Jürgen Habermas’s Translation of the Human Being as Created in the Image of God: Perspectives from Joseph Ratzinger and Alasdair MacIntyre
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Translation of the Sacred into the Profane
2.1. Habermas’s Translation Proviso
2.2. Secular Reason, the Impulses of Religion, and the Defense of Democracy
The activity of translation is, for Habermas, a collective effort of the whole of society, i.e., those with religious and non-religious perspectives. Such collaborative translation of religious concepts is predicated upon the principle of the ethic of citizenship, in which all citizens acknowledge that each citizen can make meaningful contributions to political debate. Thus, from an ethical (but not legal) perspective, all citizens are acknowledged to be endowed with equal rights and are recognized as participants in co-legislation. Religious citizens cannot be a priori dismissed as irrational, just as secular citizens cannot be dismissed by those of religious persuasion (Habermas 2006a, pp. 9–12). Habermas insists that if reason and religion are to speak to one another, rather than at or about one another, reason must accept that religion has meaningful contributions to offer. Likewise, religion must accept the authority of natural reason “as the fallible results of the institutionalised sciences and the basic principles of universalistic egalitarianism in law and morality” (Habermas 2010a, p. 16). Without this structure for dialogue, it is the secular character of the state, rather than religions, that is endangered.“For all the world religions associate with ritual practices their own epistemic paths to the sacred, be it revelation, meditation and ascetic exercise, or prayer. These particularistic ties explain the need, in the context of the political will formation of a pluralistic society, to test the generalisable content of religious assertions independently of their epistemic context of origin. This is the point of the translation proviso”.
2.3. Secular Reason as a Shared Language Accessible to All
Such translations express profound interpersonal and existential experiences in secular language, some of which “leave us speechless”. To date, only religious language has adequately articulated such experiences (Habermas 2002, p. 164). Habermas’ translation proviso is caveated by two qualifications: First, translation of sacred concepts into secular language is not a re-embedding of reason in history or nature. Modernity is compatible only with Kantian universalism, and religions that fail to acknowledge the cognitive limits of modernity, insisting instead on retaining premodern religious attitudes, are fundamentalist (Habermas 2002, p. 151). Second, he acknowledges that it is an open question as to whether the political deficiencies of modernity can indeed be offset by translation of the unexhausted meaning of religious concepts into secular language (Habermas 2013, p. 357).“Those moral feelings which only religious language has as yet been able to give a sufficiently differentiated expression may find universal resonance once a salvaging formulation turns up for something almost forgotten, but implicitly missed. The mode for non destructive secularisation is translation”.
2.4. Translation as a Structurally Critical Aspect of Habermas’s Thought
“The sublimation of the sacred into a transcendent power went hand-in-hand with distinct paths to salvation, which in turn involved an ethical reinterpretation of the traditional rites and the abolition (or late on the inversion) of the magical meaning of sacrifice”.
2.5. Alternatives to Habermas’s Translation Proviso
2.5.1. A Socratic-Pauline Dialogue with Cultures and Religions: Ratzinger/Benedict XVI
2.5.2. A Different Diagnosis of the Problem: Alasdair MacIntyre
2.6. Religion in Habermas’s Kantian Republican Framework
A close reading of Habermas indicates that the translation of religious concepts is not so much an arriving at the same conclusion from different perspectives, but a simple acquisition of things needed from religious and other philosophical traditions. These acquired things are used to plug gaps in modernity’s self-understanding while simultaneously claiming that modernity is self-sufficient. What Habermas is doing cannot be described as “translation”. It is, as he himself has often, in parallel, described it, the activity of assimilation and re-appropriation. Ratzinger, as Benedict XVI, describes it in his 2011 address to the Reichstag as modern philosophy “covertly drawing upon God’s raw materials, which we refashion into our own products” (Benedict XVI 2011).“Among the modern societies, only those that are able to introduce into the secular domain the essential content of their religious traditions which point beyond the merely human realm will also be able to rescue the substance of the human”.
