A Critical Assessment of Shafer-Landau’s Ethical Non-Naturalism
Abstract
:1. Introduction
- (i)
- Do issues about emergent properties generalize to other areas of philosophy, especially those in metaethics? For two reasons, the answer is yes. First, discussions of emergence began in the philosophy of science, and debates about property emergence vs. Nagelian or property reduction surfaced in a wide range of topics, e.g., biology, systems theory, chemistry, and philosophy of mind. Second, Frank Jackson’s defense of staunch naturalism (see below) addressed alleged emergent properties in four areas of philosophy: indexical properties associated with the first-person point of view, properties of consciousness, secondary qualities, and normative, e.g., moral properties (Jackson 1998; Sturgeon 1986).
- (ii)
- Some claim that Shafer-Landau seldom, if ever, talks about emergent properties in developing his ontology for moral realism. Thus, critiques of emergent properties (see below) are beside the point. I acknowledge his lack of explicit reference to emergent properties. However, I think that is because his discussion fails to appropriate insights from philosophy of science and mind that are relevant to his views. Discussions about ethical non-naturalism within metaethics seldom bring issues about emergent properties into their discussions.
- (iii)
- Objection: Employment of an emergence theory for moral properties would be a form of naturalism. Since Shafer-Landau in an ethical non-naturalist, this is something he simply would not do. We have already seen reasons for thinking that Shafer-Landau does, in fact, quantify over emergent moral properties, and I will not rehearse those. But what should we make of this objection?
2. The Nature of Naturalism as a Worldview: Preliminary Remarks
2.1. Staunch vs. Faint-Hearted Naturalism
2.2. Emergent vs. Structurally Supervenient Properties
3. Why Contemporary Naturalists Ought to Be Staunch Naturalists (and Most Are)
3.1. The Inner Logic of Scientific/Philosophical Naturalism
3.2. The Naturalist Epistemic Attitude
Every fact in the universe is in principle knowable and understandable by human investigators. Because reality is physical, and because science concerns the investigation of physical reality, and because there are no limits on what we can know of physical reality, it follows that all facts are knowable and understandable by us.
Can we gain any deeper insight into what makes the problem of consciousness run against the grain of our thinking? Are our modes of theorizing about the world of the wrong shape to extend to the nature of mind? I think we can discern a characteristic structure possessed by successful scientific theories, a structure that is unsuitable for explaining consciousness… Is there a “grammar” to science that fits the physical world but becomes shaky when applied to the mental world? Perhaps the most basic aspect of thought is the operation of combination. This is the way in which we think of complex entities as resulting from the arrangement of simpler parts. There are three aspects to this basic idea: the atoms we start with, the laws we use to combine them, and the resulting complexes… I think it is clear that this mode of understanding is central to what we think of as scientific theory; our scientific faculty involves representing the world in this combinatorial style.
3.3. The Naturalist Grand Story
3.4. The Naturalist Ontology
- (a)
- Faint-Hearted vs. Staunch Naturalism One More Time
- (b)
- The Location Problem
3.5. The Logic of the Standard Mereological Hierarchy
Today, any proposed general ontology of the world…is defined by its relation to materialism, the position that the world consists exclusively of bits of matter and structures made up of bits of matter, all behaving in accordance with physical law. Everything is an arrangement of matter and living organisms and minded creatures are no exceptions.(Kim 2018)
- Entities should conform to the naturalist epistemology.
- Entities should conform to the naturalist Grand Story.
- Entities should bear a relevant similarity to those found in chemistry and physics or be capable of one-to-one or one-to-many correlation with entities in chemistry/physics or depend necessarily on entities in chemistry/physics. This is an expression of microphysical priority.
