God as “The Highest and Most Elevated Thing”: Contributions to the Theological, Phenomenological Interpretations of God-Experiences in Heidegger, Conrad-Martius, and Stein
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Phenomenological Concept of God-Experiences in Heidegger, Conrad-Martius, and Stein: Coincidences and Differences
2.1. Heidegger’s Arguments for and Against the Onto-Theological Analyses of God-Experiences
[…] if philosophy has resolved to make the decisive existential potentiality of factual life visible and graspable, i.e. if philosophy has radically and unequivocally decided to do so, without any ideological enthusiasm, to set factual life on its own footing from its own factual possibilities, i.e. if philosophy is fundamentally atheistic and understands this, then it has made a decisive choice and has won factual life as its object in terms of its facticity.
The religious desire of experience, and the strive for the presence of Jesus as genuine, is only possible as a result of a basic experience. Such experiences are not freely available by following the regulations of church law. The ‘knowledge’ about them, and their essence, arises only from the real experience. Such an experience is only truly effective in a closed context of experience (stream of experience), it is not transferable and evocable by description.(Cf. Heidegger (1995, GA 60, p. 334))
Questionability is not religious, but rather it may really lead into a situation of religious decision for the first time. I do not behave religiously in philosophizing, even if I as a philosopher can be a religious man. “But here is the art”: to philosophize and thereby to be genuinely religious, i.e., to take up factically its wordly, historical task in philosophizing, in action, and a world of action, not in religious ideology and phantasy.
Philosophy, in its radical questionability—a questionability depending upon itself alone—must be in principle atheistic. In virtue of its fundamental tendency, philosophy may not have the daring [of claiming] to possess God and to be able to define Him. The more radical philosophy is, the more decisively it is an “away” from Him, that is to say, precisely in radically carrying out the “away”, it is a specifically difficult [being] “with” him.9
Atheistic not in the sense of a theory as materialism or the like. Every philosophy, which understands itself in what it is, must know as the factual how of the interpretation of life just then, if it still has a “suspicion” of God, that the pulling back of life to itself, religiously spoken, is a lifting of the hand against God. But with this alone it stands honestly, i.e., according to the possibility available to it as such before God; atheistically means here: keeping free of seductive, religiousness merely eloquent concern. Whether the very idea of a philosophy of religion, and even if it makes its calculation without the facticity of man, is not a pure absurdity?(Cf. Heidegger (2005, HGA 62, p. 363))
To begin speaking of God does not necessarily mean beginning to speak about Him as soon as He is there, as soon as He is present, but may very well be taken to mean beginning to speak about Him by preparing for his presence and thereby outlining His (as yet empty) place—the place He will fill in as soon as He comes. For, lacking such a place, He would have, as it were, nowhere to arrive.(Cf. (Fehér 1996, p. 40))
The same thing that happens with the word res happens with the name corresponding to res, dinc; for dinc means every single thing that somehow is. Accordingly Meister Eckhart uses the word dinc as much for God as for the soul. God is to him “the highest and most elevated thing [dinc]”. The soul is a “great thing”. With this, this Meister of thinking by no means wishes to say that God and the soul would be the same as a block of stone, a material object; dinc is here a careful and unassuming name for anything that is at all.
2.2. Hedwig Conrad-Martius and Edith Stein, the Critique of Heidegger’s Interpretation, On the Possibility for the Philosophical Analysis of God
2.2.1. Hedwig Conrad-Martius Critique
A timelessness, as such, includes the indifference and thus the absolute autonomy of existence. But apart from the fact that the temporal mode of existence—let alone the spatial—is a constituent characteristic everywhere, since God as the most real of all real beings must be thought of as super-spatial and super-temporal (but this idea by no means includes an objective re-meaning)—apart from this, temporality or spatiality cannot be cited as a moment that affects the essence of the thing in itself, because their presence is always only the objective consequence of a specifically designed real existence, but not the precondition for it: something is not real because it exists spatially or temporally, but it exists spatially and temporally because it essentially belongs to a certain mode of reality. Or more generally: it can only come to a spatiotemporal positing because it is constituted in itself as reality and thus fulfills the preconditions that are necessary for the possibility of a spatio-temporal positing.(Cf. Conrad-Martius (1923, p. 164))
Therefore, the revelation of God is at the same time born of reality by the creation, as the precondition of phenomenological thinking. In this sense, the existence of God discloses itself, as the reality in itself, in the real existential being. This is the gate of being, which is not the precondition but the main possibility of being.