2.7. Points of Confluence and Divergence with Ratzinger and MacIntyre
3. Habermas’s Translation of Humanity as Created in the Image of God
3.1. The Human Being as a Moral Agent
3.2. Genesis: Creation and the Fall of Humanity
3.3. Alternative Interpretations
3.3.1. Ratzinger and the Truly Human—Two Natures in One Person
3.3.2. MacIntyre on Human Dignitas and the Respect Due from Justice
“It is widely held that what theists and atheists disagree about and have reason to disagree about is the existence of God and only that. About everything else, about everything that comprises nature—that is everything except God—there is, so it is believed, no reason to disagree. I contrast this view with what I take to be the theistic understanding of that disagreement, that it concerns some aspects of everything. To be a theist is to understand everything particular as, by reason of its finitude and its contingency, pointing towards God. It is to believe that, if we are to try to understand finite particulars independent of their relationship to God, we are bound to misunderstand them. It is to hold that all explanations and understanding that does not refer us to God both as first cause and final end is incomplete, and that foremost among the finite particulars of which this is true are we ourselves as human beings”.
3.4. The Fullness of Meaning Associated with the Original Concept: Creation in the Image of God
4. Habermas’s Problem Statement and the Presupposition Proviso
4.1. The Origin and Grounds of Reason
4.2. The Presupposition Proviso: Dialogue and Legitimate Argument
4.3. The Presupposition Proviso’s Questions
As noted, in his 2006 Regensburg address as Pope Benedict XVI, Ratzinger asked that same question in a different way: if the rational structure of matter is accepted as a given by the natural sciences, why is that given not also applied to the spiritual and human aspects of reality and existence? Third, as MacIntyre noted, an account of why and how the human being can ask, let alone answer, any of these questions must be provided. (MacIntyre 2009a, pp. 177–80). The presupposition proviso compels an answer to the question “who is the human being?”, from which all other presuppositions flow. At every turn, it is first a question of how the human being can claim a metaphysical structure or reject or deconstruct it. It forces a unity to the account of the human being, which incorporates the relationships of the present and the sequence of their very existence. It places each account in its proper context. The individual particular contingent human being gives an account of the human being. Everything flows from such an account. All philosophical questions depend upon and are determined by the account of how the human being can give an account of the human being.“The question is whether reason, or rationality, stands at the beginning of all things and is grounded in the basis of all things or not. The question is whether reality originated on the basis of chance and necessity … luck and cunning … from what is irrational; that is whether reason, being a chance by product of irrationality and floating in an ocean of irrationality, is ultimately just as meaningless”.
4.4. A Burden Placed Equally upon All
5. Conclusions: Oscillating between Periclean and Post-Periclean Athens
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | This paper addresses open questions within a consideration of Habermas’s approach to the human being and to religion, and to religion in society, included in the following papers: (McKenna 2019, 2024a, 2024b, 2024c). For consideration of the issues discussed in this paper, see also (McKenna 2015b, 2016, 2017, 2018). |
2 | Habermas’s translation proviso takes up questions on the public use of reason in John Rawls’ political theory. It rejects the respective arguments of Paul J. Weithman and Nicholas Wolterstorff that citizens have a right to justify their public political statements on religious grounds and that no institutional filter is required ahead of the creation and enactment of law, such that the ruling majority can base law on religious or confessional grounds. |
3 | The reader may want to reference other responses to Habermas’s translation proviso that are both critical and supportive. Critical critiques include the following: (Rees 2018; Taylor 2011; Lafont 2007, 2013; Cooke 2013; Lima 2013; Adams 2006; Bretherton 2009). Supportive critiques include the following: (Aguirre 2013; Junker-Kenny 2009; Cummings 2017; Schmidt 2010). |
4 | The Hebrew word adam “is not to be understood as an individual named Adam; rather, ‘the Human’ is the whole of humanity”. (Viviano 1985, p. 15). Or, as the 2004 letter “On the Collaboration between Men and Women” notes in relation to Genesis 1:27 (“God created man in his own image, in the image of God he created him; male and female he created them”): “From the very beginning therefore, humanity is described as articulated in the male-female relationship. This is the humanity, sexually differentiated, which is explicitly declared “the image of God”. It also notes that in the second creation account in Genesis 2:7 the “generic expression Adam” is used to describe the created human being (The Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith 2004, para. 5, 6). |
