The Ark and Other Bubbles: Jewish Philosophy and Surviving the Disaster
Abstract
:1. Introduction
The end of all flesh is come before Me; for the earth is filled with violence through them; and, behold, I will destroy them with the earth.—God
Who built the ark? Noah, Noah. Who built the ark? Brother Noah built the ark.—Traditional
2. Judaism Is Not the Solution to the Ecological Disaster
3. The Drunken Farmer Noah Is a Better Model for Jewish Philosophy Than Abraham the Herdsman
4. In Defense of Herding Things
5. The Case of the Unnatural Jew
6. Contemporary Shepherds, Imaginary Sheep
Instead of looking to human technology as the salvation of the human species, we will do better to draw our inspiration from the religious imaginaries of the monotheistic traditions—Judaism, Christianity and Islam—because they offer a meaningful narrative in which humanity and nature are interdependent but not fused into each other. A religious imaginary will enable humanity to modify and adapt its behavior in order to survive and perhaps even thrive on our damaged planet which they might heal if they choose to alter their conduct.
7. It Is Too Late for Good Behaviour
Today, the most lucid analysts do not warn against what will happen if we press the wrong buttons; they rather insist that the wrong button has already been pressed. The apocalypse has already started and is becoming an active part of our life and our world, such as it is. It is not waiting for us somewhere in the future, but is dictating our social, economic, environmental conditions as we speak.26
8. New Figures
There is little to be gained by reading [Genesis] 1–11 as a warning sign of an approaching “natural” disaster. The Noah of Genesis, unlike his equivalent in the Quran (11:25), is not a prophet trying to amend humanity’s corrupt ways before it is too late. …A better way of approaching the story of the flood would have us notice that although the Abrahamic tradition tends to relegate Armageddon to some messianic future, the Torah treats it as an accomplished fact that occurred in the primordial past. It is thus coping with the aftermath of an event that some are still anticipating.
Don’t be fooled for a second by those who preach the call of wide-open spaces, of “risk-taking”, those who abandon all protection and continue to point to the infinite horizon …. Those good apostles take risks only if their own comfort is guaranteed. Instead of listening to what they are saying about what lies ahead, look instead at what lies behind them: you’ll see the gleam of the carefully-folded golden parachutes, of everything that ensures them against the random hazards of existence.
9. How to Think Small Things
10. Looking Out, Looking At
Sloterdijk borrowed von Uexküll’s notion of Umwelt and extended it to all spheres, all enclosures, all the envelopes that agents have had to invent to differentiate between their inside and their outside… For Sloterdijk, the complete singularity of Western philosophy, science, theology, and politics lies in the fact that they have infused all the virtues into the figure of a Globe—with a capital G—without paying the slightest attention to the way in which that Globe might be built, tended, maintained, and inhabited.41
11. Jewish Thought and Maternal Spaces
12. Liberal Relationships
Many of the great central European Jewish thinkers of the previous century…recast the anthropology of the “obligated self” they inherited from classical Judaism into relational terms. In the realm of interpersonal relationships and embodied daily life, they saw the potential to understand the nature of the divine, or at least the tools with which to investigate the human relationship to the divine. These thinkers reread obligation, seeing in it not the burden imposed by a commanding God on the Jewish people, but rather a status generated in the encounter between two subjects in everyday human relationships.47
In the modern Jewish imagination, obligation would be confined to the intimate, intersubjective realm. The sphere of obligation was to be primarily realized within dyadic encounters… This restriction of obligation to the intersubjective sphere testifies both to theological creativity and, simultaneously, to the impoverishment of the scope of obligation in the modern period … What remained was the dyadic encounter with another individual, a realm protected from the social and political critiques that continued to vex practitioners of the mitzvot.
Most influential Jewish thinkers conceived of the intersubjective encounter, and therefore of the individuals who participate in it, in decidedly abstract terms. The “other” they envisioned has no specific social location or set of needs. It is difficult, on the basis of these thinkers’ writings, to imagine how such meetings occur in the course of ordinary life, and how duration of relationship, social proximity, and differences of power might affect them. An insistent tendency toward abstraction enabled these thinkers to argue for the universality of dyadic encounter and obligation.