But how does Heidegger evaluate this ontological position, which almost inevitably leads to—metaphysics? Do we not have a proof of God in our hands? Doesn’t one’s own inner dialectic of this existential finitude and nullity lead to existential eternity? Or better still [and in order to tie in with the deepest proofs of God of all philosophical mystics up to Descartes]: can we at all in the intuitive conception of this creatural I, which is temporally finite from its deepest ground, which is unfounded and unfounded in itself, without at the same time realizing the conception of God? Heidegger not only does not draw this conclusion, he simply cuts it off with emphatic philosophical intention.
2.2.2. Edith Stein’s Approaches
It was revealed to us as being in person, as being in three persons. If the Creator is the archetype of creation, is it not necessary to find in creation an image, however distant, of the triune unity of primordial-original being? Historically, it is shown that the effort to grasp the doctrine of revelation from the concept of the most holy Trinity gave rise to the philosophical concepts of ‘hypostasis’ and ‘person’.
3. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Cf. Heidegger (1985a, p. 91.): “Without that theological origin I would never have arrived to the path of thinking.” [Ohne diese theologische Herkunft wäre ich nie auf dem Weg des Denkens gelangt.]; Cf. also: (Pöggeler 1990, p. 28f.): “[…] I must say that I am not a philosopher. I do not even claim to be doing anything of the sort; I have no intention to do that either. […] I work concretely and factically out of my ’I am’, out of my intellectual and wholly factic origin […] To this facticity of mine belongs what I briefly call the fact that I am a ’Christian theologian”. |
2 | “The past two years, in which I have take pains to reach a fundamental clarification of my philosophical standpoint and so have laid asaid all specialised scholastic tasks, have led me to results for which, had I any ties beyond philosophical ones, I could not have preserved the freedom of conviction and of what I have taught. Epistemological insights, extending as far as the theory of historical knowledge, have made me the system of Catholicism problematic and unacceptable to me—but not Christianity and metaphysics (the latter, to be sure, in a new sense). […] I believe that I have an inner call to philosophy and that by answering in research and teaching I can do what lies withing my powers for the internal vocation of the inner man—and only for this—and thus justify my existence and work itself before God”. Cf. Casper (1980, p. 536). For more phenomenological interpretations precisely in this topic Cf.: van Buren and Kisiel (1994). |
3 | |
4 | |
5 | Cf. Joachim W. Storck (1989, Nr. 8.): “My own work is very concentrated, principled and concrete: basic problems of phenomenological methodology, getting free from the last dross of learned points of view—constant new penetration to the real origins, preliminary work for the Phenomenology of Religious Consciousness—tight setting for intensive, high quality academic effectiveness, constant learning in the community with Husserl”. |
6 | |
7 | Cf. Fehér (1996, p. 38): “Heidegger takes up Husserl’s password “Back tot he things themselves” and soon turns it against Husserl. He does so by interpreting the subject matter of philosophy, i.e., the “thing itself”, in terms of life rather than transcendental consciousness”. |
8 | Cf. Heidegger (1995, HGA 60, p. 53). In Phenomenology of Religious Life—Phänomenologie des religiösen Lebens (HGA 60), Heidegger sought to interpret the Christian life in phenomenological terms, while also discussing the question whether Christianity should be construed as historically defined. Heidegger thus connected the philosophical discussion of religion as a phenomenon with the character of the religious life taken in the context of factical life. According to Heidegger, every philosophical question originates from the latter, which determines such questions pre-theoretically, while the tradition of early Christianity can also only be understood historically in such terms. For more to this topic, Cf. (Theodore Kisiel 1993; Holger Zaborowski 2004; Johannes Schaber 2004; Philippe Capelle 2004; Anna Jani 2016). |
