Gass is a selective reader, who has learned from authors that left ideas and insights, not ruins, middens, and fossils. They are living authors who contribute to valuable beliefs and convictions worth perpetrating, because, in Gass’s view, they make us better humans, more intelligent, courageous, and moral. Gass might argue that for each virtue articulated and promulgated by these authors, seven vices have followed, and that consequently in spite of the good these authors have done (himself included), in the end, the world is worse for what they thought and wrote. Gass does think the world is worse because Christians go to church and believe in myths and superstitions, but he does not think the world is worse because of the authors in his temple of texts. In fact, we need them.
4.1. Gass’s Nihilism
Is Gass’s nihilism, thus, plausible? His definition of evil as “a mosaic made of petty little pieces placed in malignant position (
Gass 2006, p. 414) implies that it takes an accumulation of acts to constitute evil. It implies we can keep a ledger of virtues on one side and then seven vices they cause on the other. If we could, then certainly the world is much worse off every passing day. However, this seems an impossible ledger to keep for two reasons. First, we cannot neatly separate virtues and vices into discreet, measuring units. If we were to pull out a vice, so to speak, and number it on the right side of the ledger, then we would also be pulling out many choices, effects inescapably connected to the vice. The ledger would be very messy.
Second, it is unimaginable to think we can quantify all the virtuous and vicious acts in human history and reach any kind of conclusion that would convince us that the world is worse than it was at some point in the past. It seems arbitrary to say 51% more vicious acts rather than 49% would lead to ruins, middens, and the fossil record. Possibly, the 49% of virtuous acts could prevent the 51% of vicious acts from defeating our efforts to improve the world. To say that we can settle in a quantifiable way whether the world is more prone toward the destructive consequences of evil than the constructive consequences of goodness is wrongheaded from the start.
However, Gass’s real point is more metaphysical than empirical. In the chapter titled “Finding a Form” in the book of that name, he says:
Early on I learned that life was meaningless, since life was not a sign; that novels were meaningful, because signs were the very material of their composition. I learned suffering served no purpose; that the good guys didn’t win; that most explanations offer me to make the mess I was in less a mess were self-serving lies. Life wasn’t clear, it was ambiguous; motives were many and mixed; values were complex, opposed, poisoned by hypocrisy, without any reasonable ground; much of adult society, its institutions and its advertised dreams, were simply superstitions that served a small set of people well while keeping the remainder in miserable ignorance.
Because life is meaningless, without a cosmology or teleology, (
Gass 1996, p. 272), it is willful ignorance to write fiction with a plot. No narrative story can accurately depict reality and our experiences within it. Life is not story with a plot, and thus a writer must reject narrative explanations. In fact, Gass says of his own agenda that “My stories are malevolently anti-narrative, and my essays are maliciously anti-expository.” (
Gass 1996, p. 46)” We cannot stop from turning all of our best efforts into ruins, middens, and fossils and, thus, should not pretend our philosophies and fictions can make the world meaningful. Reality is ultimately pointless. We cannot improve the world and that goodness will not win in the end.
Gass implies an inevitability to humanity turning its best efforts into only more ruins, middens, and fossils. This notion of evil’s inevitability reveals a central inconsistency in Gass’s definition and explanation of evil. In his definition, evil seems more circumstantial than inevitable. It “is a mosaic made of petty little pieces placed in malignant position mostly by circumstance.” (
Gass 2006, p. 418) However, his prognostications are about evil’s inevitability. He wants to say that evil results from our presumed virtues but also that the world will assuredly get worse. The upshot of his essay is that though humanity makes evil, we cannot stop its appearance or growth. For Gass, honest, clearheaded, and courageous persons should admit and accept this pessimism.
However, Gass writes to persuade us to adopt certain views, to help us live more authentically as humans in the world. He perpetuates a certain intellectual and literary tradition, which he maintains clarifies reality better than other traditions (especially the Judaic/Christian tradition) and which, by adopting it, he makes the case that the legacy should be continued for future readers to study, apply, and change their lives.
