas Aquinas. Religions, 15(2), 235. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15020235