9 | Cf. Heidegger (1994, HGA 61, p. 197). I have partly adopted Fehér’s translation in “Heidegger’s Understanding of the Atheism of Philosophy”, 51, and his adoption of John D. Caputo’s translation in his Heidegger and Theology. The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger, 278. |
10 | |
11 | Cf. here: Heidegger (2004, HGA 9, p. 63): “All the theological concepts of existence centered on faith mean a specific transition of existence, in which pre-Christian and Christian existence are united in their own way. This transitional character motivates the characteristic multidimensionality of the theological term, which cannot be discussed in detail here”. |
12 | Cf. Heidegger (2004, HGA 9, p. 65): “Philosophy is the formally indicating ontological corrective of the ontic, and namely pre-Christian content of the basic theological concepts”. |
13 | Cf. (Heidegger 1985b, p. 4): “Theology wishes to go forward from a revival of belief, its basic relationship to the reality which it thematizes, so that it may arrive at an original explication of the being of man toward God, which involves the disengagement of the fundamental question of man from the traditional systematic approach of dogmatics. For this systematic approach is based upon a philosophical and conceptual system which has created confusion in both the question of man and the question of God and all the more in the question of the relationship of man to God”. |
14 | Cf. to this also Fehér M.’s remarkable note, Fehér (1996, p. 57): “Heidegger’s notion of philosophy’s “atheism” is thus not atheistic in any usual sense of the term, but it is rather, conversely, insired very much by a religious-theological motivation or attitude or comportment. The latter is labelled “atheistic” precisely by another, alternatively or differently religious attitude. It is, in other words, “atheistic” only if we tacitly orient religiously toward one among many possible religious comportments, the one namely, for which questioning is impious, which prohibits questioning, for which radical questioning is audacity, presumptuousness.” |
15 | Cf. von Herrmann (2001, p. 119): “Whereas in fundamental-ontological thinking uncovering of a being is made pos-sible by a disclosing-thrown projecting-open of the truth of being, in being-historical thinking, disclosing-letting-itself-be-sheltered (entbergende Sichbergenlassen) of the throwing-projecting truth of be-ing belongs to the full essential swaying of the truth of being. This is to say that through en-grounding-projecting-opening and through letting-itself-be-sheltered of what is projected-open in disclosing a being, there occurs a restauration of a being ‘from within the truth of be-ing’ (GA 65, 11; CP, 8)—after a being has been abandoned for so long by be-ing, i.e., abandoned by such a sheltering”. |
16 | |
17 | Cf. to it in details (Jani 2015). |
18 | Cf. Stein (2009, p. 20): “Starting from the simple, immediately certain fact of being, we have come to distinguish three spheres of being: [1] the immanent sphere, which is immediately and inseparably close to us and of which we are conscious, [2] a transcendent sphere, which heralds itself in immanence, and [3] a third sphere radically different in its being from the immanent sphere as well as from this transparent sphere. Of this pure being we have said so far that it discloses itself in immanent being only “in our idea”, whereas we should take the evincing of finite substances in immanence as evidence of their existence [Existenzbekundung]. But what we have said does not rule out that the existence of this pure being may also be evinced in immanence”. |
References
- Backmann, Jussi. 2015. Complicated Presence. Heidegger and the Postmetaphysical Unity of Being. Albany: SUNY Press. [Google Scholar]
- Capelle, Philippe. 2004. ‘Katholizismus,’ ‘Protestantismus,’ ‘Christentum’ und ‘Religion’ im Denken Martin Heideggers: Tragweite und Abgrenzungen. Heidegger und die Anfänge Seines Denkens 1: 346–71. [Google Scholar]