I think an inconsistency is obvious—even though Gass believes we inevitably create more ruins, middens, and fossils with our efforts, he in practice believes that there is a goodness in his work and his intellectual and literary legacy. In theory, he is a pessimist, but in practice he seeks to construct a better society (at least to his readers). He acts as though the goodness in his works will withstand the relentless corruption of them. It may appear that I am putting thoughts in Gass’s mind, but my main point is that (as illustrated in Gass’s teaching and writing agenda) we instinctively believe that there is a goodness to our best efforts that is not reduced to our actions and is greater in reality than our particular deeds.
My proof for this claim about Gass’s is his own reliance and propagation of an intellectual and literary legacy. It is not incidental to Gass’s purpose that he titles the book A Temple of Texts, as though he contends that by reading and taking seriously this legacy, we enter into a sacred space that defines the good ideas, moral commitments, and authors. He urges the reader to enter into this temple. For instance, Gass presents Voltaire’s anti-theism as a belief that is more conducive to authentic living than, for example, Leibniz’s theological optimism. He knows that Nietzsche’s tireless exposing of the genealogy of our morals as the conflict of wills couched in euphemisms of truth and pity is more ennobling of the human effort to face the misery of the world than, for example, Kierkegaard’s leap of faith. Gass finds more insight in Rilke’s creative use of language and imagination to interpret our experiences in a world without an obvious metaphysic to it than he would, for example, in the profoundly traditional narratives of T. S. Eliot’s poetry or in the manifestations of the divine in nature in the poetry of Gerald Manley Hopkins. These ideas reveal commitments to what a reasonable and courageous person ought to do in a world fraught with ruins, middens, and fossils. Gass must hope that the good he does as a writer outlives him and shapes future generations of readers, just as those writers shaped him.
On occasion, Gass admits the task of an artist and writer is more than the display of style and method. Near the end of
Finding a Form, after berating the “moralists” for abusing the artists with their unfounded moral dogmatism, he says of the value of writing, “I do happen to feel, with Theodor Adorno, that writing a book is a very important ethical act,” because it can “spit in the face of the [corrupt and debauched society of the] present.” (
Gass 1996, pp. 290–91) However, the value of writing is more than defiance against the moralist. It can also supplement the fleeting images of beauty the world.
It is the artist’s task to add to the world’s objects and ideas those delineations, carving, tales, fables, and symphonic spells which ought to be there; to make things whose end is contemplation and appreciation; to give birth to beings whose qualities harm no one, yet reward even the most casual notice, and which therefore deserve to become the focus of a truly disinterested affection. There is perhaps a moral in that.
Hence, as a writer, Gass wants to leave a moral legacy, because it would be better, more important, and real to us than the world of oligarchical moralists.
Consequently, to defend why we must learn from this legacy and why it defines what kind of people we ought to be, Gass would have to articulate an ontology of the good, which would not reduce goodness only to what we will it to be but to what it is in itself. If his notion of the good is only what we will it to be, then, frankly, it is no better or worse than what religious people or evil people will it to be. However, Gass would never equate the good he promotes with the others, and thus he must be relying on a sense of what reality ought to be.
4.2. The Vocation for the Good
Gass as a writer represents what we can call the “vocation for the good.” The phrase refers to those who believe what they do actually improve lives and consequently makes society a better place to live. The notion of the good is important, and, of course, a clear definition is debatable. I do not mean by it a transcendently perfect reality by which we can measure in all ways all our actions. Rather, I mean it in the sense Hans Jonas uses it, when he makes the distinction between what we ought to do and what ought to be (
Jonas 1984). The obligatoriness of moral action reflects what we think about the reality of something, and that reality conditions the actions which determine whether we properly act or not. It is the case that we do not merely accept whatever happen to be the reality that generates a sense of obligation in us. We make distinctions and discriminations between what ought not to be and what ought to be. We always make ontological judgments about the value of the realities we experience and fashion our lives according to the reality (or realities) that promises fulfillment for our loves and possibly the world. The “vocation of the good” thus means people committing themselves to certain actions that promote what they think ought to be, what they maintain to be the proper ways for people to act in light of the nature of reality.