And even as prayer is not in time but time in prayer, the sacrifice not in space but space in the sacrifice—and whoever reverses the relation annuls the reality—I do not find the human being to whom I say You in any Sometime and Somewhere.
13. Maternal Obligation in the Storm
14. Wooden Bubbles
15. Violence in the Womb (We Will Need a Better Ark)
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Kavka rightly notes that to understand the general role “catastrophe or doom plays in Jewish theology”, we cannot limit ourselves to any single text, no matter how seemingly exemplary. Instead, one would want to track the role “catastrophe” plays in the “Jewish theological imagination”. This paper is thus in no way an exploration of the general concept of disaster, or response to disaster in Judaism, or Jewish philosophy: it focuses instead on a single figure which is used to bind together a few possible responses, chosen not because they teach us about the phenomenon of Judaism but, rather, because I think they are useful for thinking about disaster, right now (Kavka 2014, p. 111). |
2 | More will be left out here than included, and Hans Jonas’ work will be noticeably absent: because much of his work, while fairly characterized as Jewish philosophy, presented itself as a form of secular Kantianism. His explicitly Jewish attempt at ecological thought will be glancingly treated, as it falls into the same trap as the other works I will survey. His Luria-inspired cosmology and theodicy will not be treated here, for as fascinating as they are, they will lead me too far afield. For the clearest articulation of his cosmology, see (Jonas 1996). See Margolin for the relationship between Jonas’ religious and secular thought (Margolin 2008). |
3 | I am not invoking the obnoxious cliché that Judaism is relentlessly particular, and therefore not helpful for universal problems. Judaism, or Jewish philosophy, is a well-known intersection between the particular and the universal, or a particular with universal significance, a space of universal particularity (and therefore illustrative of other positions) or particular universality (and therefore an instance of the manifestation of the universal), but it is one of many such intersections, and there is no reason to think it should be dominant here (Jaffee 2001). For a development of this logic, see (Erlewine 2010). For an attempt to move beyond it (as regards philosophy), see (Hughes 2014). Erlewine and Hughes are united in seeing much of Jewish philosophy as an exercise in identity construction. While I am compelled by this position, I believe there is philosophical value in staying with the tension generated by supposedly particular forms of universality. For a view that embraces this tension as productive but remains critical of apologetic employments, see (Tirosh-Samuelson et al. 2015). |
4 | Here, my concern with invoking the “Abrahamic” is not so much the levelling of particularity (as in Levenson 2012) but the strangeness of falling back on it in order to “spread”, or “generalize”, Jewish ethics. It is clear that Jews, a small group, are not going to have a particularly massive impact on ecological issues. Thus, the only way for “Jewish ethics” to do any work outside of this population is to suggest that Christian or Muslim ethics should follow the lead set by Jewish thinkers. One notes in many articles (and especially Tirosh-Samuelson’s) a convenient slippage between “Jewish thought” and “religious thought”, as if the one is isomorphic with the other (when convenient). |
5 | There are many thoughtful responses to White, but I am not entirely sure his piece is deserving of them. If one wants to make the move from a text to a political reality, more work is needed than just indexing a few problematic phrases. That said, for those looking for such a response, see Martin Yaffe’s introduction to Judaism and Environmental Ethics: A Reader (Yaffe 2001), as well as several papers therein, such as Jeremy Cohen, “On Classical Judaism and Environmental Crisis” (Cohen 2001); Jeanne Kay, “Concepts of Nature in the Hebrew Bible” (Kay 2001). The nub of Yaffe’s critique is as such: White does not ask “whether the promoters of modern science and technology were historically accurate, or merely rhetorically opportunistic, in ascribing to Genesis 1:28 or the biblical tradition the morally dubious reasoning they attached to it.” See (Yaffe 2001), p. 8. |