5 | In the prologue to the third edition of After Virtue published in 2007, MacIntyre acknowledges that when he published the first edition of After Virtue in 1981 he was still an Aristotelian, “not yet a Thomist” (MacIntyre 2007, p. x). |
6 | MacIntyre rightly points to the controversy surrounding the Mother and Child Scheme in Ireland in the early 1950s as a notorious example of morality driven by its negative rather than positive precepts. He argues that this type of morality is to a large degree responsible for the collapse of Catholicism in Ireland. It is certainly correct that such morality discredits and discredited Catholic morality. The Mother and Child Scheme’s failure can be seen as a symptom of other forces that were to lead to the collapse of Catholicism in Ireland. The collapse of Catholicism in Ireland must be placed in a much wider context, which would include three critical trends: First, the end of the Cold War meant that the United Kingdom no longer held a strategic interest in Northern Ireland, opening the way for a political settlement for the six counties. This, in turn, transformed the hostile relationship between Ireland and the UK, releasing the need for Catholicism to bolster Irish identity. Second, Ireland underwent an economic transformation such that Irish society transitioned from being a society dominated by agriculture, poverty, and emigration to a wealthy society and hub of multiple international companies. Third, the catastrophic handling of child sexual abuse at the diocesan level and by religious orders raised serious questions about the Christianity of Catholic Ireland. |
7 | From the discussion in Section 2 and Section 3 it is clear why MacIntyre argues that not only does Aquinas express disagreement with Aristotle, with that disagreement at times being significant, but that Aquinas does not automatically prioritize Aristotle’s philosophy. MacIntyre notes that, although Aquinas adapts Aristotle’s definition of the virtues, he follows Plato and Cicero’s scheme for the relationship of the four cardinal virtues to one another. Likewise, in relation to justice, he unified Aristotle, Cicero, and Augustine’s definitions of justice into a single, albeit complex, account of justice. Critically, nothing was accepted from philosophy that was at odds with Scripture. Indeed, Aquinas integrated Aristotelian elements into a Pauline and Augustine framework, so that his synthesis was not just an integration of Christian elements into the Aristotelian framework (MacIntyre 1988, pp. 164–208). See in particular Mac-Intyre’s summation in paragraphs two and three on page 205. |
8 | In his description of Mary, Kreeft, following Aquinas, equates the female or woman with femininity—specifically, femininity as defined by Aristotle. While Aquinas rightly moves Aristotle’s highest good from the city to God, he failed to undertake the parallel necessary move for humanity, from Aristotle’s dichotomy of masculinity and femininity to the relational human being created in the image of God as male and female. Ratzinger, as Prefect (Head) of the Congregation for the Doctrine of Faith, in the 2004 letter “On the Collaboration between Men and Women”, addressed this issue. Stating that masculinity and femininity are both human traits, of which men and women are signs, masculinity and femininity are relocated to the human being. Each human being, male and female, has both masculine and feminine traits. This relocation of masculinity and femininity to the human being is a Scriptural interpretation of the creation of humanity (Gen 1:27) and the human being (Gen 2: 7, 21–22) as the image of God. This approach fully retains the theological and spiritual implications of biology while ensuring that the interpretation of the human being, created as male and female, reflects the data of Scripture (The Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith 2004, para. 16, 14, 6, footnote 5). |
References
- Adams, Nicholas. 2006. Habermas and Theology. Cambridge: CUP. [Google Scholar]
- Aguirre, Javier. 2013. Habermas’ account of the role of religion in the public sphere: A response to Cristina Lafont’s critiques through an illustrative political debate about same-sex marriage. Philosophy and Social Criticism 39: 7. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Benedict XVI. 2006. Faith, Reason and the University Memories and Reflections. September 12. Available online: www.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speeches/2006/september/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20060912_university-regensburg (accessed on 30 July 2022).
- Benedict XVI. 2008a. Lecture the Holy Father Intended to Present at the University of Rome “La Sapienza”. January 17. Available online: www.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speeches/2008/january/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20080117_la-sapienza (accessed on 1 September 2022).
- Benedict XVI. 2008b. Meeting with Representatives from the World of Culture Collège des Bernardins, Paris. September 12. Available online: www.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speeches/2008/september/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20080912_parigi-cultura (accessed on 12 September 2022).