- Casper, Bernhard. 1980. Martin Heidegger und die Theologische Fakultät Freiburg 1909–1923. In Kirche am Oberrhein. Festschrift für Wolfgang Müller. Edited by Richard Bäumler, Karl Suso Frank and Hugo Ott. Freiburger Diözesan Archiv, vol. 100. Freiburg i. Br.: Herder, pp. 534–41. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1923. Realontologie. In Jahrbuch für Philosophie und Phänomenologische Forschung 6. Edited by Edmund Husserl. Halle: Max Niemeyer, p. 164. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1963a. Dasein, Substantialität, Seele. In Schriften zur Philosophie. Erster Band. Edited by Eberhart Avé-Lallemant. München: Kösel, pp. 194–228. [Google Scholar]
- Conrad-Martius, Hedwig. 1963b. Heideggers ‘Sein und Zeit’. In Schriften zur Philosophie. Erster Band. Edited by Eberhart Avé-Lallemant. München: Kösel, pp. 185–94. [Google Scholar]
- Fehér, M. István. 1996. Heidegger’s Understanding of the Atheism of Philosophy: Philosophy, Theology, and Religion on His Way to Being and Time = Existentia. An International Journal of Philosophy VI–VII: 33–65. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1971. On the Way to Language. New York: Harper & Row. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1978a. Die Kategorien- und Bedeutungslehre des Duns Scotus. In Frühe Schriften. Frankfurt a. M.: Vittorio Klostermann, pp. 189–412. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1978b. Frühe Schriften. Edited by Friedrich Wilhelm von Herrmann. HGA 1. Frankfurt a. M.: Vittorio Klostermann. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1985a. Aus einem Gespräch von der Sprache. Zwischen einem Japaner und einem Fragenden. In Ibid. Unterwegs zur Sprache. Edited by Friedrich Wilhelm von Herrmann. HGA 12. Frankfurt a. M.: Vittorio Klostermann, pp. 79–144. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1985b. History of the Concept of Time. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1993. Building Dwelling Thinking. In Basic Writings from Being and Time to the Task of Thinking. Edited by David Farrell Krell. San Francisco: HarperCollins Publisher, pp. 343–65. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1994. Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zu Aristoteles. Edited by Käte Bröcker-Oltmanns. HGA 61. Frankfurt a. M.: Vittorio Klostermann. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1995. Phänomenologie des Religiösen Lebens. Edited by Claudius Strube. HGA 60. Frankfurt a. M.: Vittorio Klostermann. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1998. Phenomenology and Theology. In Pathmarks. Edited by William McNail. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 39–63. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 2002. The End of the Philosophy and the Task of Thinking. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 2004. Wegmarken. Edited by Friedrich Wilhelm von Herrmann. HGA 9. Frankfurt a. M.: Vittorio Klostermann. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 2005. Phänomenologische Interpretationen ausgewählter Abhandlungen des Aristoteles zu Ontologie und Logik. Edited by Günther Neumann. HGA 62. Frankfurt a. M.: Vittorio Klostermann. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 2007a. Mein Weg in die Phänomenologie. In Ibid. Zur Sache des Denkens. Edited by Friedrich Wilhelm von Herrmann. GA 14. Frankfurt a. M.: Vittorio Klostermann, pp. 91–103. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 2007b. Phänomenologie der Anschauung und des Ausdrucks. Edited by Claudius Strube. HGA 59. Frankfurt a. M.: Vittorio Klostermann. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 2012a. Bremen and Freiburg Lectures. Insight into That Which Is. Translated by Andrew J. Mitchell. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 2012b. Contribution to Philosophy (Of the Event). Bloomington: Indiana University Press, chap. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 2012c. The Thing. In Bremen and Freiburg Lectures. Insight into That Which Is. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 5–23. [Google Scholar]
- Jani, Anna. 2015. Edith Steins Denkweg von der Phänomenologie zur Seinsphilosophie. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann. [Google Scholar]
- Jani, Anna. 2016. Historicity and Christian Life Experience in the Early Philosophy of Martin Heidegger. Forum Philosophicum, International Journal for Philosophy 21: 29–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jani, Anna. 2017. Religiöses Erlebnis und Werterkenntnis: Zum Fragment der religionsphilosophischen ‘Aufzeichnungen’ Adolf Reinachs. In Jahrbuch für Religionsphilosophie 16. Edited by Markus Enders and Holger Zaborowski. Freiburf: Karl Alber, pp. 185–216. [Google Scholar]