6 | By a negative universal, I mean a thing which affects us all (is universal), but not as a positive characteristic we all share but rather a problem which manifests differently depending on our locations. Thus, it is both equally true that the ecological collapse affects and endangers us all and, yet, does so in completely different ways depending on our location (both political and geographical). For a recent popular articulation of this, see (Butler 2021). Therefore, we are all in this together but not in the same way. If only for this reason the problem inspires apathy. Because it is hard to imagine us doing anything when the rich seem to literally respond to this by a drive to leave the planet, or at least, move to their bunkers. As for the rest of us, we are—as regards agency—by nature fractured. As Latour notes: “It would be absurd in fact to think there is a collective being, human society, that is the new agent of geohistory, as the proletariat was thought to be in an earlier epoch. In the face of the old nature—itself reconstituted—there is literally no one about whom one can say that he or she is responsible. Why? Because there is no way to unify the Anthropos as an actor endowed with some sort of moral or political consistency, to the point of charging it with being a character capable of acting on this new global stage”. See (Latour 2017), p. 122; see also p. 42. On climate apathy, see (Zupančič 2018). |
7 | It will require a level of collective action previously unseen and, for this reason alone, is terrifying. Jewish philosophy cannot guide this collective, but it might participate in it. |
8 | Kishik notes: “a winemaker is a rather dubious savior, and alcoholism is not a legitimate branch of messianism”. This, like many other gnomic statements from Kishik’s book, helped develop my reading of the ark story, without my being in accord with his overall kabbalistic or political theological claims about the nature of God in the text (as created by the “beginning”) or the desire to prescind the first several chapters of Genesis from the rest of the text. The former is too speculative for me to follow, and the latter—like many source-critical approaches—does not accord with my hermeneutic approach which (following Buber et al.) is to treat the redacted text as a whole, one that in turn inspires and influences several traditions (which are the object of my study). See (Kishik 2018), p. 61. |
9 | This saving of nonhumans is cited approvingly in Bereshit Rabbah as the reason God stopped the flooding. “AND ELOHIM REMEMBERED NOAH. What did He remember in his favour? That he provided for [the animals] the whole twelve months in the Ark, hence AND GOD REMEMBERED NOAH, and the spirit of justice approves it, for the sake of the clean animals that were with him in the Ark”. See Midrash Rabbah on Genesis: (Midrash 1983), 1:263. |
10 | I am not promoting Boethius’ view of the world or suggesting a return to Wittgenstein’s psychoanalytically inflected philosophy of mind and language (nor am I discouraging them). And I am far from presenting ataraxia as a goal of thought, or uncritically taking a Stoic position. But much as Maimonides’ Guide seeks to cure an intellectual-psychological condition, contemporary Jewish philosophy might well help us here. In this respect, I follow Hadot, but in a more circumscribed manner, holding philosophy “as a way of life” must be more circumscribed by political and social location than, say, philosophy of math. See (Hadot and Davidson 1995). |
11 | I mention this because Yaffe, despite organizing the collection, is not overly sanguine about the power of a stewardship ethics, despite this being the position argued for by an overwhelming number of the contributions. |
12 | I am thus excluding the more relentlessly critical pieces (including the Wolfson piece I will treat below) from the discussion in this section, or Jonas who asks in some articles what we should do “if we are Jews” even as the majority of his work is not aimed at a Jewish argument, nor does it appeal to Jewish authorities (although this in no way suggests the work itself is not Jewish philosophy). And even Jonas ends up calling for an ethics of restraint, one that is arguably futile. See (Jonas 2001; Scodel and Jonas, 2003). For an ecologically adjacent ethics that does not call for restraint, see the discussion of ought and can (where Serres argues that can and must are equivalent) in (Serres and Latour 1995). |
13 | I reject absolutely any claim that pantheism leads necessarily to good ecological behaviour. Seen cosmologically, the Earth is but a speck of God’s pantheistic body, and there is no reason to think it needs protection or care: these needs must have some other ground. This is, in a nutshell, the problem with David Mevorach Seidenberg’s Kabbalah and Ecology: God’s Image in the More-than-Human World: see (Seidenberg 2015). |