4. Problems with Naturalistic Emergent Properties
4.1. The View
4.2. Seven Criticisms of the View
5. Ontological Difficulties with Shafer-Landau’s Ethical Non-Naturalism
5.1. Three Features of Shafer-Landau’s Ontology13
5.1.1. Non-Natural Moral Properties and Facts
5.1.2. Universal Moral Laws and Absolutism
5.1.3. Where Do Moral Standards Come From?
5.2. The Problematic Nature of Contingent Brute Facts
6. Difficulties with Shafer-Landau’s Moral Epistemology
6.1. A Precis of Shafer-Landau’s Moral Epistemology
6.2. An Evolutionary Argument against Shafer-Landau’s Epistemology
6.3. The Main Ethical Non-Naturalist Rejoinder to the Evolutionary Argument
Yes! Absolutely! Objective moral values are clearly a part of reality… The question of course, is how this all came to be… These atheistic theories tell us that we ought to act morally, but they do so with a conception of the universe that makes it difficult to see why and how we should believe that these shared moral values have anything like true normative objectivity. Objective morality may not be impossible on an atheistic worldview, but it feels like an ad hoc addition.
6.4. Responding to Leibowitz’s Defeaters for Evolutionary Debunking Arguments
- Evolution provides the best explanation of moral phenomena.
- Evolutionary explanations of moral phenomena do not require that our moral judgements are true.
- If (2), then the chance of any one of our moral judgements being true is slim.
- If the chance of any one of our moral judgments being true is slim, then even after rational reflection the chance of any one of our moral judgments being true remains slim.
- If even after rational reflection the chance of any one of our moral judgments being true remains slim, then each one of our moral judgments is unjustified.
- Therefore, each one of our moral judgments is unjustified.
- Evolution provides the best explanation of moral phenomena.
- Evolutionary explanations of moral phenomena do not require that our moral judgments are true.
- If (2), then we have no reason to believe of any one of our moral judgments that it is true.
- If we have no reason to believe of any of our moral judgments that it is true, then even after rational reflection we have no reason to believe of any one of our moral judgments that it is true.
- If even after rational reflection we have no reason to believe of any one of our moral judgments that it is true, then each of our moral judgments is unjustified.
- Therefore, each one of our moral judgments is unjustified.
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | |
2 | Kripke (1972). Interestingly, in the article entitled “Moral Realism” in the online Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, the author is preoccupied with the ontology of moral realism and the truth conditions of moral claims so interpreted. Other subareas of the article are discussed in relation to the ontological issues. A short section covers semantic issues, but the discussion is preoccupied with minmalism (a version of redundancy theory for truth) and its problems. Synthetic/analytic issues are not significantly present in the artricle. See Sayre-McCord (2021). |
3 | Shafer-Landau (2003), pp. 98–114. Interestingly, Shafer-Landau explicitly claims that causal closure issues and irreducible properties of consciousness are structurally paralled with irreducible moral properties. |
4 | Strawson (2006), pp. 3–31. The quote is from page 3. Strawson’s idiosyncratic use of “physicalism” includes irreducible experiential states as a kind of physical state, and he distinguishes his view from “physicSalism”, the faith commitment that the nature or essence of all concrete reality can in principle be captured in the terms of physics. The definition of “physicalism” in the quote is not his own panpsychist one, but is more akin to physicSalism and what we mean by staunch naturalism. |
5 | For my purposes, I set aside the distinction between Global Naturalists (who deny the existence of abstract objects) and Local Naturalists (who accept abstract objects, usually with the proviso that the only abstract objects that are exemplified must be physical properties or relations.) For a good treatment of this distinction put in different terms and including a case that naturalists ought to be Global, see Grossmann (1992), pp. 1–46; Rickabaugh and Moreland (2023), chp. two. |
6 | |
7 | |
8 | |
9 | |
10 | When John Searle developed his biological naturalism, he dismissed the problem of (genuinely) emergent properties such as those constituting consciousness by making a tight analogy between them and structurally supervenient properties, e.g., solidity, liquidity. This allowed him to find emergent mental properties to be ordinary physical, structural ones and their appearance to be unsurprising. See Searle (1992), pp. xii, 13–19, 25–28, 32, 56–57, 85–93, 95, 118–24. For a response to Searle, See Moreland (2008), chp. three. |
