Environmental Ethics and the Cambridge Platonist Henry More
Abstract
:1. The Problem
Omnipresence is not an extended presence in all places but God’s ability to know what is going on in any place and ability to act in any place. While this distinction between action and actor is not terribly medieval,5 part of Descartes’ account is, nonetheless, built upon the long-standing tradition growing out of Anselm and Aquinas (see Monologium chs. 20, 22 and Proslogium chs. 13; Summa contra Gentiles, lib. 3 d. 68 and Summa Theologiae I. q. 8), where God is present but not in the same way as material objects. Variations on this position remain one of if not the primary account of omnipresence today (Inman 2017, p. 4). Wieranga (Wierenga and American Catholic Philosophical Association 1988; Taliaferro et al. 2010), Leftow (Leftow 1988), and Taliaferro (Taliaferro 1994; Taliaferro et al. 1997) hold basic reinterpretations of the model, while Hartshorne (Hartshorne 1941) and Swinburne (Swinburne 1993) have expanded it further, arguing that if God knows and controls all things in the world, then, in some sense, the world constitutes God’s body (in the same way that the human mind has knowledge of and control over its own body). Stump has also offered her own rendition of the classic view, albeit one supplemented by a notion of shared attention and personal presence (Stump 2013; Stump and Weithman 2008).there is no extension of substance in God, in angels or in our minds, but only one of power … I believe that God is everywhere in respect of his power, whereas he has no relation to space whatsoever in respect of his essence.
Although it is a tad anachronistic to put it this way, More is essentially worried that the problem of Cartesian dualism between mind and matter simply reoccurs here between the divine mind and its extended creation. While Descartes is open to the sort of bare extension that analogous accounts require, he is not open to the literal or true extension that seems to describe our everyday phenomenon of entities that are present with us in height, width, and depth. More wonders how Descartes can bring together unextended and truly extended entities without at least a momentary overlap of some kind, fearing that if God cannot be truly extended, then God and the extended world are substantially distinct, so neither can be present to the other. While we do not have room here to launch a full critique of unextended (or, rather, not truly extended) versions of omnipresence and their rich historical and contemporary articulations, we can gesture toward such critiques by others in the field, which indicate that objections similar to More’s continue to be made and updated today. For example, James Gordon has argued that,I cannot but suspect that by the power of God you want to understand an effect transferred into matter. However, if you understand it this way, I cannot see how that should not equally come to naught. For there is no other way for this effect to be transferred than by the divine power touching matter and matter receiving it; in other words, by some real mode united to the matter and, therefore, extended.
Likewise, Nicholas Everitt writes that,recent treatments of … omnipresence in philosophy and theology fail to give a compelling account of what it means for God to be present in, with, at, or to specific persons or places … the non-occupation accounts of Wierenga, Leftow, and Stump fall short. Their fatal flaw is that they cannot account for the spatiality of God’s presence.
Similarly, Luco J. van den Brom asks how “spaceless contact with spatial objects” is possible, suggesting that “‘the assumption that God is totally present everywhere in a spaceless mode does not appear to be meaningful at all” (van den Brom 2010). Now, many would surely protest this characterization of the classical view of omnipresence, with recent authors rushing to defend the genuinely spatial presence of God in classical accounts (Inman 2017; Pasnau 2011). Yet our goal here will not be primarily to prove that there is a problem but to defend More’s possible solution to it. Thus, we can tentatively say that—regardless of whether it is an inescapable problem or not—there are some scholars who believe traditional accounts of divine omnipresence have not allowed God to be sufficiently and spatially near enough to creation. This avoids the specter of pantheism but—arguably—at the cost of severing God from the environment.Omnipresence is standardly construed by both the medievals and moderns in a surprising way. It does not consist in permanent occupancy of the whole of space, but instead is explained in terms of God’s knowledge and power… Theists are of course free to define the terms they use in whatever way they see fit. But if this is how omnipresence is interpreted, one might well think that it would be clearer to say straightforwardly that God is not omnipresent at all …
2. More’s Answer
I have always been prone to think this [i.e., space] … to be a more obscure shadow or adumbration, or to be a more general and confused apprehension of the Divine Amplitude … For this will be necessarily, though all Matter were annihilated out of the World. Nay indeed this is antecedent to all Matter, forasmuch as no Matter nor any Being else can be conceived to be but in this … Lord thou hast been our dwelling-place in all generations. Before the Mountains were brought forth, or ever thou hadst formed the Earth or the World: even from everlasting to everlasting thou art God.
