Blind Man, Mirror, and Fire: Aquinas, Avicenna, and Averroes on Thinking
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Aquinas’s Critique of Falsafa
Text 1:But it is contrary to the nature (rationem) of sensible things for their forms to subsist without their matters, as Aristotle proves in a number of ways. Accordingly, Avicenna, after ruling out this view, posited not that the intelligible species of all sensible things subsist on their own without matter, but that they preexist immaterially in separated intellects. Such species are derived from the first of these separated intellects into the next one, and so on down to the final separated intellect, which he named the Agent Intellect. From this intellect, as he says, intelligible species emanate into our souls, and sensible forms into corporeal matter.10(ST, I, q.84, a.4 (144))
Text 2:It might be said, however, in line with Avicenna, that the senses are necessary to the soul because they arouse it to turn toward the Agent Intelligence, from which it receives species. But this is not adequate. For if it belongs to the soul’s nature to understand through species emanating from the Agent Intelligence, then it would follow that the soul could sometimes turn toward the Agent Intelligence out of the inclination of its own nature, or even that, aroused by one sense, It turns toward the Agent Intelligence to receive the species of sensibles belonging to a sense that the person does not have. In this way, someone born blind could have knowledge of colours, which is clearly false. Accordingly, it must be said that the intelligible species by which our soul understands do not emanate from separate forms.12(ST, I, q.84, a.4 (145–6))
Text 3:He said that the understanding of that separate substance is my understanding or that person’s understanding, in so far as that possible intellect is joined to me or to you through phantasms which are in me and in you. He said that this is accomplished in the following way. Now the intelligible species, which becomes one with the possible intellect since it is its form and act, has two subjects: one, the phantasms themselves; the other, the possible intellect. So therefore the possible intellect is in contact with us through its form by means of the phantasms; and thus, as long as the possible intellect understands, this man understands.16(DUI, c. 3, par. 63 (49))
Text 4:Unless perhaps it be said that the possible intellect is in contact with phantasms as a mirror is in contact with the man whose appearance is reflected in the mirror. But such a contact clearly does not suffice for the contact of the act. For it is clear that the action of the mirror, which is to represent, cannot on this account be attributed to the man. Whence neither can the action of the possible intellect be attributed, on account of the above-mentioned joining, to this man who is Socrates, in such a way that this man would understand.19(DUI, c. 3, par. 65 (50))
3. Abstractionism versus Emanationism
Text 5:As for the intellectual faculty (al-quwwa al-ʿaqliyya), when it reviews (aṭlaʿat) the particulars that are in the imagination, and the light of the active intellect (we discussed) sheds light upon [the particulars] in us, [the particulars] are transformed (istaḥālat) to [things] abstract (mujarrada) from matter and its accidents and are impressed upon the rational soul.(al-Nafs, 235 lines 2–5)
Text 6:So [the intellect] turns to these accidents, then extracts them (yanziʿu), as though it were (yakūnu kaʾannahu) peeling away (yuqashshiru) those accidents from it and throwing them away to one side until it arrives at the meaning (al- maʿnā) in which they participate and by which they do not differ; and then [the intellect] acquires (yuḥaṣṣilu) it and conceptualises (yataṣawwaru) it. From the first moment that [the intellect] inspects the mix in the imagination, it finds (yajidu) accidents and essential components, and of the accidents, [it finds] those that are necessary and those that are not. It separates (yufridu) the meanings from the mixed multiplicity in the imagination and takes its essence from [the mixed multiplicity].(al-Burhān, 222 lines 8–11)
4. Does Avicenna Fall Prey to the Blind Man Argument?
I1: The essence of colour is nothing but the phenomenal colour that one directly experiences in one’s colour-experiences, so the real knowing of the what-ness of a colour is not a dry conceptual belief that one can hold based on one’s colour-concepts. Instead, the direct colour-experience brings one to the thing-itself—to literally see the colour itself.I2: The essence of colour is what the intellect grasps by the concept of colour, so it is intellectual and not the qualia that one experiences. Therefore, having the conception of the essence of colour is sufficient for the knowledge of what colour is.I3: The intellect grasps the essence of colour through the concept of colour but to have a real understanding of what a colour is, one needs to properly form an explanatory connection between one’s concepts and the relevant experiences.