- Benedict XVI. 2010. Meeting with the Representatives of British Society, including the Diplomatic Corps, Politicians, Academics and Business Leaders. September 17. Available online: www.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speeches/2010/september/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20100917_societa-civile (accessed on 12 September 2022).
- Benedict XVI. 2011. Address of His Holiness Benedict XVI. Reichstag Building, Berlin. September 22. Available online: www.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speeches/2011/september/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20110922_reichstag (accessed on 12 September 2022).
- Biggar, Nigel. 2009a. Not Translation, but Conversation. In Public Debate about Euthanasia. In Religious Voices in Public Places. Edited by Nigel Biggar and Linda Hogan. Oxford: OUP. [Google Scholar]
- Biggar, Nigel. 2009b. Conclusion. In Religious Voices in Public Places. Edited by Nigel Biggar and Linda Hogan. Oxford: OUP. [Google Scholar]
- Biggar, Nigel. 2023. Natural Law and Unalienable Rights. Telos 2023: 40–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bretherton, Luke. 2009. Translation, Conversation, or Hospitality? Approaches to Theological Reasons in Public Deliberation. In Religious Voices in Public Places. Edited by Nigel Biggar and Linda Hogan. Oxford: OUP. [Google Scholar]
- Brieskorn, Norbert. 2010. On the Attempt to Recall a Relationship. In An Awareness of What Is Missing Faith and Reason in a Post-Secular Age. Translated by Ciaran Cronin. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Cooke, Maeve. 2013. Violating Neutrality? Religious Validity Claims and Democratic Legitimacy. In Habermas on Religion. Edited by Craig Calhoun, Eduardo Mendieta and Jonathan VanAntwerpen. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Cummings, Andrew. 2017. The Habermas-Ratzinger Discussion Revisited: Translation as Epistemology. The Catholic Social Science Review 22: 311–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1983. The Principle of Reason: The University in the Eyes of its pupils. Diacritics 13: 2–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 1978. Politik, Kunst, Religion: Essays uber Zeitgenossische Philosophen. Stutgart: Reclam. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2002. A Conversation about God and the World. In Religion and Rationality Essays on Reason, God, and Modernity. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2003a. Faith and Knowledge. In The Future of Human Nature. Translated by Hella Beister, and Max Pensky. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2003b. On the Question: What is the ‘Good Life’? In The Future of Human Nature. Translated by William Rehg. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2003c. The Debate on the Ethical Self-Understanding of the Species. In The Future of Human Nature. Translated by Hella Beister, and Max Pensky. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2006a. Religion in the Public Sphere. European Journal of Philosophy 14: 1–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2006b. Pre-political Foundations of the Democratic Constitutional State. In The Dialectics of Secularisation on Reason and Religion. Translated by Brian McNeil. San Francisco: Ignatuis Press. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2010a. An awareness of What is Missing. In An Awareness of What Is Missing Faith and Reason in a Post-Secular Age. Translated by Ciaran Cronin. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2010b. A Reply. In An Awareness of What Is Missing Faith and Reason in a Post-Secular Age. Translated by Ciaran Cronin. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2011. “The Political”: The Rational Meaning of a Questionable Inheritance of Political Theology. In The Power of Religion on the Public Sphere. Edited by Eduardo Mendieta and Jonathan VanAntwerpen. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2013. Reply to My Critics. In Habermas and Religions. Edited by Craig Calhoun, Eduardo Mendieta and Jonathan VanAntwerpen. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2017. Postmetaphysical Thinking II. Translated by Ciaran Cronin. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2023. Also a History of Philosophy, Volume 1: The Project of a Genealogy of Postmetaphysical Thinking. Translated by Ciaran Cronin. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Junker-Kenny, Maureen. 2009. Between Postsecular Society and the Neutral State: Religion as a Resource for Public Reason. In Religious Voices in Public Places. Edited by Nigel Biggar and Linda Hogan. Oxford: OUP. [Google Scholar]
- Kreeft, Peter. 2009. The Modern Scholar: The Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas (Recorded Lecturers). Prince Frederick: Recorded Books, LLC. [Google Scholar]
- Kreeft, Peter. 2021. The Greatest Philosopher Who Ever Lived. San Francisco: Ignatius. [Google Scholar]
- Kreeft, Peter. 2023. The Marriage of Medieval Metaphysics and Modern Personalism. In Word on Fire Great Debates of Philosophy, Lecture 12. May 26. Available online: www.wordonfire.org/videos/the-great-debates-of-philosophy/the-marriage-of-medieval-metaphysics-and-modern-personalism/#:~:text=The%20Marriage%20of%20Medieval%20Metaphysics%20and%20Modern%20Personalism,St.%20Thomas%20Aquinas%20with%20the%20anthropology%20of%20Personalism (accessed on 31 August 2023).
