Noteworthy Problems with God’s Immutability, Impassibility, and Simplicity. Should We Treat These Divine Attributes and the Hellenic Conditions of Christian Theism as a Dogma?
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Discussion, Objections, and Results
2.1. Between Jerusalem and Athens—An Original Tension and the Problem of God’s Immutability
2.2. From Immutability to Impassibility
2.3. From Immutability to Simplicity—Classical Foundations
2.4. God’s Simplicity under Discussion
3. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | A synthetic presentation of this issue can be found in: Stump 2010, pp. 270–77 and Creel 2010, pp. 324–28. I am aware that, if we assume that God is mutable, passible, and composite, a number of difficulties arise, although the minute analysis of these problems goes beyond the scope of my paper. |
2 | That is why I reflect upon the concepts of God’s immutability, impassibility, and simplicity in one paper. God’s immutability and impassibility are analyzed jointly, e.g., by Creel, who claims additionally that one of the most important arguments for God’s immutability comes from the concept of the divine absolute simplicity (Creel 2010, p. 322). When exploring the thought of Aquinas, Emery points out that the acknowledgment of divine simplicity “excludes the possibility of […] the “suffering” of God. It also provides the foundation for the affirmation of divine immutability” (Emery 2009, p. 59). |
3 | Since the theistic tradition has been deeply embedded in patriarchal culture, male pronouns for God dominate the theological-philosophical discourse. I understand the modern call to use inclusive language in reference to God; however, this problem has no primary importance in my paper. Nb. The editors of the leading Companions to Philosophy of Religion do not oppose the use of male pronouns for God (e.g., Stump 2010, p. 272). |
4 | In my opinion, there is no doubt that the Christian doctrine has been influenced by various philosophical conceptions. Moreover, I recognize this fact as valuable for the rational religious reflection. The significant challenge consists in identifying the proper line of demarcation in the fruitfull exchange of ideas and in weighing the benefits against the risks in the particular cases. The fundamental problem is often mistakably identified with finding an unequivocal answer to the question: does one share the Harnack thesis or not? The devil is, however, in many other details I am trying to present. Nb. P. Gavrilyuk, who oposes the Harnack thesis, deliberating on God’s suffering, admits: “It is true that among educated pagans, whose philosophical views tended towards later Platonism, the divine impassibility did acquire the status of a universally shared opinion” (Gavrilyuk 2006, p. 34). |
5 | This is why I disregard various nuances of the analyzed issue that should be minutely undertaken within revealed theology (although, in the footnotes, I delineate some Christological problems, important for my paper) and within systematic theology (e.g., the difference between the catholic, the orthodox, and the protestant view on the Hellenization of the Christian doctrine). |
6 | The classical Thomists would probably express the similar opinion concerning the marginalization of their tradition in the analytic milieu. In this context, Analytical Thomism is a praiseworthy example of developing the classical tradition. |
7 | The Scripture does often present God as immutable (e.g., The Book of Malachi 3:6; The Letter of James 1:17). Nevertheless, even the Thomists admit that biblical statements often concern not so much ontic immutability but God’s unchanging love for us (see footnote 15). Moreover, among the classical Thomists there are different views on the important aspects of the problem. Salij writes: God is most literally infinitely perfect, there is no (never has been and never will be) becoming in Him (Salij 2018). Przanowski, when analyzing Aquinas’ view on the Incarnation, claims: Becoming (fieri) actually took place, but there was no change (mutari) in the divine nature (Przanowski 2017, p. 335). Others minimize the meaning of the biblical assertions regarding God’s mutability by the emphasis on the specific language of the Scripture: “While such statements say something literally true about God, they are, I believe, not to be taken literally” (Weinandy 2001). The last opinion does not close the discussion, although the issue of language used in the Scripture is extremely important and the differences among the literal, metaphorical, figurative, analogous, and mystical language of the particular expression have to be carefully taken into account see for example: (Alston 2005, pp. 220–44; Soskice 2007). Nb. When depicting the causes of suffering, Weinandy overlooks the specific language of the Bible (see footnote 15). |
8 | For G. Emery: “God’s immutability should not be thought of as inactivity: God acts by a voluntary impulsion from within rather than being swayed from without. The immutability that is proper to God guarantees precisely the transcendence and the perfection of his free action“ (Emery 2009, p. 29). But “a voluntary impulsion from within” need not exclude “being swayed from without”. Why and how does one’s immutability guarantee the perfection of their free action? |
9 | The following quotation shows how strong was Tertulian’s position regarding the relationship between faith and reason: “What has Jerusalem to do with Athens, the Church with (Plato’s) Academy, the Christian with the heretic? Our principles come from the Porch of Solomon, who had himself taught that the Lord is to be sought in simplicity of heart. I have no use for a Stoic or a Platonic or a dialectic Christianity. After Jesus Christ we have no need of speculation, after the Gospel no need of research. When we come to believe, we have no desire to believe anything else; for we begin by believing that there is nothing else which we have to believe” (Tertulian 1956, p. 36). |