5. Revisiting the Unity of Intellect
Text 7:(7A) For if the thing understood in me and in you were one in every way, it would happen that when I would know some intelligible, you would also know it, and many other impossible things [would also follow]. If we assert it to be many, then it would happen that the thing understood in me and in you would be one in species and two in individual [number]. In this way the thing understood will have a thing understood and so it proceeds into infinity.(7B) Thus, it will be impossible for a student to learn from a teacher unless the knowledge which is in the teacher is a power generating and creating knowledge which is in the student, in the way in which one fire generates another fire similar to it in species, which is impossible. That what is known is the same in the teacher and the student in this way caused Plato to believe that learning is recollection.(7C) Since, then, we asserted that the intelligible thing which is in me and in you is many in subject insofar as it is true, namely, the forms of imagination, and one in the subject in virtue of which it is an existing intellect (namely, the material [intellect]), those questions are completely resolved.28(LCDA, 411.710–412.728)
The impossibility argument of knowledge transmissionP1: If the intelligible form can be individualized, then the intelligible form must become a member of a species of natural things.P2: If the intelligible form is a member of a species of natural things, then different intelligible forms cannot share the same content.P3: If different intelligible forms cannot share the same content, then teaching is impossible.P4: Teaching is possible.C1: Different intelligible forms can share the same content.C2: The intelligible form is not a member of a species of natural things.C3: The intelligible form cannot be individualized.
Text 8:The one form in the intellect is related to the many, and it is on this consideration (al-iʿtibār) a universal, it is one meaning in the intellect, whose relation to any given animal does not differ; that is, the form of any of them is present to the imagination immediately; the intellect then extracts its meaning (maʿnāhu) abstracted from accidents, [then] the form itself occurs (ḥaṣala) in the intellect. This form is the one which occurs by abstracting animality from any individual image, taken either from an external existent or from something that plays the role of an external existent even if it itself does not exist externally but [is something] the imagination invents.(al-Ilāhiyyāt, p. 156, lines 10–18)
6. Concluding Remarks
Text 9:Allāh said “I will declare war against him who shows hostility to a friend of Mine. And the most beloved things with which My servant comes nearer to Me, is what I have enjoined upon him; and My servant keeps on coming closer to Me through performing nawāfil (praying or doing extra deeds besides what is obligatory) till I love him, then I become his hearing with which he hears, and his sight with which he sees, and his hand with which he grips, and his leg with which he walks; and if he asks Me, Twill give him, and if he asks My Protection (Refuge), I will protect him (i.e., give him My Refuge); and I do not hesitate to do anything as I hesitate to take the soul of the believer, for he hates death, and I hate to disappoint him.”(al-Bukhari 1997, pp. 275–76, revised based on Khan’s translation)
Text 10:They are distinguished by their knowledge of truth before Allāh when Allāh creates in them the faculty of true knowledge of Himself. This faculty emanates from Allāh and must be attributed to Him and not to the person in whom it is endowed. The possession of this faculty marks the fullness of endeavours before God.
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Although Falsafa usually refers to philosophers who engage in philosophy in the Islamic intellectual tradition that treats Greek philosophy as paradigmatic (e.g., al-Fārābī, Avicenna, and Averroes), I use the term in this article to refer to Avicenna and Averroes. The naturalistic account of religion refers to the approach taken by the Falsafa school, which seeks to explain the nature of religion using the best available theoretical framework of its era while staying within the bounds of rationality. |
2 | For a general sketch of Al-Fārābī’s Theory of Prophecy, see (Walzer 1957). |
3 | For an overview of Al-Fārābī and Avicenna’s theory of intellect, see (Taylor 2006; Gutas 2012b). |
4 | For an overview of Averroes’s theory of intellect, see (Davidson 1992, chp. 6–8). |