Descartes defined true extension as inherently material, creating a dualism of substance between truly extended matter and unextended (or barely extended) mind. More believed this relegated spiritual substances to some ethereal, unextended, non-location, undermining any sense in which the divine was truly present in the world. However, by broadening extension beyond matter, More was trying to allow for the possibility that there could be immaterial extensions, bridging the qualitative chasm between matter and mind, for both are truly extended. Thus, instead of defining matter as extension, More now defined matter as impenetrability:9… the definition which you give of matter or body is far broader than is warranted. For God also seems to be an extended substance … Hence, extension is apparently coterminous with the absolute essence of things, although the latter may differ according to the differences between the essences themselves. I view God as being extended in his own way on account of his omnipresence, occupying as he does the whole fabric of the world and each of its particles in an intimate fashion. How else could he impress motion upon matter, which, as you yourself concede, he did at some point and which he does to this day, unless he touches, or had at least at some point touched, the matter of the universe from close up? He could not have done so at any time had he not been present everywhere and occupied every single place. Hence, God is extended and expanded in his own way, and therefore is an extended substance … For this reason, “extended substance” is broader than “body”.
One can picture a ghost that is extended in height and width and, yet, is still penetrable—e.g., it can walk through walls. Yet, material things are impenetrable, pushing back against the borders of each other—e.g., an incoming bird crunches against a closed window. As such, extension can be conceived indifferently to materiality and immateriality, for both the immaterial ghost and the material bird are extended in height, width, and depth. If extension and matter can be conceived separately, then—at least within the cognitive Cartesian framework More is posing his argument within—they must be conceptually distinct. One need not forfeit the extended world to materiality, as Descartes did when he reduced all extension to matter. Rather, one can conceive of true extension as consistent with both materiality and immateriality. This allows God to be truly present throughout the extended universe without becoming material, setting the stage for More’s bolder proposal of divine space.this reveals another property of matter or body which we could call “impenetrability”: one body cannot penetrate or be penetrated by another body. From that, the difference between the divine and the corporeal nature becomes quite clear: the former is able to penetrate the latter, while the latter cannot penetrate itself.
Thus, More’s divine space seeks to chart a middle way between Spinoza’s pantheism and the Cartesian divorce of spirit and matter, potentially offering us a theological resource for our contemporary environmental crisis. Whether More’s intended middle way actually achieves its aim and avoids what it critiques will now be addressed.Since, therefore, stones, lead, dung, an ass, a toad, a louse and all things of that sort are individual things, it is necessary that they be modes of the attributes of God and their expressions in a certain and determinate manner. Moreover, since besides substance and modes there is nothing, and modes cannot be without substance, it is clear that the substance of God is the substance of stones, lead, dung, an ass, a toad, and a louse, and those extended things modes of divine extension and those thoughts modes of divine thought, so that the God of Spinoza thinks in an ass as an ass, in a toad as a toad, in a louse as a louse, and indeed in a stone, lead and dung as stone, lead and dung.
3. Countering Potential Defeaters
Indeed, only the remnants of an outdated positivism could totally dismiss the possibility of immaterial absolutes lingering behind our experience of relative material phenomena. While relativity cannot locate an objective frame, this does not mean that there is none, especially from the point of view of an omniscient God (Lucas 1973, p. 71). These verificationist epistemological principles underlying the metaphysical correlates of relativity were steadily abandoned in the latter half of the twentieth century and should never have dictated terms to theology—whose object is not empirical, at least not in the usual sense—to begin with.11 As Craig writes:It is often said that relativity refuted Newton. But it is a misleading oversimplification. There is no straight opposition between relativity theories and Newtonian, absolute, theories... Theologically (and not only theologically) speaking we may assign a preferred frame of reference … which is at rest… Only there is no physical reason why we should.
Even if the physicist’s calculations do not require a broader, metaphysical space in which spacetime expands, this does not entail that such a space does not exist. Special and general relativity can provide accurate physical descriptions within a broader reality that, nonetheless, transcends and encompasses them both. We can concede that spacetime is immanent and creaturely while still postulating a divine and/or metaphysical space that transcends it.Despite the triumph of Einstein’s Special Theory, contemporary physics has burst the old wineskins of positivism and verificationism as metaphysical elements have increasingly entered the mainstream of modern physical discussions. Therefore, as we enter a new century of scientific exploration, freed from the blinders of positivism, the time is ripe for a reassessment of the metaphysical question of the existence of absolute time and space.