10 | Despite his well-known statements against philosophy, Tertullian uses a lot of philosophy to do theology. |
11 | In a sense, the relationship between revealed faith and philosophical reason already started with The Septuagint—the earliest extant Greek translation of the Hebrew Bible. |
12 | It has to be noticed that there is no single Greek view of the divine, and “there is no one unified account of the divine emotions and of the divine involvement advocated by major Hellenistic schools of philosophy, let alone the Hellenistic religions at large” (Gavrilyuk 2006, pp. 21–22). In this regard, essential differences between various Hellenistic schools of philosophical thought are depicted by Rowe (Rowe 1994, p. 88). Kearsley warns: “The question ‘What is God in ancient Greek philosophy?’ would furnish the perfect tide for someone wishing simply to write a really long book. Aristotle, Plato and Zeno would each give a different answer, even if you were fortunate enough to get only one answer from any of them! We should therefore be a little suspicious of sweeping statements to the effect that Christians have grafted ‘the Greek view of God’ on to a simple, pristine and pure Christianity. Just as the philosophical schools of the early Christian centuries were eclectic within a broad spirit and rationale, so Christian ‘philosophical theologians’ did not import entire systems of thought from any particular philosopher or school” (Kearsley 1992, p. 308). |
13 | In this context, one can doubt whether God is active in the face of human sufferings. Defenders of the thesis that the God of the classical theism is not inactive accentuate that the absolute being is pure act. But this is not sufficient argumentation, which creates particular problems, e.g., weak consistency: “by being pure act, God possesses the potential to perform acts that are singular to His being pure act” (I have underlined the words to be found in Weinandy’s analysis). There are also (insufficient) arguments from ignorance: “While we cannot comprehend how God, as pure act, acts, the act of creation is God acting as pure act, whereby created beings are related to God as He is and so come to exist” (Weinandy 2001). Moreover, one of the analogies in the Thomistic argumentation for God’s immutability presents a passive God. When recalling Aquinas’ view on the Creator–creation relationship, Przanowski asserts: “our intellect apprehends God in relation to creation in the way in which it comprehends the object of cognition in relation to knowledge. God (in this analogy: the object of cognition) is therefore in mental (conceptual, logical) relation to creation (in this analogy: knowledge), while creation exists in a real relation to Him.... The statement that God is in a mental (conceptual, logical) relation to creation does not mean the negation of any reference, but the negation of any change introduced by that reference” (Przanowski 2017, p. 332). Now, the object of perception is static in relation to the one who apprehends it. |
14 | There is no place here to introduce minutely the reflection of the Church Fathers upon the divine impassiblity. For comprehensive study in this regard, see: Gavrilyuk 2006, pp. 47–63. A separate attention should be paid to the thought of Cyril of Alexandria, for “it was Cyril’s vision that determined the key questions in the discussions of divine (im)passibility in the centuries that followed” (Gavrilyuk 2006, pp. 19, 135–71). Obviously, the idea of God’s impassibility (as well as that of God’s immutability) did not penetrate the Christian doctrine of the first centuries solely due to the process of Hellenization. Christian thinkers made a theological interpretation of these concepts; for example, God’s impassibility became not only an aspect of the God’s strong separateness from the world, but also made the very foundations of soteriology: God can redeem us from evil, sin, and suffering, because He himself is not subordinated to them at all (Strzelczyk 2006, p. 169). |
15 | I am not convinced by the following way of arguing for God’s impassibility: “only if He existed in the same ontological order in which the evil was enacted could He then suffer” or “God is absolutely impassible because He is absolutely passionate in His love” (Weinandy 2001). Nb. The latter argumentation stresses the ethical dimension of God’s immutability (see footnote 7). In his reasoning, Weinandy assumes the privation theory of evil: “since evil, which causes suffering, is the privation of some good, it would mean that a suffering God was deprived of some good and thus He would no longer be perfectly good”. Such a view on evil was criticized for many reasons (see for example: Calder 2007, pp. 371–81). There is also a problem of the cause of suffering. Weinandy asserts: “The compassion of God is seen then not in His suffering in solidarity with humankind, but in His ability to alleviate the cause of human suffering—sin” (Weinandy 2001). This conception—dispite any of Weinandy’s declarations regarding the proper understanding of the first part of The Book of Genesis—originates in its literal interpretation and creates widely recognized problems. Can it be rationally and satisfactory explained that the suffering of a terminally ill child is caused by sin? Whose sin? The ultimate cause of any suffering should be rather found in the contingency of the world, which characterizes thereof in each place and moment of the history. Nb. When delineating the cause of suffering, Weinandy reflects upon various examples of suffering, but disregards the above-mentioned case (as well as the suffering of some animals with a developed nervous system). |