5 | For a general account of Latin Averroism, see (Marenbon 2007). |
6 | For an overview of Aquinas’ critique of Averroes’ theory of intellect, see (Taylor 1999). |
7 | Texts 1 and 2 are from (Aquinas 2002). For the Latin text, see (Aquinas 1889), henceforth, ST. The page number of the English text is in brackets. |
8 | There is an ongoing debate concerning whether, for Aquinas, intellectual cognitions of material things must be mediated through the intellectual awareness of the relevant intelligible species. An affirmative answer may lead one to the so-called representationist’s reading, whereas a negative answer may lead one to a direct realist reading. In this article, I leave the question open. For a detailed examination of the debate, see (Baltuta 2013). |
9 | ST, I, q.84, a.4 (144): “Respondeo dicendum quod quidam posuerunt species intelligibiles nostri intellectus procedere ab aliquibus formis vel substantiis separatis. Et hoc dupliciter. Plato enim, sicut dictum est, posuit formas rerum sensibilium per se sine materia subsistentes; sicut formam hominis, quam nominabat per se hominem, et formam vel ideam equi, quam nominabat per se equum, et sic de aliis.” |
10 | ST, I, q.84, a.4 (144): “Sed quia contra rationem rerum sensibilium est quod earum formae subsistant absque materiis, ut Aristoteles multipliciter probat; ideo Avicenna, hac positione remota, posuit omnium rerum sensibilium intelligibiles species, non quidem per se subsistere absque materia, sed praeexistere immaterialiter in intellectibus separatis; a quorum primo derivantur huiusmodi species in sequentem, et sic de aliis usque ad ultimum intellectum separatum, quem nominat intellectum agentem; a quo, ut ipse dicit, effluunt species intelligibiles in animas nostras, et formae sensibiles in materiam corporalem.” |
11 | Note that Avicenna himself did distinguish between intelligible species and intelligible forms. Therefore, in Text 1, Aquinas’s reconstruction of Avicenna’s doctrine may not be historically accurate. In the next section, I will discuss how Aquinas’s emanationist reading of Avicenna’s theory of concept formation is currently the topic of a heated scholarly debate. |
12 | ST, I, q.84, a.4 (145–6): “Si autem dicatur, secundum Avicennam, quod sensus sunt animae necessarii, quia per eos excitatur ut convertat se ad intelligentiam agentem, a qua recipit species; hoc quidem non sufficit. Quia si in natura animae est ut intelligat per species ab intelligentia agente effluxas, sequeretur quod quandoque anima possit se convertere ad intelligentiam agentem ex inclinatione suae naturae, vel etiam excitata per alium sensum, ut convertat se ad intelligentiam agentem ad recipiendum species sensibilium quorum sensum aliquis non habet. Et sic caecus natus posset habere scientiam de coloribus, quod est manifeste falsum. Unde dicendum est quod species intelligibiles quibus anima nostra intelligit, non effluunt a formis separatis.” Note that, in this text, when Aquinas points out that, for Avicenna, the human intellect receives the species of the sensibles (species sensibilium) from the agent intellect, the species of the sensibles refer to the intelligible form of the sensible. This is because, for Avicenna, only the intelligible forms emanate from the agent intellect. |
13 | See Text 3 in Section 2. |
14 | Aquinas insightfully notes that the emphasis of the role of the senses is not essential for Avicenna’s theory of human intellection. One significant clue that justifies Aquinas’ observation is Avicenna’s well-known analogy of a horse and rider. According to Avicenna, in the process of concept acquisition, the relation between the rational soul and the senses is like that of a rider and a horse crossing a river. Once the rider successfully crosses the river, they can abandon the horse and continue their journey on their own; likewise, when the intellect first acquires the intelligible form, the intellect itself becomes more powerful, such that it can trigger the re-awareness of the same form solely through its own will without relying on the senses. For the horse–rider analogy, see (Avicenna 1985, p. 374, ll. 8–14). |
15 | Texts 3 and 4 are from (Aquinas 1968). For the Latin text, see (Aquinas 1976, pp. 289–314), henceforth, DUI, followed by the chapter and passage number in the Latin text and the page number of the English text in brackets. |