A person adopting a “vocation of the good” could be a person committed to a marriage and family; an artist producing art works; a police person protecting a neighborhood; a nurse caring for the sick; a writer writing about evil; and so on. It could be Aristotle trying to restore the aristocratic virtues of courage, temperance, wisdom, and justice in a time of cultural decline and cynicism, because he thought without these virtues, society cannot continue, and people cannot find purpose and fulfillment. It could be the rationale to Kant’s insistence that for individuals and culture to mature beyond the religious and regional wars that ravaged Europe for a hundred years we must ground ethics upon universal, rational principles, so that we can peaceably and convincingly settle our moral quandaries and disputes. It could be the motive for the creation of the League of Nations and the United Nations after the two world wars of the 20th century. It could be the former victims of apartheid in South Africa implementing Truth and Reconciliation so that healing could occur, and a country scarred by racism and oppression could find a way to progress toward justice and shared happiness.
In each instance, people believe they make the world better, though the difference may be small. Their actions are more than the particular acts but a contribution to a goodness, which the doers think they increase by their actions, and which outlives the duration of their deeds. They think there is actually more goodness in the world because of their vocational activity.
Of course, they may not articulate an ontology of goodness or be philosophically committed to such an ontology, but their vocational actions presuppose an ontology of goodness, that by their deeds they are overcoming destructive or lethargic forces to human history and expanding the presence and transformative power of goodness. This may not require the support of a metaphysical system, but it does presume a worthy goal to seek. Surely, not every family, artist, police person, nurse, writer, institution, etc. takes on this vocation. Some are willfully destructive towards others and falsify reality. Yet, those who adopt the “vocation for the good” in that they intend a constructive agenda with their actions, persevere in their efforts to introduce more goodness in the world in spite of the presence of lies and destruction.
The importance of the “vocation of the good” frankly highlights a problem in appreciating Gass’s writing agenda. According to Philip Stevick, Gass’s purpose as an author is inconsistent with his nihilism. “[His] body of work seems so whole and continuous partly because the nonfiction and the fiction overlap so easily that a distinction between them seems artificial.” (
Stevick 1991). That is, Gass has an agenda to prove something and to represent how we ought to think and believe about the world. There is thus a disjunction between a pessimism that says our efforts only turn into ruins, middens, and fossils and a vocation that works for the good of others and society. Both cannot be true. The former denies the integrity of the latter, and the latter either denies or puts limitations on the former. His pessimism has no way to dissuade a society of walking away from its “vocation for the good,” of seeing our lives and history as a boring and boorish attempt to roll perpetually a stone up a mountain.
However, I do not think Gass believes his agenda is false and should be dismissed, even though that might follow from his antecedent position of nihilism about life and reality.
Frankly, Gass is not totally nihilistic. Always aware of the ethical and existential fissures in our finitude, Gass’s philosophical and literary legacy does not see itself as just another set of ruins, middens, and fossils.
9 In his output, he knows there are such things, but Gass marshals his best intellectual and literary creativity to keep them from increasing. His actual position could be that life and reality have to be rightly interpreted and that his agenda attempts to offer a correct interpretation of life and reality. That at least would be logically consistent and is perhaps Gass’s real position.
At this point, Gass could interject and say that the criticism I am raising (that is, his nihilism is inconsistent with his agenda as a writer of philosophical essays and fiction) is irrelevant to his project, that, because he is attempting to present as clearly and forthrightly as possible the bleakness of human existence, he is under no logical burden to conform his convictions and authorial appeals to any notion of the vocation of the good.