16 | Some theologians are so strongly fascinated by the concept of impassibility that in its analysis they miss the problem of Incarnation (Charamsa 2003, pp. 259–77). Other thinkers, when analyzing the issue of Incarnation and redemption, underline exclusively the duality of Christ’s nature: “since it was the Son of God who suffered, did He not equally experience such suffering within His divinity? No, for suffering is caused by the loss of some good, and while as man the Son was deprived of His human well-being and life, He was not deprived of any divine perfection or good” (Weinandy 2001). Such an argumentation neglects the personalist dimension of suffering and refers to the position of St. John of Damascus: “The Word of God then itself endured all in the flesh, while His divine nature which alone was passionless remained void of passion. For since the one Christ, Who is a compound of divinity and humanity, and exists in divinity and humanity, truly suffered, that part which is capable of passion suffered as it was natural it should, but that part which was void of passion did not share in the suffering… Observe, further, that we say that God suffered in the flesh, but never that His divinity suffered in the flesh, or that God suffered through the flesh.” (John of Damascus 1899, III:26). In the context of such statements, the following question arises: Can we not claim that Christ suffered as a person? Emery gives the positive answer to this in the following way: “the person or hypostasis of the Son suffered by virtue of the human nature he had assumed” (Emery 2009, p. 31). |
17 | Already in the nineteenth century, some Anglican theologians challenged the conception of God’s impassibility (for example Andrew M. Fairbairn). One should also note the influence of the nineteenth century German Kenoticism (the school represented by G. Thomasius and F. Rohmer, as well as the more radical group of thinkers such as W. Gess and F. Godet) to the twentieth century British Kenoticists (such as C. Gore, F. Weston, A. M. Fairbairn, C. A. Dinsmore) and through the latter to the critics of God’s impassibility (Weinandy 2002, pp. 110–23). |
18 | See note 7 and 15. |
19 | There are important differences among the particular theoretical proposals of the processualists concerning the question: what does it mean that God is active and dynamic? Hartshorne’s conception of God substantially differs from that of Whitehead. The latter is much closer to the classical Christian theism. |
20 | Aquinas often grounded his argumentation for God’s simplicity (and immutability) on the Aristotelian physics, which was largely a result of commonsense beliefs, containing many oversimplifications and errors (Dodds 1986, pp. 119–40). |
21 | As stressed in one of the reviews to my paper, this is the most personal achievement of Aquinas in this field. From Origen to Bonaventure, most Christian theologians put matter in every creature in order to distinguish creatures from their Creator: the presence of matter means that every creature is composite while God is simple. Aquinas does not need this distinction because he has efficiently introduced another one: between essence and existence. |
22 | In such a foundationalist view on God’s attributes, it is hardly surprising that the Thomists strongly defend their position. It has several advantages; however, I present some reasons for keeping the discussion open: rational counterarguments and the value of alternative approaches. |
23 | The specific status of affirmations about God was deeply studied by Aquinas (Thomas Aquinas 1920, I.3:premium) and his many followers, e.g., by Stump, who claims: “What the doctrine of simplicity requires one to understand about all the designations for the divine attributes is that they are all identical in reference but different in sense, referring in various ways to the one actual entity which is God himself or designating various manifestations of it … ‘Perfect power’ and ‘perfect knowledge’ are thus analogues for ‘the morning star’ and ‘the evening star’: non-synonymous expressions calling to mind quite distinct manifestations of one and the same thing referred to. There is as much truth and as much potential misinformation in ‘Perfect power is identical with perfect knowledge’ as there is in ‘The morning star is identical with the evening star’” (Stump 2005, pp. 99–100). When formulating statements on the divine attributes one has to realize that—to give an example—the content of the phrase “God is wise” conveys a different meaning than “God is good”. Only in this sense can it be asserted that God has various properties. Simultaneously, one can rationally state that God’s wisdom does not differ from His goodness. Analogically, “the wisdom of God” does not signify something essentially different from what is conveyed by the name “God” (Przanowski 2010, p. 56). Contemporary supporters of the doctrine of God’s simplicity often maintain that Plantinga understood it incorrectly. According to Leftow, Plantinga thinks that, when he states that there is no difference between God and His nature, it is assumed that He possesses all of the attributes usually connected with divine nature, and lacks the attributes associated with the word “God”, which are inconsistent with the attributes commonly ascribed to it. This is a mistaken reasoning—underlines Leftow—because the statement “God=God’s nature” signifies only that what is identical to divine nature is not an example of attributes ordinarily associated with the nature of God. Therefore, the thesis of