It is, thus, possible to admit the facts of STR while providing a variety of alternative and empirically equivalent explanations for those facts, allowing for an essentially classical model of space and time to remain intact and transcendent in a way not often considered possible post-Einstein. While this paper will definitively not commit to any one of these four defenses taken individually (indeed, I have my own criticisms of them), it will argue that they cumulatively make a case for a plausibly transcendent space that need not be thought of as creaturely or pictured as material in the same way as contemporary spacetime has tended to be.Padgett considers the spatio-temporal view a conflation of what is logical with what is physical. Koperski argues similarly, stating that STR’s treatment of all points in time as real is an idealization. He gives multiple examples of how these mathematical idealizations are utilized in science. For instance, every point of a swinging pendulum can be mapped mathematically. However, the pendulum is in only one of these states at a given moment. A further advantage to the antirealist perspective is that it removes the contradiction between GTR and particle physics.
in not in tension with the classical view that God is aspatial. Consider: to be spatial is to be enclosed by space. [Yet] if God’s Omnipresence is just what constitutes space, God could hardly be interior to space; obviously, God could not be an occupant of that which His Omnipresence constitutes.
While Leibniz used this within a broader argument against divine space (and there is a rich history of this discussion that is beyond our purview here), we can turn his observation on its head, ironically enlisting it to show how space presents itself to the mind as deeply self-identical and unified. For without material markers (“without things”) to designate the difference between spaces, there is nothing left to distinguish one place from another, so there are no conceptual distinctions left in space. If we can picture space on its own without any material objects existing to demarcate its regions, then this suggests that space, qua space, is conceptually one. Just as More could conceive of an extension that is penetrable and, thereby, show that extension and impenetrable matter are not conceptually synonymous, so too can we conceive of a space that is not demarcated by distinguishable objects, showing that space and distinguishable parts are not conceptually synonymous. Space, imagined on its own, has no distinctions or parts within it. Distinctions are, thus, not inherent to our thought of space itself but to the secondary objects we introduce into that space, for we can imagine a space that is not differentiated by objects. In the same way that Bergson distinguished between the measures of time and duration itself, we can arguably distinguish in our minds between the measures of space and the mental phenomenon of space itself. Even if one simply pictures a grid of lines to measure and distinguish spaces, the grid itself is something secondary added on top of space and so is an attempt to provide a material or objective measure for something that is conceptually prior to such measures.Space is something absolutely uniform, and without the things placed in it, one point of space absolutely does not differ in any respect whatsoever from another point of space … they are absolutely indiscernible … [the parts of] space without things has nothing by which it may be distinguished.
The space between parts is simply more space, so space is the one thing that cannot be parted like everything else, for the thing that is meant to divide it is just more of the same. Space parts other things without itself being parted, suggesting that an asymmetrical relation can exist between the simplicity of space and the complexity of material objects. Space is not only indivisible but is one of the means by which other things are divided; the manyness of matter is seen in contrast to the oneness of space that constitutes the gaps that help distinguish material parts. Space itself is not parted, yet its presence constitutes the gaps (between contiguous entities) and distances (between non-contiguous entities) that help shape the distinctions between material parts. Matter does not divide space; rather, space divides matter. While this may not apply to the sort of formal distinctions between, for example, an apple and the color red (i.e., parts that are not distinguished by separations in space), it would certainly apply to material parts, such as an apple and its tree, which are separable into different locations in space and are, thereby, distinct. While space is present in the apple as much as outside of it (and so is not broken up by the apple), the apple can be plucked from its tree or sliced into separate pieces (and so is broken up by space). Of course, this is not only true of everyday parts on the macro level but, arguably, also on the micro level as well, for the space between distinct molecules and atoms prevents my body or the universe from collapsing into a singularity. One might retort to this that two subatomic entities could conceivably exist perfectly touching each other without any spatial gaps, so space is not the only basis for parting. Yet, we need not argue that space is the only possible way to distinguish parts but that it is merely one of the ways to do so. One might also retort that parts might actually be able to overlap and interpenetrate, as was raised in recent discussions of bosons (Hawthorne and Uzquiano 2011); in which case, distinct physical parts are not necessarily always separated by space in the way I have described here. However, again, we are not arguing that space is the only way to distinguish physical parts. Furthermore, this interpenetration would argue our case in another direction, for, then, an overlapping complexity of matter could exist in a simple space, providing a precedent against mereological harmony, which could add legitimacy to our broader claim that a simple space can contain complex objects. Similar arguments against mereological harmony—e.g., interpenetration, multilocation, extended simples—might also provide relevant examples of a possible disparity between the complexity/simplicity of space and matter (even though this asymmetry is often going in the wrong direction, e.g., arguing that a simple object may be multi-located within a complexity of spaces). Thus, to sum up this wide-reaching point, we can say that spatial gaps do not only later reveal parts (e.g., when we cut the apple into slices) but also actually helped constitute them all along (e.g., these spatial gaps always existed between the finer particles of the apple and are only later revealed in the slicing). Space may have an asymmetrical relationship with matter, in which it affords divisibility to other things without itself being divided. Space divides the things that exist within it, yet the reverse does not necessarily hold. Far from spoiling divine simplicity, space may provide the doctrine with a renewed way forward, as space may be the one thing in the extended universe that precludes parting.… infinite space is one, absolutely and essentially indivisible, and to suppose it parted is a contradiction in terms, because there must be space in the partition itself, which is to suppose it parted and yet not parted at the same time.
4. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Note this excellent recent volume, edited by two leading scholars in the Christian Platonist field (Hampton and Hedley 2022). |
2 | “For this infinite and immobile extension will be seen to be not something merely real (which we have noted in the last place) but something divine after we shall have enumerated those divine names or titles which suit it exactly, and with the greatest certainty make it not possible to be nothing, seeing that so many and such excellent attributes fit it. Of which kind are those which follow, which metaphysicians specifically attribute to First Being. Such as one, simple, immobile, eternal, complete, independent, existing from itself, subsisting by itself, incorruptible, necessary, immense, uncreated, uncircumscribed, incomprehensible, omnipresent, incorporeal, permeating and encompassing everything, Being by essence, Being by act, pure Act. There are not less than twenty titles by which the divine numen should be designated, which most aptly suit this infinite place which we have demonstrated to be in the universe; if we may omit that the same divine numen is called among Cabbalists מקום, that is, place. It would be an absolutely amazing thing, more than can be expressed, and a wonder, as it were, if all this would merely define nothing”. (More 1995). |
3 | A broader and non-environmentally charged exploration of More’s thesis is undertaken in my forthcoming book (Lyonhart 2023). |
4 | Some insist that extension and location are not synonyms, such that God can exist and be ‘somewhere’ without being extended (Pasnau 2011); ‘Mind and Extension (Descartes, Hobbes, More)’ in (Lagerlund 2007). |
5 | It is difficult to parse how close Descartes’ view is to the classic medieval account. As Pasnau notes: “The classic formulation is due to Aquinas, Summa theol. 1a 8.3… Aquinas holds that God is present everywhere both with respect to his power and with respect to his essence (1a 8.3c). This might seem to put him at odds with Descartes’s view, but that is not so clear, in light of the passage… in Descartes’s last letter to More: “it is certain that God’s essence must be present everywhere so that his power can exert itself there” (V 403)”. Lagerlund (2007). |
6 | Pasnau draws out this helpful distinction between bare and true extension (Pasnau 2011, p. 336). |
7 | Some attempt to sidestep these issues by coupling pantheism with privation, such that only the Good exists, offering a moral hierarchy from positive Being to evil non-being. While sufficiently nuanced versions of this ilk may perhaps survive unscathed, popular versions tend to slip into some of the same difficulties, negating the existence of any moral issues in the world at all and, thus, any environmental crisis to fix. For example, Paul Selig writes, “It was always illusion that you were separate from God… It was always illusion that there was war… always illusion that you were not loved by your fellow man… You are all perfect…” (Selig 2010). Likewise, Joel Goldsmith contends that, in reality, there is “no sinner to be reformed, no sick to heal, no poor to enrich”. (Goldsmith 1956). On a more academic level, some have put pantheism in conversation with the Christian environmental theologies of such thinkers as Pierre Teilhard De Chardin, Liberty Hyde Bailey, Thomas Berry, Catherine Keller, Mary Jane Rubenstein, and Laurel Kearns. However, there is inherently a lot of subjectivity and controversy surrounding which of these authors and their specific works truly classify as ‘pantheistic’ in the sense of seeing the God-world relation as one of identity and/or which truly classify as ‘Christian’. |
8 | Note that More existed centuries before our contemporary environmental crisis. While More provides resources that we can appropriate for today, one is not here claiming that More himself would be an ‘environmentalist’ in our modern sense. |
9 | While Descartes also believed matter was impenetrable (and stated this explicitly in his correspondence with More; see (Hengstermann 2019, p. 18)) this was not its essential definition but one of its secondary traits. More inverts this, allowing impenetrability to be the defining feature of matter while making extension something it has but is not synonymous with. |
10 | Note that the ‘absoluteness’ here defended is not necessarily identical with the substantivalist thesis of contemporary philosophy of science but provides an additional sense of absolute as providing a “preferred frame of reference”. |