16 | DUI, c. 3, par. 63 (49): “Dixit quod intelligere illius substantiae separatae est intelligere mei vel illius, in quantum intellectus ille possibilis copulatur mihi vel tibi per phantasmata quae sunt in me et in te. Quod sic fieri dicebat. Species enim intelligibilis, quae fit unum cum intellectu possibili, cum sit forma et actus eius, habet duo subiecta: unum ipsa phantasmata, aliud intellectum possibilem. Sic ergo intellectus possibilis continuatur nobiscum per formam suam mediantibus phantasmatibus; et sic, dum intellectus possibilis intelligit, hic homo intelligit.” |
17 | For a detailed reconstruction of the two-subject theory, see (Davidson 1992, pp. 289–90). |
18 | For a detailed reconstruction of Aquinas’s different arguments against UI, see (Wu 2017). It is worth noting that, in addition to the theoretical criticisms, Aquinas also argues that UI is not a faithful reading of Aristotle himself. For the purpose of this paper, I will solely focus on the theoretical dimension of Aquinas’s critique. Whether Averroes’s theory of intellect is a faithful interpretation of Aristotle’s relevant doctrines, or whether Averroes indeed aims to present Aristotle faithfully, remains an open question. |
19 | DUI, c. 3, par. 65 (50): “Nisi forte dicatur quod intellectus possibilis continuatur phantasmatibus, sicut speculum continuatur homini cuius species resultat in speculo. Talis autem continuatio manifestum est quod non sufficit ad continuationem actus; manifestum est enim quod actio speculi, quae est repraesentare, non propter hoc potest attribui homini: unde nec actio intellectus possibilis propter praedictam copulationem posset attribui huic homini qui est Socrates, ut hic homo intelligeret.” |
20 | One might point out that, in the mirror case, we do somehow attribute the images in the mirror to the man because, if one were asked to whom the image belongs, one could say that the image belongs to the man. Nonetheless, we should make a distinction between what the image is about and what possesses the image; however, in both cases, the term “belongs to” might be used in our natural language. |
21 | Text 5 is from (Avicenna 1959), henceforth al-Nafs; Text 6 is from (Avicenna 1956), henceforth al-Burhān; and Text 8 is cited from (Avicenna 2005), henceforth al-Ilāhiyyāt. Texts 5 and 6 are my own translation; Text 8 is revised based on Marmura’s translation. |
22 | For a recent overview of the debate, see (Ogden 2020, pp. 2–7). |
23 | For the empiricist’s reading, see (Gutas 2012a, pp. 391–436). For the rationalist’s reading, see (Zarepour 2020, pp. 819–33; Kaukua 2020, pp. 215–40). |
24 | For Avicenna’s account of perception, see (Avicenna 2013, p. 175, ll. 3–12, p. 176, ll. 1–6). For a detailed study of Avicenna’s theory of sensation, see (Black 2014, pp. 185–214); for perception and intentionality, see (Kaukua 2014, pp. 215–42). |
25 | That people born blind cannot understand colour is not a self-evident thesis in contemporary cognitive science. See (Kim et al. 2021; Striem-Amit et al. 2018). |
26 | For Avicenna’s account of the divine intellection, see (Avicenna 2005, p. 285, ll. 8–13). |
27 | Averroes, Long Commentary on De Anima = Averrois Cordubensis Commentarium Magnum in Aristotelis De Anima Libros (Averroes 1953), henceforth LCDA. For a detailed reconstruction of Averroes’s discussion of different commentator’s views on the material intellect, see (Davidson 1992, pp. 282–95). |
28 | The English translation is from (Averroes 2011, pp. 328–29). |
29 | A more detailed reconstruction of the infinite regress argument might run in the following way: Suppose the intelligible form can be individualised. If the intelligible form can be individualised, then the intelligible form must become a member of a natural species. If the intelligible form is a member of a natural species, then the intelligible form will have another intelligible form, and so on infinitely, which will in turn make the intellectual cognition impossible. However, one does have actual intellectual cognitions, so the intelligible form cannot proceed into infinity. Therefore, the intellectual cognition is possible, and the intelligible form cannot be individualised. |
30 | According to Ogden’s new account of the infinite regress, if one has an individualised F in their mind, then there must be a universal and intelligible F* in their mind through which F occurs as an individualised form. Since F* itself is intelligible, one needs a further F**; thus, it proceeds to infinity. However, it is unclear why Averroes would accept the quasi-Platonic principle that an individualised concept subsists in the mind through the participation of its universal and intelligible species. |
31 | For Averroes’s account of the apprehension of essence, see (Weimer 2019). |