- Jani, Anna. 2020. Historicity and Religiosity in Heidegger’s Interpretation of the Reality: With an Outlook to Adolf Reinach’s contribution to Heidegger’s Phenomenological Conception. Human Studies 43: 409–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jani, Anna. 2022. The Ontological Roots of the Phenomenology. Rethinking the History of Phenomenology and Its Religious Turn. New York and London: Lexington. [Google Scholar]
- Kisiel, Theodore. 1993. The Religion Courses (1920–21). In The Genesis of Heidegger’s “Being and Time”. Edited by Theodore Kisiel. Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 149–220. [Google Scholar]
- Pöggeler, Otto. 1990. Drei Briefe Heideggers an Karl Löwith. In Zur philosophischen Aktualität Heidegger Bd. 2. Im Gespräch der Zeit. Otto P0ggeler. Frankfurt a. M.: Klostermann, pp. 27–39. [Google Scholar]
- Pöggeler, Otto. 1999. Heidegger in Seiner Zeit. München: Wilhelm Fink. [Google Scholar]
- Schaber, Johannes. 2004. Martin Heideggers ‘Herkunft’ im Spiegel der Theologie- und Kirchengeschichte des 19. und beginnenden 20. Jahrhunderts. In Heidegger-Jahrbuch 1. Heidegger und die Anfänge seines Denkens. Edited by Alfred Denker, Hans-Helmuth Gander and Holger Zaborowski. Freiburg i. Br.: Karl Alber, pp. 159–84. [Google Scholar]
- Stein, Edith. 2002. Finite and Eternal Being: An Attempt at an Ascent to the Meaning of Being. In The Collected Works of Edith Stein. Translated by Kurt F. Reinhardt. Washington, DC: Institute of Carmelit Studies, vol. 9. [Google Scholar]
- Stein, Edith. 2009. Potency and Act. In The Collected Works of Edith Stein XI. Translated by Walter Redmond. Washington, DC: ICS Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Stein, Edith. 2010. Endliches und ewiges Sein: Versuch eines Aufstiegs zum Sinn des Seins. In Edith Stein Gesamtausgabe 11/12. Edited by Andreas Uwe Müller. Freiburg: Herder. [Google Scholar]
- Storck, Joachim W., ed. 1989. Martin Heidegger–Elisabeth Blochmann Briefwechsel 1918–1969. Marbach am Neckar: Deutsche Schillergesellschaft. [Google Scholar]
- van Buren, John, and Theodore Kisiel, eds. 1994. Reading Heidegger from the Start: Essays in His Earliest Thought. Albany: SUNY Press. [Google Scholar]
- von Herrmann, Friedrich-Wilhelm. 2001. Contributions to Philosophy and Enowning-Historical Thinking. In Companion to Heidegger’s Contributions to Philosophy. Edited by Charles E. Scott, Susan M. Schoenbohm, Daniela Vallega-Neu and Alejando Vallega. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 105–29. [Google Scholar]
- Zaborowski, Holger. 2004. ‘Herkunft aber bleibt stets Zukunft’: Anmerkungen zur religiösen und theo- logischen Dimension des Denkweges Martin Heideggers bis 1919. In Heidegger-Jahrbuch 1. Heidegger und die Anfänge seines Denkens. Edited by Alfred Denker, Hans- Helmuth Gander and Holger Zaborowski. Freiburg: Alber, pp. 123–58. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Jani, A. God as “The Highest and Most Elevated Thing”: Contributions to the Theological, Phenomenological Interpretations of God-Experiences in Heidegger, Conrad-Martius, and Stein. Religions 2023, 14, 1064. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14081064
Jani A. God as “The Highest and Most Elevated Thing”: Contributions to the Theological, Phenomenological Interpretations of God-Experiences in Heidegger, Conrad-Martius, and Stein. Religions. 2023; 14(8):1064. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14081064
Chicago/Turabian StyleJani, Anna. 2023. "God as “The Highest and Most Elevated Thing”: Contributions to the Theological, Phenomenological Interpretations of God-Experiences in Heidegger, Conrad-Martius, and Stein" Religions 14, no. 8: 1064. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14081064
APA StyleJani, A. (2023). God as “The Highest and Most Elevated Thing”: Contributions to the Theological, Phenomenological Interpretations of God-Experiences in Heidegger, Conrad-Martius, and Stein. Religions, 14(8), 1064. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14081064