identity does not lead to the conclusion that God is an abstract being (Leftow 1990, p. 593; Leftow 2006, pp. 365–80; Przanowski 2010, p. 55; Słomka 2021, p. 41). Davies points out that Plantinga did not sufficiently understand the negative character of the divine simplicity: this doctrine refers to what God is not rather than to what He is (Davies 1987, p. 59). Rogers, in turn, reproaches Plantinga for omitting the (essential for Aquinas) connection between the simplicity of God and His unique “mode of existence”—Actus Purus. Simplicity does not generate an abstract, impersonal, image of God. God always acts in a rational way, and He can be perfectly identified with His own action (Rogers 1996, p. 171; Przanowski 2010, p. 57; Słomka 2021, p. 42). In contrast, Copan and Craig argue that “if God is not distinct from his essence, then God cannot know or do anything different from what he knows and does. He can have no contingent knowledge or action, for everything about him is essential to him. But in that case, all modal distinctions collapse and everything becomes necessary. Since ‘God knows that p’ is logically equivalent to ‘p is true,’ the necessity of the former entails the necessity of the latter. Thus, divine simplicity leads to an extreme fatalism, according to which everything that happens does so with logical necessity” (Copan and Craig 2004, pp. 178–79). |
24 | “By virtue of God’s simplicity, God cannot be or do other than God is or does. God’s act, which is God’s being, is absolutely necessary. At the same time, the doctrines of God’s free creation, creation from nothing, and the gratuitousness of God’s saving grace all likewise follow from God’s independence. But creation and salvation are divine acts. Therefore, there is an apparent contradiction: for what is supposed to be perfectly free is actually completely necessary. Older thinkers recognized the potential puzzle and proposed to dissolve it with a distinction. They distinguished between two kinds of necessity: one, absolute necessity, and the other known variously as hypothetical, conditional, or suppositional necessity. Absolute necessity is that necessity by which God exists and exists in a certain way. It is the kind of necessity that God’s aseity, and so God’s simplicity, involves. The latter, hypothetical necessity, is the necessity by which God creates and saves. It is the kind of necessity that an absolutely necessary being imposes on the things it knows or does ad extra“ (Pedersen and Lilley 2022, p. 129). Aquinas stressed that the distinction between absolute and hypothetical necessity rests solely on the source (or ground) of a thing’s necessity in relation to its essence or concept (Thomas Aquinas 1955–1957, I.81–83). Only when the predicate forms part of the definition of the subject, or when the subject forms part of the notion of the predicate, is a thing absolutely necessary. A hypothetical necessity is one in which the opposite is true, and the source of a thing’s necessity is extrinsic to its concept (Thomas Aquinas 1920, I.19:3, resp.; Pedersen and Lilley 2022, pp. 131–32). Pedersen and Lilley notice that theists “from Boethius to Leibniz have been satisfied that this distinction in sorts of necessity is adequate to distinguish the way God necessarily exists from the necessity of the effects God freely produces” (Pedersen and Lilley 2022, pp. 129–30), recent thinkers, however, “have been less satisfied. Some now argue that the distinction collapses. Because, they argue, the distinction between absolute and hypothetical necessity reduces to absolute necessity, it cannot be used to solve the puzzle in the way older thinkers thought it could. The result, they charge, is that God’s effects, such as the world, are as necessary as divine being. The puzzle is now a serious problem, and the available solutions are accordingly more extreme. Most rely on the abandonment of premises that were important to thinkers from Augustine and Aquinas to the Protestant scholastics. In many cases, the point of the argument is precisely to force the abandonment of such premises—premises such as ‘strong’ notions of divine aseity and simplicity. This strategy is, once again, sometimes known as the argument from modal collapse. And one of its main contentions is that “because simplicity entails a modal collapse, we should revise or abandon the doctrine of simplicity” (Pedersen and Lilley 2022, p. 130). Duby admitts that to “the extent that advocates of divine simplicity wish to retain the freedom of God in the work of creation, this represents a significant challenge—indeed, perhaps the most difficult for a traditional understanding of divine simplicity” (Duby 2016, p. 194). Richards proposes that God’s being includes potentiality, for this secures the freedom of God to create or not to create the world. In Richard’s opinion, if God is without any residual potency (actus purus), He should do all that He possibly can do, including creating all possible worlds, which He has not done (Richards 2003, pp. 234–35; Duby 2016, p. 193). Even some Thomists opt to ‘weaken’ divine simplicity. Stump and Kretzmann openly concede that “God is not the same in all possible worlds”. Only given an ‘”nitial-state set”—a set of chosen creaturely circumstances on which the (formerly indeterminate) will of God is now terminated—is God fully in act and determinate (Stump and Kretzmann 1985, pp. 355, 362–69). Ross underlines that such weakening is an enervation of divine simplicity and that, if this doctrine is to be preserved, it must preserve God’s ‘trans-world’ simplicity (Ross 1985, pp. 383, 387–88; Duby 2016, p. 194). |