11 | I am indebted to an anonymous referee for these suggestions. |
12 | |
13 | Important sources for Shafer-Landau’s ontology are (Shafer-Landau 2003, 2004). |
14 | Roughly, the view that holds two theses: psychological non-cognitivism (ethical claims express mental states with a world-to-mind direction of fit, e.g., desires, pro-attitudes) and semantic ideationalism (the semantic contents of an ethical claim are objectively given their associated mental states such that an expression of some ethical claim p expresses confidence or agreement with p that just is the meaning of “p is true.” |
15 | I think Shafer-Landau needs “murders” rather than “kills” doing the latter. In cases of a car accident, self-defense, war, or capital punishment, the wrongness of killing is controversial to say the least. |
16 | Brackets mine. |
17 | |
18 |
References
- BonJour, Laurence. 1998. In Defense of Pure Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Chalmers, David J. 2017. The Combination Problem for Panpsychism. In Panpsychism: Contemporary Perspectives. Edited by Godehard Brüntrup and Ludwig Jaskolla. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 204–6. [Google Scholar]
- Chisholm, Roderick. 1989. On Metaphysics. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. [Google Scholar]
- Craig, William Lane, and J. P. Moreland. 2009. The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology. Malden: Wiley Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Grossmann, Reinhardt. 1992. The Existence of the World. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Inman, Ross. 2019. Substance and the Fundamentality of the Familiar. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Jackson, Frank. 1998. From Metaphysics to Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kim, Jaegwon. 1998. Mind in a Physical World. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kim, Jaegwon. 2011. Philosophy of Mind, 3rd ed. Boulder: Westview Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kim, Jaegwon. 2018. Against Cartesian Dualism. In The Blackwell Companion to Substance. Dualism. Edited by Jonathan J. Loose, Angus J. L. Menuge and J. P. Moreland. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell, pp. 152–67. [Google Scholar]
- Kripke, Saul. 1972. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Leibowitz, Uri D. 2021. A dilemma for evolutionary debunking arguments. Philosophical Studies 178: 45–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Linsky, Bernard, and Edward N. Zath. 1995. Naturalized Platonism versus Platonized Naturalism. The Journal of Philosophy 92: 525–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Linville, Mark D. 2009. The Moral Argument. In The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology. Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 391–448. [Google Scholar]
- Mackie, John L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. London: Penguin Books. [Google Scholar]
- McGinn, Colin. 1999. The Mysterious Flame. New York: Basic Books. [Google Scholar]
- Melnyk, Andrew. 2019. Physicalism—Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Oxfordshire: Taylor and Francis. Available online: https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/physicalism/v-1 (accessed on 13 April 2023).
- Miller, Christian. 2006. Review Essay: Russ Shafer-Landau’s Moral Realism: A Defense. Social Theory and Practice 32: 311–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moreland, J. P. 2008. Consciousness and the Existence of God. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Moreland, J. P. 2009. The Recalcitrant Imago Dei: Human Persons and the Failure of Naturalism. London: S. C. M. Press, pp. 165–80. [Google Scholar]
- Moreland, J. P. 2012. A Reluctant Traveler’s Guide for Slouching Towards Theism: A Philosophical Note on Nagel’s Mind and Cosmos. Philosophia Christi 14: 415–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moreland, J. P. 2013. Exemplification and Constituent Realism: A Clarification and Modest Defense. Axiomathes 23: 247–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moreland, J. P. 2018. Scientism and Secularism: Learning to Respond to a Dangerous Ideology. Wheaton: Crossway. [Google Scholar]
- Moreland, J. P. 2020. Wielenberg and Emergence: Borrowed Capital on the Cheap. In God and Morality: What Is the Best Account of Objective Moral Values and Duties? Edited by Adam Lloyd Johnson. New York: Routledge, pp. 93–114. [Google Scholar]
- Moreland, J. P., and David Horner. forthcoming. Metaethics and Worldview. Nashville: Broadman & Hollman.