14 | “Nature” is a painfully fraught word, and notoriously difficult to define. One half of a number of binaries, or an all-inclusive concept of physical being, or the object of pleasure: it often obscures more than it illuminates. Thus, a very partial definition will have to do: for the analysis of the following papers, the authors seem to mean all Earthly non-human physical systems that in some way support or impinge upon human existence. |
15 | (Schwarzschild 2001), pp. 270–73. For a thorough refutation of the view that there is no incarnation in Judaism, see (Wolfson 2008; 2005; 2012) and (Magid 2015). |
16 | Intriguingly, his notion of Judaism would exclude a number of feminist approaches, and Judith Plaskow’s Standing Again at Sinai would be downright heretical. |
17 | (Schwarzschild 2001), p. 275. Note that because of a small typo in the article, this is listed as 3:9. |
18 | Here, it depends on how one reads “all the trees were created for man’s companionship”: is this more important than the conversation that trees have with one another? If so, arguably the creation of the trees remains instrumental from an anthropocentric vantage point. Seen otherwise, this allows for a more Buberian, or Jonas-inspired, philosophy of nature. See Midrash Rabbah on Genesis: (Midrash 1983), 1:100. |
19 | This is important because, citing Clingerman, it is claimed (Tirosh-Samuelson 2020, p. 391) that any discussion of ecology must take into account religion, “since religion is fundamental to how human beings understand themselves and their place in the world”. The word “fundamental” does too much work here: I can think of several forces we could call “fundamental” (love, anxiety, or sexuality, for instance), which may well need to be part of this discussion, but the case needs to be made for each fundamental. The other argument adduced is that religion is important, because these questions concern ethical “oughts”. But again, a case needs to be made as to why religion is the proper source of oughts for this discussion. Otherwise, we spare ourselves the difficult question of asking the pragmatic question: “is this useful, or are we engaging this out of necessity?” Our answer to this question will surely affect how we think about this problem. More crassly put, if the issue is just that we are religious, then surely Jewish responses will be unimportant to anyone other than Jews, and there are hardly enough Jews to matter as regards ecology. |
20 | Indeed, as Latour notes, “At the very moment when it was becoming fashionable to speak of the “post-human” in the blasé tones of those who know that the time of the human is “outdated”, the “Anthropos” has come back—and with a vengeance—owing to the thankless empirical work of researchers whose lack of culture intellectuals like to mock by calling them mere “naturalists”. See (Latour 2017), p. 117. |
21 | (Tirosh-Samuelson 2020), p. 417 (emphasis added). |
22 | By qualified anthropomorphism, I mean a pragmatic position which places humans at the centre of a set of fundamental problems but not therefore as metaphysically central. |
23 | Anthropocentrism modified to say the human is at the centre of our thought and action is not the same as anthropomorphism, or the belief that humans are intrinsically superior to all other forms of life. See Shaviro for an apposite discussion, albeit one which comes to the opposite conclusion I take. See (Shaviro 2014). |
24 | My work here is influenced deeply by Samuel Moyn’s critique of “rights” language, and the cold-war re-use of natural law language to ground “rights” and “ethics” as a substitute for serious political transformation. See (Moyn 2018). |
25 | Indeed, as suggested above, Tirosh-Samuelson’s claim that religion is important because people are religious really means little more than “we will be unable to convince people unless we can translate ecological thought into religious language”; in other words, religion is useful for propaganda. This may well be true, but this is a tactical, not philosophical, position. Note above that Jonas, despite his long studies of political forms and ecology, often falls back on the notion that what is needed is ethical and aesthetic “restraint”. |
26 | (Zupančič 2018), p. 24 (emphasis in original). |
27 | Neither can it merely turn to nihilism, and take pleasure in the supposedly sublime act of destruction. See (Heglar 2019). Kant is correct when he notes that the sublime can only be enjoyed from a position of safety, and who would dare to claim such a position now? |
28 | See Braiterman on the collapse of theodicy after the holocaust for a recent example. (Braiterman 1998). |