25 | One of my anonymous reviewers noticed that Thomists would take exception with this statement. In my paper, however, I follow the interpretation of Stump, who—in the context of the Aquinas’ reflection upon God’s choice of creation and accidental properties—claims: “this is the sense in which we should understand that God has no accidents—not that God is exactly the same in all possible worlds in which he exists but that there is nothing at all incomplete or insubstantial about God in any respect, even though God is not the same in all possible worlds” (Stump 2005, p. 113). |
26 | This statement would be rejected by the Thomists. O’Connor attempts to solve the analyzed problem by means of eliminating the causally intermediating intention of creating the world: God creates a contingent order directly. God’s action is not constituted by a certain internal state but by a particular “execution” of divine power which efficiently “produces” a given state of affairs. In such a way, no God’s internal states are presupposed apart from the reasons behind creating this or that possible world. The will to create a given world is not an internal state distinct from God. The contingency of various world orders does not imply the existence of any accidental properties in God’s nature (O’Connor 1999, pp. 405–12; Koszkało and Pepliński 2016, p. 99; Słomka 2021, p. 43). |
27 | In the second half of the thirteenth century, leading academic centers were quickly permeated with the Stagirite’s works, brought to Europe by the Arabs. Then, in order to meet the needs of the times, notable theologians strived to reconcile Aristotelian thought with the doctrine of the Church (Słomka 2021, p. 54). |
28 | It is worth noticing that, even to some classical theologians, these divine attributes are not absolutized. According to Augustine, God is in some way moved. Aquinas understood this in regards to God’s knowing, willing, and loving: “motion of this sort can be affirmed of God” (Dodds 1986, p. 150). |
29 | For example, Creel proposes the path “toward a unified position” regarding God’s immutability and impassibility (Creel 2010, pp. 324–27). Among twentieth century theologians, an interesting interpretation of the divine impassibility was formulated by K. Rahner, who utilizes the conception of “communicatio idiomatum”, which was rooted in the old Christian tradition and played a significant role in the formation of the Christological dogma. By distinguishing the “natures” of the Son of God, we place suffering unambiguously on the side of humanity, leaving divinity above it. At the same time, however, we can point to the person of the Son of God, the eternal Logos, as the ultimate subject of what was experienced by humanity: also suffering and death. When asked “what suffered?” from the perspective of the “communicatio idiomatum”, we answer—humanity; to the question “who suffered”—Jesus Christ, the incarnate Son of God, one of the Trinity. Such classical Christology has placed suffering at the very heart of the life of the Triune God! The question of the divine nature’s ability to suffer was relegated to the background when facing the fact of Incarnation. The Son of God has—irremovably—also a nature capable of suffering... Therefore, in the light of the dogmatic tradition of the Church, the statement that one of the divine persons has become the subject of suffering is not of a purely metaphorical or anthropomorphic character (Strzelczyk 2006, pp. 170–72). |
References
- Alesse, Francesca, ed. 2008. Philo of Alexandria and Post-Aristotelian Philosophy (Studies in Philo of Alexandria, 5). Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Alston, William P. 2005. Religious Language. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Qilliam Wainwright. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 220–444. [Google Scholar]
- Anselm of Canterbury. 1903. Proslogion. In St. Anselm: Proslogium; Monologium: An Appendix in Behalf of The Fool by Gaunilo; And Cur Deus Homo. Translated by Sidney N. Deane. Chicago: The Open Court Publishing Company, Reprinted 1926. Available online: https://sourcebooks.fordham.edu/basis/anselm-proslogium.asp (accessed on 11 June 2021).
- Anselm of Canterbury. 1986. Monologion. In L’Oeuvre d’Anselme de Cantorbéry (Vol. 1). Edited by Michel Corbin. Paris: Cerf. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1989. Metaphysics (Aristotle in 23 Volumes: Vols. 17–18). Translated by Hugh Tredennick. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. London: William Heinemann Ltd. [Google Scholar]
- Athanasius. 1857a. Oratio contra Gentes (PG, 25). Paris: Garnier. [Google Scholar]
- Athanasius. 1857b. Orationes adversus Arianos (PG, 26). Paris: Garnier. [Google Scholar]
- Augustine of Hippo. 1887a. On the Trinity. In Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers (First Series, Vol. 3). Edited by Philip Schaff. Translated by Arthur West Haddan. Buffalo: Christian Literature Publishing Co., Revised and edited for New Advent by Kevin Knight. Available online: https://www.newadvent.org/fathers/1301.htm (accessed on 11 June 2021).
- Augustine of Hippo. 1887b. The City of God. In Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers (First Series, Vol. 2). Edited by Philip Schaff. Translated by Marcus Dods. Buffalo: Christian Literature Publishing Co., Revised and edited for New Advent by Kevin Knight. Available online: https://www.newadvent.org/fathers/1201.htm (accessed on 11 June 2021).
- Basil the Great. 1895. De Spiritu Sancto. In Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers (Second Series Vol. 8). Edited by Philip Schaff and Henry Wace. Translated by Blomfield Jackson. Buffalo: Christian Literature Publishing Co., Revised and Edited for New Advent by Kevin Knight. Available online: https://www.newadvent.org/fathers/3203.htm (accessed on 11 June 2021).