32 | For a detailed reconstruction of Avicenna’s quiddity–existence distinction, see (Bertolacci 2012, pp. 257–88); for Averroes’s critical reworking of the quiddity–existence distinction, see (Menn 2011, pp. 51–96); and for a study of how Avicenna’s quiddity–existence distinction is received in the post-Avicennian traditions, see (Benevich 2017, pp. 203–58). |
33 | It’s important to note that the concept of intellectual subjectivity in the realm of the intelligible does not align with the realist perspective on universals. This stance is distinct in that it does not subscribe to universals as inherent in individual natural entities, nor does it adhere to Platonic forms. |
34 | For a general introduction to Ḥadīth al-Nawāfil and its reception in the spiritual traditions of Islam, see (Ebstein 2018, pp. 271–89). |
35 | For Ibn al-ʿArabī’s account of al-Nawāfil, see (Chittick 1989, pp. 325–31). |
References
- al-Bukhari. 1997. The Translation of the Meanings of Sahih Al-Bukhari: Arabic-English. Translated by Muhammad Khan. Houston: Dar-us-Salam Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, St. Thomas. 1889. Summa Theologiae, Opera Omnia. Edited by Leonine. Rome: Typographia Polyglotta S. C. de Propaganda Fide. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, St. Thomas. 1968. On the Unity of the Intellect Against the Averroists. Translated by Beatrice Zedler. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, St. Thomas. 1976. De Unitate contra Averroistas. In Opera Omnia Iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita. Tomus 43. Rome: Editori di san Tommaso, pp. 289–314. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, St. Thomas. 2002. Treatise on Human Nature: Summa Theologiae 1A 75–89. Translated by Robert Pasnau. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Averroes. 1953. Averrois Cordubensis Commentarium Magnum in Aristotelis De Anima Libros. Edited by F. Stuart Crawford. Cambridge: The Mediaeval Academy of America. [Google Scholar]
- Averroes. 2011. Long Commentary on the de Anima of Aristotle. Translated by Richard Taylor. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Avicenna. 1956. al-Shifāʾ: Al-Burhān. Edited by Abū Ela ʿAffīfī. Cairo: L’Organisation Egyptienne Générale du Livre. [Google Scholar]
- Avicenna. 1959. Avicenna’s De Anima (Arabic Text): Being the Psychological Part of Kitāb al-Shifāʾ. Edited by Fazlur Rahman. London: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Avicenna. 1985. Kitāb al-Najāt. Edited by M. Dānishpažūh. Tehran: Dânishgâh-i Tihrân. [Google Scholar]
- Avicenna. 2005. The Metaphysics of “The Healing” (al-Shifāʾ). Translated by Michael Marmura. Provo: Brigham Young University. [Google Scholar]
- Avicenna. 2013. al-Taʿlīqāt. Edited by S. H. Mousavian. Tehran: Iranian Institute of Philosophy. [Google Scholar]
- Baltuta, Elena. 2013. Aquinas on Intellectual Cognition: The Case of Intelligible Species. Philosophia 41: 589–602. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Benevich, Fedor. 2017. The Essence-Existence Distinction: Four Elements of the Post-Avicennian Metaphysical Dispute (11–13th Centuries). Oriens 45: 203–58. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bertolacci, Amos. 2012. The Distinction of Essence and Existence in Avicenna’s Metaphysics: The Text and Its Context. In Islamic Philosophy, Science, Culture, and Religion: Studies in Honor of Dimitri Gutas. Edited by Felicitas Opwis and David Reisman. Leiden: Brill, pp. 257–88. [Google Scholar]
- Black, Deborah. 2005. Psychology: Soul and Intellect. In The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy. Edited by Peter Adamson and Richard Taylor. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 308–26. [Google Scholar]
- Black, Deborah. 2014. Sensing Bodies, Sensing Ourselves: Avicenna on the Nature of Sensation. Documenti E Studi Sulla Tradizione Filosofica Medievale 25: 185–214. [Google Scholar]
- Chittick, William. 1989. The Sufi Path of Knowledge: Ibn al-ʿArabi’s Metaphysics of Imagination. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Davidson, Herbert. 1992. Alfarabi, Avicenna and Averroes on Intellect: Their Cosmologies, Theories of the Active Intellect, and Theories of Human Intellect. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ebstein, Michael. 2018. The Organs of God: Ḥadīth al-Nawāfil in Classical Islamic Mysticism. Journal of the American Oriental Society 138: 271–89. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gutas, Dimitri. 2012a. The Empiricism of Avicenna. Oriens 40: 391–436. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gutas, Dimitri. 2012b. Avicenna: The Metaphysics of the Rational Soul. Muslim World 102: 417–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hasse, Dag Nikolaus. 2001. Avicenna on Abstraction. In Aspects of Avicenna. Edited by Robert Wisnovsky. Princeton: Markus Wiener Publishers, pp. 39–72. [Google Scholar]