29 | For a thorough critique of the identity-building function Jewish philosophy serves, see (Hughes 2014). Where I part way with Hughes is that I think tarrying with the tension between particular and universal allows for a philosophy that takes account of the role it plays in discourses of power while still unapologetically using this tension to develop concepts. |
30 | It is also the case that the flood episode is not, strictly speaking, an apocalypse: it lacks the revelation, and in terms of genre conventions, the encounter with God is completely lacking in the visual element which is so preponderant in the ancient apocalypses. From a properly philosophical perspective, the flood episode in Genesis (as when an “ark” saves the baby Moses) keeps a firm distinction between space and time (unlike the apocalypses, where they bleed into one another) and the element of a divine secret is completely lacking. See (Wolfson 2000). For the visual element, see the introduction and chapter one in (Collins 2016). As well see (Henning 2020). Finally, for the genre conventions of ancient apocalyptic literature, see (Himmelfarb 2010). |
31 | For a thorough social-political critique of the way ethical monotheism has been used to construct Jewish identity, see (Erlewine 2010). |
32 | It is these figures—more than any specific code of behaviour—that I think “religion” in general, and Judaism in particular, can offer thinking when it moves into new domains. Following Peirce, I think much of our thinking is directed by images, icons, and diagrams, and much of our work is little more than the protection and extrapolation of these figures. |
33 | Each of these further opens up other resources for Jewish thought: Wolfson obviously opens up elements of the mystical tradition for philosophical analysis (and vice versa), and I will contentiously suggest Benjamin provides us with the tools for a philosophical analysis of psychoanalysis, especially in its Kleinian formation. |
34 | As noted above, I am committed to the position that a great deal of philosophical work consists in working out the details of a pre-existing image or shape, or if the reader prefers, that many of our pre-theoretical commitments have a form (often visual, but not always). This dovetails nicely with the phenomenological tradition (as epitomized in Jewish philosophy by Elliot Wolfson) where the forms of thinking this paper suggests would consist of the working out of a phenomenological vision, or form of “seeing”. It also accords with the closely related hermeneutic school, as these shapes are thought in relation to a text (and the text interpreted through these forms of thought). Here I include everything from Derrida, Plaskow, to Ochs and his school of textual reasoners. Braiterman has further demonstrated that a great deal of early 20th century Jewish aesthetic and religious thought was dominated by the relation between forms and the formless. My direct inspiration for this approach is, however, more mundane, owing itself to Peirce and his belief that the foundation of most thinking is iconic. For those who find no value in any of these approaches, I hope what follows provides some value if only for the possibilities it marks out. The two books that most inform this project’s phenomenology are: (Wolfson 1994, 2011). On shape, see (Braiterman 2007). |
35 | Note Schwarzschild and Tirosh-Samuelson both call upon the various monotheisms to join together as shepherds (and here they have good company). This figure is far more expansive still and has the virtue of not reducing other groups to “offshoots” of Judaism. A reviewer has helpfully noted that the covenant made at the end of the story (Genesis 9:12–13) is a covenant made with the earth itself (including all of its inhabitants), and this can be employed to undercut the claim to theological supremacy on the part of all specific so-called Abrahamic religions, further increasing the figure’s extension. |
36 | One can more easily make extravagant claims with Kishik (“The ark is God’s hedge against this genocide, which is actually a biocide, for even the basic distinction between man and animal is lost at the moment the waters gush through the land”) than actually picture this object. Granted this has not prevented countless illustrators and toy makers from trying (Kishik 2018, p. 65). |
37 | This text is not afraid to make massive extrapolations from a very small amount of data, but this is perhaps understandable in an area where there is not much data to be had. I nonetheless restricted myself to Finkel’s more sober insights and ignored his extrapolations, where possible (Finkel 2014). |