- Bauckham, Richard. 1984. Only the Suffering God Can Help. Divine Passibility in Modern Theology. Themelios 9: 6–12. [Google Scholar]
- Boethius. 1847. De hebdomadibus. Edited by Jacques-Paul Migne. Parisiis: Patrologia Latina. [Google Scholar]
- Calder, Todd. 2007. Is the Privation Theory of Evil Dead? American Philosophical Quarterly 44: 371–81. [Google Scholar]
- Charamsa, Krzysztof. 2003. Davvero Dio soffre? La Tradizione e l’insegnamento di San Tommaso. Bologna: Edizioni Studio Domenicano. [Google Scholar]
- Copan, Paul, and William Lane Craig. 2004. Creation out of Nothing. A Biblical, Philosophical, and Scientific Exploration. Grand Rapids: Baker. Leicester: Apollos. [Google Scholar]
- Creel, Richard E. 1986. Divine Impassibility. An Essay in Philosophical Theology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Creel, Richard E. 2010. Immutability and Impassibility. In A Companion to Philosophy of Religion, 2nd ed. Edited by Charles Taliaferro, Paul Draper and Philip L. Quinn. Oxford and Malden: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 322–28. [Google Scholar]
- Davies, Brian. 1987. Classical Theism and the Doctrine of Divine Simplicity. In Language, Meaning and God. Essays in Honour of Herbert McCabe. Edited by B. Davies. London: Geoffrey Chapman, pp. 51–74. [Google Scholar]
- Dodds, Michael J. 1986. The Unchanging God of Love. A Study of the Teaching of St. Thomas Aquinas on Divine Immutability in View of Certain Contemporary Criticism of this Doctrine (Studia Friburgensia). Fribourg: Editions Universitaires Fribourg Suisse. [Google Scholar]
- Dodds, Michael J. 2008. The Unchanging God of Love. Thomas Aquinas and Contemporary Theology on Divine Immutability. Washington: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dolezal, James E. 2011. God without Parts. Divine Simplicity and the Metaphysics of God’s Absoluteness. Eugene: Pickwick Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Duby, Steven J. 2016. Divine Simplicity. A Dogmatic Account. London and New York: Bloomsbury T. & T. Clark. [Google Scholar]
- Emery, Gilles. 2009. The immutability of the God of love and the problem of language concerning the “suffering of God”. In Divine Impassibility and the Mystery of Human Suffering. Edited by James F. Keating and Thomas Joseph White. Grand Rapids: Cambridge: Eerdmans, pp. 27–76. [Google Scholar]
- Gavrilyuk, Paul L. 2006. The Suffering of the Impassible God. The Dialectics of Patristic Thought. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Grant, W. Matthew. 2003. Aquinas, Divine Simplicity, and Divine Freedom. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 77: 129–45. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gregory Nazianzen. 1858. Oratio XXXI Theologica Quinta (PG, 36). Paris: Garnier. [Google Scholar]
- Gregory of Nyssa. 1863. Contra Eunomium (PG, 45). Paris: Garnier. [Google Scholar]
- Gutowski, Piotr. 1995. Filozofia procesu i jej metafilozofia. Studium metafizyki Ch. Hartshorne’a. Lublin: RW KUL. [Google Scholar]
- Gutowski, Piotr. 2016. Stare i nowe. Esej o roli jednostkowych podmiotów, zmiany i wątpienia w religii. Kraków: Dominikańskie Studium Filozofii i Teologii. [Google Scholar]
- Hahn, Lewis Edwin, ed. 1991. Philosophy of Charles Hartshorne (The Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. 20). La Salle: Open Court. [Google Scholar]
- Hartshorne, Charles. 1941. Man’s Vision of God. New York: Harper & Brothers. [Google Scholar]
- Hartshorne, Charles. 1964. The Divine Relativity: A Social Conception of God. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hasker, William. 1986. Simplicity and Freedom. A Response to Stump and Kretzmann. Faith and Philosophy 3: 192–201. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hecht, Jennifer M. 2003. Doubt: A History. The Great Doubters and Their Legacy of Innovation from Socrates and Jesus to Thomas. San Francisco: HarperOne. [Google Scholar]
- Hilary of Poitiers. 1845. De Trinitate (PL, 10). Paris: Garnier. [Google Scholar]
- Hughes, Christopher. 1989. On a Complex Theory of a Simple God. An Investigation in Aquinas’ Philosophical Theology. London and Ithaca: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hughes, Gerard J. 1995. The Nature of God. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Hume, David. 1779. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. London: Robinson. [Google Scholar]
- Jerome. 1892. De viris. In Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers (Second Series, Vol. 3). Edited by Philip Schaff and Henry Wace. Translated by Ernest Cushing Richardson. Buffalo: Christian Literature Publishing Co. [Google Scholar]
- John of Damascus. 1899. An Exposition of the Orthodox Faith. In Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers (Second Series, Vol. 9). Edited by Philip Schaff and Henry Wace. Translated by Edward William Watson, and Leighton L. Pullan. Buffalo: Christian Literature Publishing Co., Revised and Edited for New Advent by Kevin Knight. Available online: https://www.newadvent.org/fathers/33043.htm (accessed on 7 August 2021).
- John Paul II. 1988. Letter of His Holiness John Paul II to Reverend George V. Coyne, S.J. Director of the Vatican Observatory. Available online: https://www.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/letters/1988/documents/hf_jp-ii_let_19880601_padre-coyne.html (accessed on 10 June 2021).
- Jonas, Hans. 1987. The Concept of God after Auschwitz. A Jewish Voice. The Journal of Religion 67: 1–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Judycki, Stanisław. 2010. Bóg i inne osoby. Próba z zakresu teologii filozoficznej. Poznań: W drodze. [Google Scholar]
- Kearsley, Roy. 1992. The Impact of Greek Concepts of God on the Christology of Cyril of Alexandria. Tyndale Bulletin 43: 307–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Koszkało, Marek, and Martyna Pepliński. 2016. Prostota. In Przewodnik po filozofii religii. Nurt analityczny. Edited by Janusz Salamon. Kraków: WAM, pp. 87–108. [Google Scholar]
- Kowalczyk, Stanisław. 2001. Filozofia Boga. Lublin: KUL. [Google Scholar]
- La Croix, Richard R. 1977. Augustine on the Simplicity of God. The New Scholasticism 51: 453–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lee, Jung Y. 1974. God Suffers for Us. A Systematic Inquiry into a Concept of Divine Passibility. Den Haag: Nijhoff. [Google Scholar]
- Leftow, Brian. 1990. Is God an Abstract Object? Noûs 24: 581–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Leftow, Brian. 2006. Divine Simplicity. Faith and Philosophy 23: 365–80. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Leftow, Brian. 2015. Divine Simplicity and Divine Freedom. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 89: 45–56. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- MacDonald, Scott. 2001. The Divine Nature. In The Cambridge Companion to Augustine. Edited by Eleonore Stump and Norman Kretzmann. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 71–90. [Google Scholar]
- O’Connor, Timothy. 1999. Simplicity and Creation. Faith and Philosophy 16: 405–12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Origen. 1885a. Against Celsus. In Ante-Nicene Fathers (Vol. 4). Edited by Alexander Roberts, James Donaldson and A. Cleveland Coxe. Translated by Frederick Crombie. Buffalo: Christian Literature Publishing Co., Revised and edited for New Advent by Kevin Knight. Available online: http://www.newadvent.org/fathers/0416.htm (accessed on 9 June 2021).