- Lafont, Cristina. 2007. Religion in the Public Sphere: Remarks on Habermas’s Conception of Public Deliberation in Postsecular Societies. Constellations 14: 239–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lafont, Cristina. 2013. Religion in the Public Sphere. In Habermas on Religion. Edited by Craig Calhoun, Eduardo Mendieta and Jonathan VanAntwerpen. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Lima, Maria Herrara. 2013. The Anxiety of Contingency. In Habermas on Religion. Edited by Craig Calhoun, Eduardo Mendieta and Jonathan VanAntwerpen. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1985. After Virtue, 2nd ed. London: Duckworth. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1988. Which Justice, Whose Rationality. London: Duckworth. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2007. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, 3rd ed. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2009a. God, Philosophy, Universities a History of the Catholic Philosophical Tradition. London: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2009b. The Very Idea of a University: Aristotle, Newman and Us. The British Journal of Educational Studies 57: 347–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2010. On Not Knowing Where You are Going. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 84: 61–74. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2011. On Being a Theistic Philosopher in a Secularized Culture. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 84: 23–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2013. On Having Survived the Academic Moral Philosophy of the Twentieth Century. In What Happened in and to Moral Philosophy in the Twentieth Century. Edited by Fran O’Rourke. Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2021. Human Dignity: A Puzzling and Possibly Dangerous Idea? Presented at the University of Notre Dame de Nicola Centre for Ethics and Culture 2021 Fall Conference, Notre Dame, IN, USA, November 12; Entitled “I Have Called You By Name: Human Dignity in a Secular World”. FC21 Plenary—“Human Dignity: A Puzzling and Possibly Dangerous Idea?” by Alasdair MacIntyre—YouTube, Minutes 20–107. Available online: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=V727AcOoogQ (accessed on 10 December 2021).
- McKenna, Mary Frances. 2015a. Innovation within Tradition Joseph Ratzinger and Reading of the Women of Scripture. Minneapolis: Fortress Press. [Google Scholar]
- McKenna, Mary Frances. 2015b. Moral Values and Social Consensus in Democratic Secular Societies: Challenges and Responsibilities. The Heythrop Journal 56: 663–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McKenna, Mary Frances. 2016. A Consideration of Christianity’s Role in Pluralistic Society. The Way 55: 31–47. [Google Scholar]
- McKenna, Mary Frances. 2017. The idea of Europe as the Point of Encounter between Power and Freedom, Interests and Universal Values: A Consideration of Kissinger’s and Ratzinger’s Visions of Europe. European Review 25: 655–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McKenna, Mary Frances. 2018. The Promise of Enlightenment and the Incalculability of Freedom: A Consideration of Horkheimer and Adorno’s Critique of Enlightenment in Relation to Ratzinger’s Notion of Freedom. Logos 21: 114–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McKenna, Mary Frances. 2019. On the Future of Europe: Philosophical and Theological Perspectives on Pre-Political Foundations of Europe and the State from Ratzinger, Habermas, and MacIntyre. The Heythrop Journal 60: 910–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McKenna, Mary Frances. 2020. The Female Line in the Bible. Ratzinger’s Deepening of the Church’s Understanding of Tradition and Mary. Religions 11: 310. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McKenna, Mary Frances. 2022. In Search of Justice and Peace: Benedict XVI’s Questions to the Cultures and Religions of the World. Religions 13: 910. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McKenna, Mary Frances. 2024a. The Habermas Ratzinger Dialogue: Democracy and Religions in Pluralistic Societies. In Joseph Ratzinger in Dialogue with Philosophical Traditions: From Plato to Vattimo. Edited by Alejandro Sada and Tracey Rowland. London: T&T Clark, Forthcoming. [Google Scholar]
- McKenna, Mary Frances. 2024b. Benedict XVI and Edith Stein on Faith. In Joseph Ratzinger in Dialogue with Philosophical Traditions: From Plato to Vattimo. Edited by Alejandro Sada and Tracey Rowland. London: T&T Clark, Forthcoming. [Google Scholar]