11 | “…I see no reason why theists should be unduly concerned about departing from the spirit of a positivistic theory which takes no cognizance of God’s existence”. (Craig 2001b, pp. 170–71). See also (Swinburne 1983). |
12 | “It may well be the case that Newton was right… there are no compelling reasons to prefer a spacetime ontology over a classical ontology of space and time..”. (Craig 2001b, pp. 160, 186). Note that the argument of this entire section is borrowed heavily from Craig. |
13 | “Whence, as I said before, the Idea of God being such as it is, it will both justly and necessarily cast this ruder notion of Space upon that Infinite and Eternal Spirit which is God. Now there is the same reason for Time (by Time I mean Duration) as for Space. For we cannot imagine but that there has been such a continued Duration as could have no beginning nor interruption. And any one will say, it is non-sense that there should be such a necessary duration, when there is no reall Essence that must of it self thus be always, and for ever so endure. What or who is it then that this eternal, uninterrupted and never-fading duration must belong to? No Philosopher can answer more appositely then the holy Psalmist, From everlasting to everlasting thou art God. Wherefore I say that those unavoidable imaginations of the necessity of an Infinite Space, as they call it, and Eternal duration, are no proofs of a Self-existent Matter, but rather obscure sub-indications of the necessary Existence of God. There is also another way of answering this Objection, which is this; That this Imagination of Space is not the imagination of any real thing, but onely of the large and immense capacity of the potentiality of the Matter…” (More 1655, pp. 229–30). |
14 | “Admitted on all sides to be empirically equivalent to the Einsteinian interpretation, the neo-Lorentzian interpretation is neither ad hoc nor more complicated than its rival. The physical effects it posits are no less real in the received version, only there they appear as axiomatic deductions lacking causal explanations. Indeed, its fecundity in opening the question about physical causes is an important advantage of the neo-Lorentzian interpretation… With little to commend spacetime realism over a neo-Lorentzian conception of space and time and with powerful objections lodged against it, we may conclude that there is no reason to adopt a spacetime interpretation of SR rather than a neo-Lorentzian approach to the problems of Relativity Theory”. (Craig 2001b, pp. 196, 194). |
15 | “It is only now, in the light of the new experiments stemming from Bell’s work, that the suggestion of replacing Einstein’s interpretation by Lorentz’s can be made. If there is action at a distance, then there is something like absolute space. If we now have theoretical reasons from quantum theory for introducing absolute simultaneity, then we would have to go back to Lorentz’s interpretation”. (Popper 1982, p. 29). |
16 | |
17 | For a helpful outline of types of simplicity, see (Morris 2002, pp. 113–18). |
18 | E.g., John Feinberg writes, “So there appear to be problems with both the property view of simplicity and the property instance view… simplicity is not one of the divine attributes. This doesn’t mean that God has physical parts..”. (Feinberg 2006, p. 335). |
19 | |
20 | Clarke himself notes this interesting nuance in Leibniz, summarizing him as saying, “The parts of time and space are allowed to be exactly alike in themselves, but not so when bodies exist in them”. In turn, Clarke’s own diagnosis is also that bodies are our sensible measure of divisions, which are not seen in space in itself or on their own. (Leibniz et al. 2000). |
21 | More’s successor, Samuel Clarke, says something a tad similar to this: “There is no such thing in reality as bounded space, but only we in our imagination fix our attention on what part or quantity we please of that which itself is always and necessarily unbounded”. Leibniz et al. (2000). |
22 | As More writes: “And when other beings are corrupted in it, it is, however, itself incorruptible”. More (1995). Or as Clarke states: “The parts of immensity (being totally of a different kind from corporeal, partable, seperable, divisible, movable parts, which are the ground of corruptibility) do no more hinder immensity from being essentially one than the parts of duration hinder eternity from being essentially one. God himself suffers no change at all by the variety and changebleness of things which live and move and have their being in him”. Leibniz et al. (2000). |