38 | With these words, a link is drawn between the Noah myth and the beginning of the political drama of Exodus: “she took for him an ark of bulrushes, and daubed it with slime and with pitch; and she put the child therein, and laid it in the flags by the river’s brink” (Exodus 2:3) |
39 | See Midrash Rabbah on Genesis: (Midrash 1983), 1:263. |
40 | Sloterdijk’s trilogy operates very much in the background, and I would suggest any thinking of enclosures would have to take him seriously, especially the first volume (Bubbles). There are echoes of modern Jewish philosophy (especially Buber) throughout the book (it is notable that Sloterdijk wrote an introduction to Buber’s ecstatic Confessions). While here I mostly employ the critique of the Globe (volume 2), it is the “bipolar intimacy” which comes from a community of breathers that inspires my vision of an ark-intimacy. (Sloterdijk 2011). It is easy (perhaps too easy) to accuse this text of conservatism: viewed as a text about intimacy and desire, and the systems liberalism ignores which maintain these spaces, it is of immense value. |
41 | Also, here Jonas’ work on metabolism—and not his ethics—recommends itself for any future thinking of ecological disaster on the part of Jewish philosophy. See (Latour 2017), p. 122. |
42 | It is for this reason Bereshit Rabbah presents two opposing readings of “Noah was in his generations a man righteous and whole-hearted” [Gen 6:9]: it could mean either that he was only righteous in comparison to the horrendous people of his generation or that it is doubly impressive a person from such a loathsome generation was able to be righteous. |
43 | That both the Genesis and Gilgamesh floods use birds as sense organs, or instruments, is not unimportant here. |
44 | Here Kishik’s reading over-reaches in his attempt to see the planet itself as an ark: “Seen from outer space, this planet is itself an ark floating in an unlivable void. The very fact that there is an earth, where special conditions make the lives of animals and plants possible (even if they are miserable), is extremely abnormal from a cosmological perspective. As with the ark and with the garden, God did not intend the earth to embody a universal and boundless truth, for it was fashioned from the start as a rather small space for living, beyond which reigns heavenly death” (Kishik 2018, p. 62). But of course this is not the case: there was no one outside the ark to look at it, other than God. And we are not gods: indeed, the ecological crisis calls Feuerbach into question in a manner no Marxist was ever able to. As an aside, it is Feuerbach’s Principles, more than any of his religious texts, where his transformation of theological principles into anthropological ones is on full display (Feuerbach 1986). |
45 | See (Latour 2017), p. 136. As Kishik notes: “We must … rethink what it means to be made in the likeness of God. It seems that humanity, like the deity, can provoke a global cataclysm” (Kishik 2018, p. 63). In anticipation of the following reading, Benjamin also claims that the maternal position can give one insight into the character of God, but this is surely as much an attempt to transform the way we see god as the manner in which we understand maternity. She writes: “From Ludwig Feuerbach to Sigmund Freud, modern theorists of religion have insisted that theology arises from human experience. God, in this tradition, has been named as merely a projection of human desires and anxieties. Freud in particular named this projection as specifically infantile: the personal God is simply the exalted image of a powerful, protective father figure. Rather than seeking to evade the legacy of modernity, I hope to unearth a potentially subversive implication that runs counter to its secularizing thrust: to be a parent is to gain insight into what it means to be the God of the Hebrew Bible and the rabbinic imagination” (Benjamin 2018, p. xiv). |
46 | Thinkers as various as Kristeva, Melanie Klein, Winnicott, Sloterdijk, and Sedgwick, often treated or used only glancingly, could make a genuine contribution to this way of approaching the disaster. This of course presumes Jewish philosophy “wants” to think about ecological disaster, which so far seems not to be the case. |
47 | This goes a long way to explaining why so much 20th-century Jewish thought is better understood as philosophical anthropology than, say, metaphysics (as one might perhaps characterize the classics of Arabic Jewish philosophy). See (Benjamin 2018), p. xv. |