Yet, Gass cannot escape the fact that because he sees himself affirming and perpetuating an intellectual tradition canonized in his Temple of Texts, he is subject to the inner-logic of an intellectual tradition, and this inner-logic reveals the inferiority of his project in comparison to what I have been calling the Classical View within Christian history.
An intellectual tradition is a multi-generational dialectical conversation among people who attempt to sustain an inquiry into certain prevalent and consequentially serious problems of human experience by asking probing questions about the problems and by offering answers and solutions to these questions, which are passed on to future generations to critique and incorporate into their attempts to sustain the inquiry. The problems at the center of an intellectual tradition show themselves to be inescapable to reflective and serious-minded people. They are existentially demanding for a people who desire an informed and coherent life, so to be the kind of people who seek to make themselves and the world a more intelligible and moral place. Consequently, the people of an intellectual tradition marshal their analytical and probing interests to understand rightly these problems so that answers and possible solutions can be offered to subsequent generations who would be conditioned and fashioned in their own self-understanding to deal with the same issues.
The overall intentionality of an intellectual tradition follows three steps: first, a recognition of certain problems; second, a questioning of their characteristics, causes, and effects; and third, a response to the problems. Intellectual traditions persevere when they carry on to the third step without either contradicting their clear recognition of the problems or serious efforts to expose and rightly respond to them. Of course, there can be different intellectual traditions that deal with the same problems and thus offer different answers and solutions to the problem. Even though the rivals may oppose each other and may think that the other tradition represents what they seek to overcome or refute, one tradition shows its superiority as an intellectual tradition by offering coherent and persuasive solutions that clearly acknowledge and respond to the originating problems. A superior tradition is not only a contrary viewpoint to the rival but a correction to it by pointing out that its solution can better explain what the rival’s view cannot explain within its own recognition of the problems.
10Gass’s agenda as a writer lacks the resources to sustain the intellectual tradition that he claims as his “Temple of Texts” and, furthermore, undermines his attempt as a writer to offer a way to recognize and intelligibly assess the perpetual harms and malice that occur in human history. His solution to despise the Christian attempt at a theodicy and to deflate any sense of providence in history aggravates the very problem that his writing agenda tries to reveal and tries to embolden others to acknowledge with realism and honesty. He assumes that nihilism is the only proper way to face the misery and malice of the world, but such a thorough-going nihilism also undermines his own insistence to be taken seriously as an author who has not only an intellectual point but a moral position that others should adopt and emulate. Nihilism is not a solution to a problem that provokes us to seek intellectual insight and moral motivation to sustain a multi-generational dialectical conversation. In fact, it stops the conversation by insisting that, because human history and destiny are all pointless, the conversation is not worth maintaining.
Moreover, at this point, Gass could interject and say that the Classical View, which tries to clarify profound theological claims about God, creation, evil, and redemption is no different than a multigenerational, serious-dialectical investigation into the characters and plot of the Harry Potter fictional series or the Star War movie series, that the Christian theological legacy with its accompanying scholars and believers is no different than those that presume an obvious fictional story to have actual insights into reality and the prospects of humanity securing a meaningful place in the world. The Classical Tradition, Gass may assert, uses words and arguments that intend to depict the nature of reality, but, because theism is nothing but the self-serving pontifications of either fearful people who cannot face the true meaningless of reality or presumptuous people who want to use their religion to dominate over others, the Classical View is hence useless in accurately describing the metaphysical void of our experiences or it is delusional in encouraging the believers to think they are privileged and blessed in contrast to the heretics and heathens surrounding them.
Yet, if Gass were seriously to consider the business of metaphysics, he would see that the Classical View is not about fictional accounts of reality but about the basic features of reality. Even though metaphysical systems differ in their explanations of substance, change, time, and so, the following claims about the nature of reality serve as an approach to doing metaphysics, an approach that resonates in general ways with the metaphysical accounts of Plato, Aristotle, St. Anselm of Canterbury, St. Thomas Aquinas, Duns Scotus, Spinoza, Leibniz, Christian Wolf, Hegel, and A. N. Whitehead.