- McKenna, Mary Frances. 2024c. Ratzinger and the Truly Human: Person Transcending their Human Nature to Participate in Divinity. In Oxford Handbook on Joseph Ratzinger. Edited by Francesca Aran Murphy and Tracey Rowland. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Forthcoming. [Google Scholar]
- Newman, John Henry. 2015. The Idea of a University. London: Aeterna Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 1967. The Dignity of the Human Person. In Commentary on the Documents of The Second Vatican Council. Edited by Vorgrimler. London: Burns & Oates. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 1989. Man between Reproduction and Procreation. Communio 16: 206–11. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 1990. Retrieving the Tradition concerning the Notion of Person in Theology. Communio 17: 439–54. First published 1973. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 1995. ‘In the Beginning …’: A Catholic Understanding of Creation and the Fall. Translated by Boniface Ramsey. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 2004a. Introduction to Christianity. Translated by J. R. Foster, and Michael J Miller. San Francisco: Ignatius Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 2004b. Truth and Tolerance Christian Belief and World Religions. Translated by Henry Taylor. San Francisco: Ignatius Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 2005. Culture, Identify and Church Unity. The Ecumenical Review 57: 358–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ratzinger, Joseph. 2006. That Which Holds the World Together: The Pre-political Moral Foundations of a Free State. In The Dialectics of Secularisation on Reason and Religion. Translated by Brian McNeil. San Francisco: Ignatuis Press. [Google Scholar]
- Reder, Michel, and Josef Schmitt. 2010. Habermas and Religion. In An Awareness of What Is Missing. Faith and Reason in a Post-Secular Age. Translated by Ciaran Cronin. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Rees, Dafydd Huw. 2018. The Postsecular Political Philosophy of Jürgen Habermas. Cardiff: University of Wales Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rowland, Tracey. 2017. Catholic Theology. London: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
- Schmidt, Josef. 2010. A Dialogue in which there Can Only Be Winners. In An Awareness of What Is Missing Faith and Reason in a Post-Secular Age. Translated by Ciaran Cronin. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Stein, Edith. 2000. Husserl and Aquinas: A Comparison. In Knowledge and Faith. Translated by Walter Redmond. Washington, DC: ICS Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, Charles. 2011. Why We Need a Radical Redefinition of Secularism. In The Power of Religion in the Public Sphere. Edited by Eduardo Mendieta and Jonathan Vanantwerpen. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- The Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith. 2004. Letter to the Bishops of the Catholic Church on the Collaboration between Men and Women in the Church and the World. Available online: http://www.vatican.va/roman_curia/congregations/cfaith/documents/rc_con_cfaith_doc_20040731_collaboration_en.html (accessed on 6 May 2008).
- Thucydides. 1972. History of the Peloponnesian War. Translated by Rex Warner. London: Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- Urbinati, Nadia. 2012. Laïcité in Reverse: Mono-Religious Democracies and the Issue of Religion in the Public Sphere. Constellations 7: 1. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Viviano, Pauline. 1985. Genesis, Collegeville Bible Commentary. 2 vols. Collegeville: Liturgical Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
McKenna, M.F. Jürgen Habermas’s Translation of the Human Being as Created in the Image of God: Perspectives from Joseph Ratzinger and Alasdair MacIntyre. Religions 2024, 15, 118. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15010118
McKenna MF. Jürgen Habermas’s Translation of the Human Being as Created in the Image of God: Perspectives from Joseph Ratzinger and Alasdair MacIntyre. Religions. 2024; 15(1):118. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15010118
Chicago/Turabian StyleMcKenna, Mary Frances. 2024. "Jürgen Habermas’s Translation of the Human Being as Created in the Image of God: Perspectives from Joseph Ratzinger and Alasdair MacIntyre" Religions 15, no. 1: 118. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15010118
APA StyleMcKenna, M. F. (2024). Jürgen Habermas’s Translation of the Human Being as Created in the Image of God: Perspectives from Joseph Ratzinger and Alasdair MacIntyre. Religions, 15(1), 118. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15010118