48 | The liberal (and neo-liberal) adoration for empty spaces in which bodies self-organize can sneak into the work of even the most careful and thoughtful philosophers and theologians. Andrea Poma, an extraordinary interpreter, actually exacerbates this tendency in Buber in an attempt to accommodate post-modern criticism (Poma 2006). It is even more bizarre to see this fantasy of empty space in the work of leftists: thinking about enclosure and bubbles should not be left only to conservative thinkers such as Sloterdijk (who remains one of the greatest contemporary thinkers of enclosure and the need for safety). |
49 | The work of Elliot Wolfson provides another, phenomenological, approach to containment thinking. Again, as with my treatment of Benjamin, this would require some shifting of emphases, and perhaps even distortion, of his work. There are two resources that leap to mind in which Wolfson’s work offers containment thinking. The first is a thoroughgoing critique of the way kabbalist sources employ the feminine enclosure, and the rose-tinted appropriation of these “feminine” elements of the godhead (covered in some detail below). The second is his philosophical exposition of a number of kabbalistic principles, figures, and themes, where (to simplify) the finite protects the infinite. Perhaps the crudest instance of this is the claim that the name protects the name, meaning that the “revealed” or spoken name (Adonai) encloses and protects the “hidden” name (YHWH). From this starting point, the aporias and paradoxes of enclosure can be established (I owe this observation in part to conversations with Zachary Braiterman). An instance closer to my heart is the work on fragments and wholes, where the fragment encloses and protects the whole (of fragments). This leads into a fundamental tension at the heart of Jewish thought, the universal and the singular; read through Wolfson, we need not see the singular as a “piece” of the universal, but rather, see the universal only through the singular. Where I distort Wolfson is by emphasizing the protective element of these enclosures. For a discussion of the name, see (Wolfson 2015). For fragments, see (Wolfson 2019), pp. 220–30. |
50 | Benjamin deliberately sticks with the word “maternal” (rather than “parental”) in order to not obscure the ways gendered power relations inform this form of relationship, and I follow her in this. See (Benjamin 2018). |
51 | I would note that precisely here it would be useful to bring back Melanie Klein and both Freuds into the canon of modern Jewish thought, or at least develop a stronger conversation about their work: their extensive work with children and child rearing could go a long way to rectifying this absence Benjamin notes. See (Benjamin 2018), p. xiv. |
52 | Note that many parents who seek a friendship relationship (or seek to be “best friends”) with their children, often just generate confusion and alienation. |
53 | As is common, Jonas is something of an exception here. |
54 | It would be interesting to examine Arnold Eisen’s work in relation to the forms of familial enclosure-systems that allow for, and are created by, American Judaism. Neusner also recommends himself somewhat: if Judaism is a “religion of pots and pans”, one needs a place to keep them. |
55 | See notes 39. |
56 | He would of course be unsurprised: we find the grotesque in the “mythology and…archaic art of all peoples”. The basic dialectic of this grotesque inversion, while not exactly applicable to the ark, remains very useful for this “archaic” wooden bubble, and those we might need in the future: “Negation and destruction of the object are therefore their displacement and reconstruction in space. The nonbeing of an object is its ‘other face’, its inside out. And this inside out or lower stratum acquires a time element; it may be conceived as the past, the obsolete, or the nonexistent. The object that has been destroyed remains in the world but in a new form of being in time and space; it becomes the ‘other side’ of the new object that has taken its place” (Bakhtin 1984, pp. 30, 410). The primary difference here is that this is a grander reversal than the carnival: the carnival assumes the survival of “the world” and therefore is an inversion of objects in this world. The ark is the inversion of the world made into an object. |
57 | See Midrash Rabbah on Genesis: (Midrash 1983), 1:244. |
58 | For a magisterial reading of cuteness and its appropriations, see (Ngai 2012). |