- Origen. 1885b. De principiis. In Ante-Nicene Fathers (Vol. 4). Edited by Alexander Roberts, James Donaldson and A. Cleveland Coxe. Translated by Frederick Crombie. Buffalo: Christian Literature Publishing Co., Revised and edited for New Advent by Kevin Knight. Available online: http://www.newadvent.org/fathers/04121 (accessed on 4 June 2021).
- Osmański, Marek. 2002. Filon. In Powszechna Encyklopedia Filozofii (Vol. 3). Edited by Andrzej Mariniarczyk and Stanisław Bafia. Lublin: Polskie Towarzystwo Tomasza z Akwinu, pp. 440–49. [Google Scholar]
- Pannenberg, Wolfhart. 1971. Basic Questions in Theology (Vol. I). Translated by George H. Kehm. London: SCM Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pedersen, Daniel J., and Christopher Lilley. 2022. Divine Simplicity. God’s Freedom, and the Supposed Problem of Modal Collapse. Journal of Reformed Theology 16: 127–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Philo of Alexandria. 2021a. De Abrahamo. Available online: http://www.earlyjewishwritings.com/text/philo/book22.html (accessed on 15 June 2021).
- Philo of Alexandria. 2021b. De Gigantibus. Available online: http://www.earlyjewishwritings.com/text/philo/book9.html (accessed on 15 June 2021).
- Philo of Alexandria. 2021c. De Opificio Mundi. Available online: http://www.earlyjewishwritings.com/text/philo/book1.html (accessed on 15 June 2021).
- Philo of Alexandria. 2021d. De Congressu Eruditionis Gratia. Available online: http://www.earlyjewishwritings.com/text/philo/book18.html (accessed on 15 June 2021).
- Philo of Alexandria. 2021e. De Somniis. Available online: http://www.earlyjewishwritings.com/text/philo/book21.html (accessed on 15 June 2021).
- Plantinga, Alvin C. 1980. Does God Have a Nature? Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. 1992. Republic. Translated by G. M. A. Grube, and C. D. C. Reeve. Indianapolis: Hackett. [Google Scholar]
- Przanowski, Mateusz. 2010. Wprowadzenie do kwestii VII. O prostocie Bożej istoty. In Św. Tomasz z Akwinu, Kwestie dyskutowane o mocy Boga (Vol. 4: O prostocie Bożej istoty. O tym, co odwiecznie relacyjnie orzeka się o Bogu). Edited by Mateusz Przanowski and Jan Kiełbasa. Kęty and Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Marek Derewiecki and Instytut Tomistyczny, pp. 5–62. [Google Scholar]
- Przanowski, Mateusz. 2017. Istota Boga a kenoza wcielenia według św. Tomasza z Akwinu. Przegląd Tomistyczny 23: 323–37. [Google Scholar]
- Richards, Jay W. 2003. The Untamed God. A Philosophical Exploration of Divine Perfection, Simplicity, and Immutability. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rogers, Katherin. 1996. The Traditional Doctrine of Divine Simplicity. Religious Studies 32: 165–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rogers, Katherin. 2008. Anselm on Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ross, James. 1985. Comments on “Absolute Simplicity”. Faith and Philosophy 2: 383–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rowe, William V. 1994. Adolf von Harnack and the Concept of Hellenization. In Hellenization Revisited. Shaping a Christian Response within the Greco-Roman World. Edited by Wendy E. Helleman. Lanham: University Press of America, pp. 69–98. [Google Scholar]
- Runia, David T. 2001. On the Creation of the Cosmos according to Moses (Introduction, Translation and Commentary). Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Salij, Jacek. 2018. Jak nieskończenie doskonały i niezmienny Bóg może interesować się swoim stworzeniem? Available online: https://www.it.dominikanie.pl/wp-content/uploads/2018/02/260106_o_prof_Jacek_Salij_OP.pdf (accessed on 7 August 2021).