Metaphysics address the question of what is, of what is the nature of being itself. We exist and think it is important to know why we exist. Thus, we assume our existence has an importance. If we did not exist, we would not be asking the question. Being must be valuable. Furthermore, because it is better for reality to exist than not to exist, it would be incoherent to think that the absence of reality would be the cause of reality, of reality being better than reality not being. If it is better to have being than not to have it, then it is consistent to reason that being ought to be. The fact that realty exists indicates that its opposite would be a denial of the value of the existence of reality. Hence, it is valuable that being is, rather than not be.
Because we believe being ought to be, we can infer that it is good that being is. Existence has an inherent value to it. The goodness of being is that it exists and not not-exist. This goodness indicates that the perseverance of existence shows its value over against its absence of existence or its destruction. In this light, we can say goodness (in a metaphysical sense) is the perseverance of being, and, consequently, any action that enables and contributes to the perseverance of being is also a good act. In this sense, perseverance means the power to exist rather than not exist and the power to sustain existence over against the eviscerating and disintegrating of what exist.
Whether being per se is the necessary cause of all existing contingent realities or the essential power of existence of every contingent reality, being is always directed towards its own perseverance, which, thus means, that being integrates and consolidates its manifestations towards wholeness of being. The perseverance of reality as a whole makes its integration more complete, and because the perseverance integrates all aspects of reality into a coordinated whole, the direction of perseverance is towards an orderly reality. Actions that contribute to the integration of individual things into a purposeful ordering of reality are good actions. They further the principle of being itself (that it is better to persevere in existence than not) by enabling particular things to have complementarity in their integrative wholeness, in their position in relation to the order of reality.
Although destructiveness and corruption occur in our experiences of the world, they happen because being and its inherent goodness precede in reality their own destruction and corruption. The power of being is its perseverance of existing, and this perseverance integrates and consolidates what exist into a display of the goodness of existence. The more this perseverance integrates and consolidates, the more it resists and can overcome the effects of destruction and corruption. The stronger the connections are among particular existing things, the more they can resist and possibly overcome destruction and corruption. The more integrated the particulars of reality are into an ordered wholeness, the more power of existence the particulars have to stay off destruction and corruption. Destruction and corruption make the non-being of existing things more evident and makes it occur, but in that an orderly world persists and that particular things can continue to be integrated and coordinated into a meaningfully good reality in spite of the presence of the threats to being and its goodness, we can reasonably conclude that the power of being and its goodness is greater than what may cause its destruction and decay.
I grant that the details of this approach to metaphysics are highly debatable and, to be more convincing, they need much more explanation. However, this approach provides a plausible understanding of the nature of reality and how and why reality persists, even with destructive and corrupting events occurring in it. If this approach is a plausible metaphysic (which I can argue it is), then the Classical View is also a plausible account for our fundamental experiences of reality: first, it offers an explanation why being is better than nothing and why being is good (God’s creation of the heavens and earth); second, it acknowledges the reality of destructiveness and corruption (evil as the deprivation of being); and third, it offers an explanation on how being itself overcomes the appearances of destruction and corruption (redemption by God through Christ).
The Classical View is rich in biblical and theological terms and resonates with the liturgies and worship of Christians across centuries, but it is also a metaphysical account that not only communicates the language of the church, but it also communicates a fundamental understanding of reality itself, the treat of evil within reality, and how goodness prevails. Of course, the religious language to an anti-Christian like Gass comes across as offensive nonsense, but even the atheist would have to admit that if the intellectual energy put into constructing a metaphysical system is intellectually beneficial to understanding our place within the world, then the Classical View is reasonable and can contribute to the intellectual efforts to understand rightly our place within the world.