23 | Of course, the holenmerist (a term More himself coined) might laugh triumphantly at our retreat back to analogy. However, the primary issue with classical holenmerism is not necessarily that analogy is employed, but rather, that even upon employing it, the end result seems to bear little resemblance to any phenomenologically normal sense of the term ‘presence’. When one attempts to explain holenmerism (i.e., that immaterial entities are wholly replicated in every part of space) to the uninitiated, it seems to evoke nothing but a blank stare, for it resonates with little in our experience and bears even less resemblance to any of the things we usually define as ‘present’. In contrast, space has an intuitive, immediate, phenomenologically resonant sense of presence about it. We have dwelled within it all our lives. Space is the very thing this page exists within, that our eyes flit back and forth through as we read, and light travels between to make this moment of sight possible. If one simply pauses now to reach out their hand as if clawing for a loved one in the dark, they will intuitively sense the space their fingers run through like water. This analogous void may be mysterious; it may be distinct from how material objects exist, yet somehow, we all intuitively sense its presence. If God is space, then he is closer than the heavens, for space is as present between my toes as between the stars. With this said, one must admit we do not have sufficient space in this paper to properly address holenmerism and the classical view. Interested readers should turn to my book, Lyonhart (2023, particularly chapters 1–3, and 7), for a more thorough elaboration of these critiques along with More’s specific development regarding the theory. |
References
- Coffa, J. Alberto, and Linda Wessels. 1993. The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Craig, William Lane. 2001a. Time and the Metaphysics of Relativity. Philosophical Studies Series; v. 84. Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer Academic, p. 148. [Google Scholar]
- Craig, William Lane. 2001b. God, Time, and Eternity: The Coherence of Theism II: Eternity. Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 160, 186. [Google Scholar]
- Davies, Paul, and Julian Russell Brown. 1993. The Ghost in the Atom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 49–50. [Google Scholar]
- DeWeese, Garrett J. 2017. God and the Nature of Time. Milton Park: Routledge, p. 68. [Google Scholar]
- Feinberg, John. 2006. No One Like Him: The Doctrine of God, Rev. ed. Foundations of Evangelical Theology. Wheaton: Crossway Books, p. 335. [Google Scholar]
- Funkenstein, Amos. 1986. Theology and the Scientific Imagination: From the Middle Ages to the Seventeenth Century. Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 23–79. [Google Scholar]
- Goldsmith, Joel. 1956. The Infinite Way. Wichita: Devorss, p. 40. [Google Scholar]
- Gordon, James R. 2018. Rethinking Divine Spatiality: Divine Omnipresence in Philosophical and Theological Perspective. The Heythrop Journal 59: 534, 539. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hampton, Alexander J., and Douglas Hedley. 2022. The Cambridge Companion to Christianity and the Environment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hart, Seth. 2017. God, Time, and Relativity. Unpublished article, sent to the author via email. August 9. [Google Scholar]
- Hartshorne, Charles. 1941. Man’s Vision of God and the Logic of Theism. New York: Willett, Clark & Co. [Google Scholar]
- Hawthorne, John, and Gabriel Uzquiano. 2011. How Many Angels Can Dance on the Point of a Needle? Transcendental Theology Meets Modal Metaphysics. Mind 2: 53–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hengstermann, Christian. 2019. English Translation of the Descartes-More Correspondence. Unpublished Manuscript, p. 35. [Google Scholar]
- Hoffman, Joshua, and Gary S. Rosenkrantz. 2002. The Divine Attributes, Exploring the Philosophy of Religion 2. Oxford: Blackwell, p. 40. [Google Scholar]
- Hoffman, Joshua, and Gary S. Rosenkrantz. 2010. The Divine Attributes. Philosophy Compass 5: 86. [Google Scholar]
- Hudson, Hud. 2009. Omnipresence. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology. Edited by Thomas P. Flint and Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 199–216. [Google Scholar]
- Inman, Ross D. 2017. Omnipresence and the Location of the Immaterial. Oxford: Oxford University Press, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Koperski, Jeffrey. 2015. The Physics of Theism. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons, p. 124. [Google Scholar]