- Słomka, Marek. 2021. God’s Action in the World. A New Philosophical Analysis. New York and London: Bloomsbury Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Sokolowski, Robert. 1995. The God of Faith and Reason. Foundations of Christian Theology. Washington: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Soskice, Janet Martin. 2007. The Kindness of God. Metaphor, Gender and Religious Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sterling, Gregory E. 1993. Platonizing Moses. Philo and Middle Platonism. Studia Philonica Annual 5: 96–111. [Google Scholar]
- Strzelczyk, Grzegorz. 2006. O cierpieniu Boga. Głos w dyskusji. In W poszukiwaniu sensu cierpienia. Dialog interdyscyplinarny. Edited by Antoni Bartoszek. Katowice and Tarnów: Wydawnictwo Diecezji Tarnowskiej Biblos, pp. 166–80. [Google Scholar]
- Stump, Eleonore, and Norman Kretzmann. 1985. Absolute Simplicity. Faith and Philosophy 2: 353–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stump, Eleonore. 2005. Aquinas. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Stump, Eleonore. 2010. Simplicity. In A Companion to Philosophy of Religion, 2nd ed. Edited by Charles Taliaferro, Paul Draper and Philip L. Quinn. Oxford and Malden: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 270–77. [Google Scholar]
- Stump, Eleonore. 2012. God’s Simplicity. In The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas. Edited by Brian Davies and Eleonore Stump. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 135–46. [Google Scholar]
- Swieżawski, Stefan. 1999. Byt. Zagadnienia metafizyki tomistycznej. Kraków: Znak. [Google Scholar]
- Tertulian. 1956. Prescription against heretics. In Early Latin Theology (Library of Christian Classics V). Translated and Edited by Stanley Lawrence Greenslade. pp. 19–64. Available online: https://www.tertullian.org/articles/greenslade_prae/greenslade_prae.htm (accessed on 17 June 2021).
- Thomas Aquinas. 1920. Summa Theologiae (Second and Revised Edition). Translated by Fathers of the English Dominican Province. London: Burns Oates and Washbourne, Online Edition Copyright © 2022 by Kevin Knight. Available online: https://www.newadvent.org/summa/ (accessed on 18 June 2021).
- Thomas Aquinas. 1955–1957. Summa Contra Gentiles (Book I). Edited by Joseph Kenny O.P. Translated by Anton C. Pegis. New York: Hanover House. Available online: https://isidore.co/aquinas/ContraGentiles1.htm (accessed on 18 June 2021).
- Torrell, Jean-Pierre. 2002. Initiation à saint Thomas d’Aquin. Sa personne et son oeuvre. Fribourg: Cerf. [Google Scholar]
- Vallicella, William F. 2008. Divine Simplicity. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/divine-simplicity/ (accessed on 18 June 2021).
- Vardy, Peter. 2015. The Puzzle of God. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Varillon, François. 1983. The Humility and Suffering of God. Translated by Nelly Marans. New York: Alba House Publisher. [Google Scholar]
- Weigel, Peter. 2008. Aquinas on Simplicity. An Investigation into the Foundations of his Philosophical Theology. Oxford: Peter Lang. [Google Scholar]
- Weinandy, Thomas. 2000. Does God Suffer? Edinburgh: T&T Clark. [Google Scholar]
- Weinandy, Thomas. 2001. Does God Suffer? First Things 117: 35–41. Available online: https://www.firstthings.com/article/2001/11/does-god-suffer (accessed on 19 August 2021).
- Weinandy, Thomas. 2002. Does God Change? (Studies in Historical Theology). New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehead, Alfred N. 1929. Process and Reality. An Essay in Cosmology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wildman, Wesley J. 1998. Evaluating the Teleological Argument for Divine Action. In Evolutionary and Molecular Biology. Scientific Perspectives on Divine Action. Edited by Robert J. Russell, William R. Stoeger and Francisco J. Ayala. Vatican City: Vatican Observatory Publications, Berkeley: The Center for Theology and the Natural Sciences, pp. 117–50. [Google Scholar]
- Wojtysiak, Jacek. 2013. Wprowadzenie do teologii naturalnej. Kraków: Dominikańskie Studium Filozofii i Teologii. [Google Scholar]
- Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 1988. Suffering Love. In Philosophy and the Christian Faith. Edited by Thomas V. Morris. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 196–237. [Google Scholar]
- Wright, Robert. 2009. The Evolution of God. New York, Boston and London: Little, Brown, and Company. [Google Scholar]
- Xenophanes of Colophon. 1992. Fragments. A Text and Translation with a Commentary. Edited by James H. Lesher. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. [Google Scholar]
- Życiński, Józef. 1988. Teizm i filozofia analityczna (Vol. II). Kraków: Znak. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Słomka, M. Noteworthy Problems with God’s Immutability, Impassibility, and Simplicity. Should We Treat These Divine Attributes and the Hellenic Conditions of Christian Theism as a Dogma? Religions 2022, 13, 759. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13080759
Słomka M. Noteworthy Problems with God’s Immutability, Impassibility, and Simplicity. Should We Treat These Divine Attributes and the Hellenic Conditions of Christian Theism as a Dogma? Religions. 2022; 13(8):759. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13080759
Chicago/Turabian StyleSłomka, Marek. 2022. "Noteworthy Problems with God’s Immutability, Impassibility, and Simplicity. Should We Treat These Divine Attributes and the Hellenic Conditions of Christian Theism as a Dogma?" Religions 13, no. 8: 759. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13080759
APA StyleSłomka, M. (2022). Noteworthy Problems with God’s Immutability, Impassibility, and Simplicity. Should We Treat These Divine Attributes and the Hellenic Conditions of Christian Theism as a Dogma? Religions, 13(8), 759. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13080759