- Morris, Dolores G. 2021. Believing Philosophy. Grand Rapids: Zondervan. [Google Scholar]
- Murphy, Nancey. 2018. For Nonreductive Physicalism. In The Blackwell Companion to Substance Dualism. Edited by Jonathan Loose, Angus Menuge and J. P. Moreland. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 317–27. [Google Scholar]
- Nagel, Ernest. 1979. The Structure of Science. Indianapolis: Hackett. [Google Scholar]
- Nagel, Thomas. 1997. The Last Word. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nagel, Thomas. 2012. Mind and Cosmos. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- O’Connor, Timothy. 2000. Persons & Causes. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Page, Ben. 2020. Arguing to Theism from Consciousness. Faith & Philosophy 37: 336–62. [Google Scholar]
- Papineau, David. 1993. Philosophical Naturalism. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Papineau, David. 2001. The Rise of Physicalism. In Physicalism and Its Discontents. Edited by Carl Gillett and Barry Loewer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 3–36. [Google Scholar]
- Papineau, David. 2002. Thinking about Consciousness. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Avin. 1993. Warrant and Proper Function. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pruss, Alexander. 2009. The Leibnizian Cosmological Argument. In The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology. Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland. Malden: Wiley Blackwell, pp. 24–100. [Google Scholar]
- Rachels, James. 1990. Created from Animals. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Reppert, Victor. 2009. The Argument from Reason. In The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology. Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 345–90. [Google Scholar]
- Rickabaugh, Brandon, and J. P. Moreland. 2023. The Substance of Consciousness: A Comprehensive Defense of Contemporary Substance Dualism. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell, chp. two. [Google Scholar]
- Rosenberg, Alex. 1996. A Field Guide to Recent Species of Naturalism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47: 1–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ruse, Michael, and E. O. Wilson. 1986. Moral Philosophy as Applied Science. Philosophy 61: 173–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Ruse, Michael. 1989. Evolutionary Theory and Christian Ethics. In The Darwinian Paradigm. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Sayre-McCord, Geoff. 2021. Moral Realism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/moral-realism/ (accessed on 13 April 2023).
- Searle, John. 1992. The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sellars, Wilfrid. 1963. Science, Perception, and Reality. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. [Google Scholar]
- Shafer-Landau, Russ. 2003. Moral Realism: A Defence. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Shafer-Landau, Russ. 2004. Whatever Happened to Good and Evil. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Strawson, Galen. 2006. Realistic Monism: Why Physicalism Entails Panpsychism. In Consciousness and Its Place in Nature. Edited by Anthony Freeman. Exeter: Imprint Academic, pp. 3–31. [Google Scholar]
- Sturgeon, Nicholas L. 1986. Harman on Moral Explanations ofNatural Facts. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 24: 69–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tabaczek, Mariusz. 2019. Emergence. Notre Dame: University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wagner, Steven J., and Richard Warner. 1993. Naturalism: A Critical Appraisal. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Moreland, J.P. A Critical Assessment of Shafer-Landau’s Ethical Non-Naturalism. Religions 2023, 14, 546. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14040546
Moreland JP. A Critical Assessment of Shafer-Landau’s Ethical Non-Naturalism. Religions. 2023; 14(4):546. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14040546
Chicago/Turabian StyleMoreland, J. P. 2023. "A Critical Assessment of Shafer-Landau’s Ethical Non-Naturalism" Religions 14, no. 4: 546. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14040546
APA StyleMoreland, J. P. (2023). A Critical Assessment of Shafer-Landau’s Ethical Non-Naturalism. Religions, 14(4), 546. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14040546