- Lagerlund, Henrik, ed. 2007. Forming the Mind: Essays on the Internal Senses and the Mind/Body Problem from Avicenna to the Medical Enlightenment. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 288–96. [Google Scholar]
- Leech, David. 2013. The Hammer of the Cartesians: Henry More’s Philosophy of Spirit and the Origins of Modern Atheism, Studies in Philosophical Theology 53, Pre-release ed. Leuven: Peeters, p. 8. [Google Scholar]
- Leftow, Brian. 1988. Anselm on Omnipresence. New Scholasticism 63: 326–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, Samuel Clarke, and Roger Ariew. 2000. Correspondence. Indianapolis: Hackett Pub. Co., p. 14. [Google Scholar]
- Lucas, John Randolph. 1973. A Treatise on Time and Space. London: Methuen, pp. 197–98. [Google Scholar]
- Lyonhart, Jd. 2023. Space God: Rejudging a Debate between More, Newton, and Einstein. Eugene: Cascade Books. [Google Scholar]
- More, Henry, and A. Jacob. 1991. Henry More’s Refutation of Spinoza. Studien Und Materialien Zur Geschichte Der Philosophie, Bd. 32. Hildesheim and New York: G. Olms, p. 99. [Google Scholar]
- More, Henry. 1655. An Antidote Against Atheism. Printed by James Flesher. London: William Morden, pp. 229–30. [Google Scholar]
- More, Henry. 1668. Divine Dialogues. Glasgow: Robert Foulis, p. 107. [Google Scholar]
- More, Henry. 1995. Henry More’s Manual of Metaphysics: A Translation of the Enchiridium Metaphysicum (1679), Studien Und Materialien Zur Geschichte Der Philosophie. Bd. 38. Hildesheim: Olms, p. 58. [Google Scholar]
- Morris, Thomas V. 2002. Our Idea of God: An Introduction to Philosophical Theology. Vancouver: Regent College Pub., pp. 113–18. [Google Scholar]
- Oakes, Robert. 2006. Divine Omnipresence and Maximal Immanence: Supernaturalism versus Pantheism. American Philosophical Quarterly 43: 176. [Google Scholar]
- Pasnau, Robert. 2011. Metaphysical Themes: 1274–1671. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 328, 350–73. [Google Scholar]
- Pickstock, Catherine. 2005. Duns Scotus: His Historical and Contemporary Significance. Modern Theology 21: 557–58. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Popper, Karl. 1982. Quantum Theory and the Schism in Physics. London: Unwin Hyman, p. 29. [Google Scholar]
- Selig, Paul. 2010. I Am the Word. New York: Penguin Publishing Group, p. 35. [Google Scholar]
- Stump, Eleonore, and Paul Weithman. 2008. Presence and Omnipresence. In Liberal Faith: Essays in Honor of Philip Quinn. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 59–82. [Google Scholar]
- Stump, Eleonore. 2013. Omnipresence, Indwelling, and the Second-Personal. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 5: 29–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Swinburne, Richard. 1983. Verificationism and Theories of Spacetime. In Space, Time and Causality. Dordrecht: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Swinburne, Richard. 1993. The Coherence of Theism, Rev. ed. Clarendon Library of Logic and Philosophy. New York: Clarendon Press, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 99–128. [Google Scholar]
- Taliaferro, Charles, Paul Draper, and Philip L. Quinn, eds. 2010. Omnipresence. In A Companion to Philosophy of Religion. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 258–62. [Google Scholar]
- Taliaferro, Charles, Paul Draper, and Philip L. Quinn. 1997. Incorporeality. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Religion. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 271–78. [Google Scholar]
- Taliaferro, Charles. 1994. Consciousness and the Mind of God. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- van den Brom, Luco J. 2010. The Divine Attributes. Philosophy Compass 5: 78–90. [Google Scholar]
- Wierenga, Edward, and American Catholic Philosophical Association. 1988. Anselm on Omnipresence. New Scholasticism 62: 30–41. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Lyonhart, J.D. Environmental Ethics and the Cambridge Platonist Henry More. Religions 2024, 15, 157. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15020157
Lyonhart JD. Environmental Ethics and the Cambridge Platonist Henry More. Religions. 2024; 15(2):157. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15020157
Chicago/Turabian StyleLyonhart, Jonathan David. 2024. "Environmental Ethics and the Cambridge Platonist Henry More" Religions 15, no. 2: 157. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15020157
APA StyleLyonhart, J. D. (2024). Environmental Ethics and the Cambridge Platonist Henry More. Religions, 15(2), 157. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15020157