Furthermore, the Classical View in Christianity does offer a solution that Gass cannot. It acknowledges the middens and ruins of human history just as much as Gass’s nihilism does. It does not ignore or underestimate the pain and grief replayed throughout all generations. It is realistic about the depravity of human existence and questions and probes just as thoroughly and poignantly as does Gass’s “Temple of Texts” into the causes and consequences of evil. Consequently, because the Classical View offers an intellectual tradition that is both realistic and hopeful, that is humbled by the forces of human suffering and is hardworking for a good that can transform human existence, and that recognizes the shortcomings and incompleteness of its tradition but also offers to its future generations texts that possibly can help them to be courageous and constructive in dealing with the evils of the world, the Classical view shows its superiority as an intellectual tradition.
The Classical View is superior because the notion of the good expressed throughout its intellectual tradition overcomes the inconsistency within the tenuous intellectual tradition Gass believes he is perpetuating. Central to the Classical View is the goodness of creation, of the substantival reality of being itself and of how all of creation is coordinated into an ordered realm in which the reality of its creator, i.e., God, is evident and in which God interacts with each aspect of creation by being the necessary existing reality that enable the contingent realities to exist. This goodness of creation, though marred and harmed by evil, is never eradicated or permanently crippled by evil but is able to preserver through the corruptive work of evil by the interactive presence of the divine creative power. The Classical View testifies of this goodness and, consequently, should be taken seriously as an intellectual tradition.
For the word “good” in the “vocation for the good” to have the content implied in Hans Jonas’ claim that what we ought to do presuppose what ought to be, it would need to refer to a wholeness of life, an integration of people with others and nature. Less than this wholeness cannot give enough content to the good to enable people to resist and perhaps overcome evil and the tendency towards the ruins, middens, and fossils. The aims of pleasures, possession, and patriotism are powerful but malleable and easily corruptible by the vices of vanity and greed. For instance, human history is full of authors, politicians, and nations who made the world worse by promulgating hate and malice. If their aims were all the content of the good that we could seek, then Gass’s cynicism would be correct. Yet, it would be preposterous to think that people could morally justify their pursuits by saying they know the desired ends increase the dismay and despair of the world.
People commit to the “vocation for the good” because they think what they do should be what is needed to fulfill human life within the particular realities and demands of the world. They assume their actions represent what our experiences of life in the world should be. This wholeness, hence, indicates the purpose for life. An act is good if it contributes to the wholeness of human experiences, and this sense of contribution implies teleology. That is, the wholeness is the purpose of the aims of good acts. In doing good deeds in the “vocation for the good,” we actualize to a degree the purpose/final aim and, thus, increase its presence.
In correcting the malicious, destructive effects of evil, we in part overcome the ruins, middens, and fossils; we repair the damage. Although Gass would reject a notion of a final aim, his vocation presupposes it—that is, he contributes to an intellectual and literary tradition, because he thinks it is necessary for people to live more faithfully to their intelligent natures and fulfill their places in the world. He presupposes an aim which is bigger than the tradition and his books—the aim to be authentically human, which for him means being smart, perceptive, courageous. These characteristics are not ends in themselves, but virtues necessary to reach authentic human existence in a world in which evil occurs. These virtues are compelling for us because they do lead to a reality greater than their functions. If it were not possible to be an authentic human being in a world in which living as such a being would integrate one into the larger purposes of creation, then frankly the virtues would not make any sense and not be compelling. It is incoherent to summons readers to be smart, perceptive, and courageous because such virtues help us to see that all our efforts will lead to seven vices and more dismay. Gass promotes these virtues so that we will not be deceived by superficial and false views about reality and human evil (i.e., the Christian ones in particular) and that we can live correctly as thinking, creative, and valuing beings within a radically contingent and fragile world. Yet, by living this way, the world will become a better place, a place much like a temple, not another set of ruins, middens, and fossils.
It is not my intention to dismiss outright Gass’s insights and writings. He offers valuable observations about a section of our society’s current self-understanding. His writing style with its acute wording and flowing sentences is enviable and worthy of emulation. However, it is my contention that his assessment of Christianity and his use of nihilistic claims within his vocation as a writer are inaccurate and untenable.