- Kader, Ali Hassan. 2014. The Life, Personality and Writings of al-Junayd. Selangor: Islamic Book Trust. [Google Scholar]
- Kaukua, Jari. 2014. The Problem of Intentionality in Avicenna. Documenti E Studi Sulla Tradizione Filosofica Medievale 25: 215–42. [Google Scholar]
- Kaukua, Jari. 2020. Avicenna’s Outsourced Rationalism. Journal of the History of Philosophy 58: 215–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kim, Judy Sein, Brianna Aheimer, Verónica Montané Manrara, and Marina Bedny. 2021. Shared Understanding of Color among Sighted and Blind Adults. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 118: e2020192118. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Lizzini, Olga. 2010. L’âme Chez Avicenne: Quelques Remarques Autour de Son Statut Épistémologique et de Son Fondament Métaphysique. Documenti e Studi Sulla Tradizione Flosofca Medievale 21: 223–42. [Google Scholar]
- Marenbon, John. 2007. Latin Averroism. In Islamic crosspollinations: Interactions in the Medieval Middle East. Edited by Anna Akasoy, James Montgomery and Peter Pormann. Edinburgh: Gibb Memorial Trust, pp. 135–47. [Google Scholar]
- Menn, Stephen. 2011. Fârâbî in the Reception of Avicenna’s Metaphysics: Averroes against Avicenna on Being and Unity. In The Arabic, Hebrew and Latin Reception of Avicenna’s Metaphysics. Edited by Dag Nikolaus Hasse and Amos Bertolacci. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 51–96. [Google Scholar]
- Ogden, Stephen. 2020. Avicenna’s Emanated Abstraction. Philosophers’ Imprint 20: 1–26. [Google Scholar]
- Ogden, Stephen. 2021. Averroes’s Unity Argument against Multiple Intellects. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 103: 429–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rahman, Fazlur. 1958. Prophecy in Islam: Philosophy and Orthodoxy. London: George Allen and Unwin. [Google Scholar]
- Striem-Amit, Ella, Xiaoying Wang, Yanchao Bi, and Alfonso Caramazza. 2018. Neural Representation of Visual Concepts in People Born Blind. Nature Communications 9: 5250. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Taylor, Richard. 1999. Averroes’ Epistemology and its Critique by Aquinas. Milwaukee: Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications, p. 293. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, Richard. 2004. Improving on Nature’s Exemplar: Averroes’ Completion of Aristotle’s Psychology of Intellect. Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies 47: 107–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Taylor, Richard. 2005. Review Essays—Al-Farabi and Avicenna: Two Recent Contributions. Middle East Studies Association Bulletin 39: 180–182. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Taylor, Richard. 2006. Abstraction in al-Fārābī. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 80: 151–168. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Weimer, David. 2019. Averroes on Knowing Essences. In Interpreting Averroes: Critical Essays. Edited by Peter Adamson and Matteo di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 116–37. [Google Scholar]
- Walzer, Richard. 1957. Al-Fārābī’s Theory of Prophecy and Divination. The Journal of Hellenic Studies 77, Pt 1: 142–8. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wu, Tianyue. 2017. Aquinas on the Individuality of Thinking. The Review of Metaphysics 71: 65–105. [Google Scholar]
- Zarepour, Mohammad Saleh. 2020. Avicenna’s Notion of Fiṭrīyāt: A Comment on Dimitri Gutas’ Interpretation. Philosophy East and West 70: 819–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Cai, Z. Blind Man, Mirror, and Fire: Aquinas, Avicenna, and Averroes on Thinking. Religions 2024, 15, 150. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15020150
Cai Z. Blind Man, Mirror, and Fire: Aquinas, Avicenna, and Averroes on Thinking. Religions. 2024; 15(2):150. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15020150
Chicago/Turabian StyleCai, Zhenyu. 2024. "Blind Man, Mirror, and Fire: Aquinas, Avicenna, and Averroes on Thinking" Religions 15, no. 2: 150. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15020150
APA StyleCai, Z. (2024). Blind Man, Mirror, and Fire: Aquinas, Avicenna, and Averroes on Thinking. Religions, 15(2), 150. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15020150