59 | The film itself seems to draw from various midrashim, but the movie’s Noah himself is a violent zealot who seems to be enacting a critique of contemporary “Christian” morality. He is puritanical in the extreme and sees himself as called not to save life but rather to be part of the purging of human existence. Here, “completing the work of creation” is to complete the destruction of human animals. The ark here is also a partial product of the “Watchers” and, rather than a maternal space, is a place of violence with the animals sedated and the human beings enacting a stark and ascetic drama which recalls the akedah more than any traditions related to Noah (Aronofsky 2014). In this way, Noah is a dark mirror of Benjamin’s claim that in these spaces, it becomes impossible to determine the source of law and obligation: “As my own experiences of motherhood over the years have demonstrated, the boundaries between ‘external’ and ‘internal’— like the difference between the law of the other and the law of the self—are not so clear. Not only bearing a child but also loving and caring for one breaks down these formal categories. The child for whom one takes responsibility becomes part of oneself. When that happens, it is impossible to know whether the law comes from outside or from within”. See (Benjamin 2018), p. xviii. |
60 | See Midrash Rabbah on Genesis: (Midrash 1983), 1:247. |
61 | For a study of Buber’s womb-appropriation (and erasure) and Levinas’ employment of the feminine (famously criticized by de Beauvoir in the Second Sex), see (Benjamin 2013). On Levinas, the feminine, mystery, and modesty, see (Wolfson 1996). |
62 | Attempts to “make” the kabbalistic sources reflect contemporary gender norms, or express feminist positions—while ignoring the tradition’s unmistakable androcentrism—are a case study in what I hope to avoid here. For a corrective, see Wolfson, especially the fourth study here (Wolfson 1995). This is particularly pertinent, given that this androcentric tradition uses the idea of feminine enclosures as a means of thinking the godhead, and these enclosures have been read as providing a feminist alternative to “traditional” theology. However, as Wolfson notes at length, and in several studies, these readings assume an androgynous “body” for God, where we would be better reading the God presented in these sources as a “male androgyne”: the “return” of the female enclosure to the male is a condition of redemption (Wolfson 2015). |
References
- Aronofsky, Darren. 2014. Noah. Regency: Hollywood. [Google Scholar]
- Bakhtin, Mikhail Mikhaĭlovich. 1984. Rabelais and His World. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Benjamin, Mara. 2013. Intersubjectivity Meets Maternity: Buber, Levinas, and the Eclipsed Relation. In Thinking Jewish Culture in America. Edited by Kenneth Koltun-Fromm. Lanham: Lexington Books. [Google Scholar]
- Benjamin, Mara. 2018. The Obligated Self: Maternal Subjectivity and Jewish Thought. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Blanchot, Maurice. 1997. The Holocaust Is Disappointing. Translated by Elizabeth Rottenberg. In Friendship. Redwood City: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Braiterman, Z. 1998. (God) after Auschwitz: Tradition and Change in Post-Holocaust Jewish Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Braiterman, Zachary. 2007. The Shape of Revelation: Aesthetics and Modern Jewish Thought. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1970. I and Thou. Translated by Walter Arnold Kaufmann. New York: Scribner. [Google Scholar]
- Butler, Judith. 2021. Creating an Inhabitable World for Humans Means Dismantling Rigid Forms of Individuality. Time. Available online: https://time.com/5953396/judith-butler-safe-world-individuality/ (accessed on 5 June 2022).
- Cohen, Jeremy. 2001. On Classical Judaism and Environmental Crisis. In Judaism and Environmental Ethics: A Reader. Lanham: Lexington Books. [Google Scholar]
- Collins, John J. 2016. The Apocalyptic Imagination: An Introduction to Jewish Apocalyptic Literature. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Erlewine, Robert. 2010. Monotheism and Tolerance: Recovering a Religion of Reason. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Feuerbach, Ludwig. 1986. Principles of the Philosophy of the Future. Translated by Manfred Vogel. Indianapolis: Hackett. [Google Scholar]
- Finkel, Irving L. 2014. The Ark before Noah: Decoding the Story of the Flood, 1st American ed. New York: Doubleday. [Google Scholar]
- Freud, Sigmund. 2010. Civilization and Its Discontents. Translated by James Strachey. New York: W.W. Norton & Company. [Google Scholar]
- George, Andrew R. 2000. The Epic of Gilgamesh: The Babylonian Epic Poem and Other Texts in Akkadian and Sumerian. New York: Penguin Books. [Google Scholar]
- Hadot, Pierre, and Arnold I. Davidson. 1995. Philosophy as a Way of Life: Spiritual Exercises from Socrates to Foucault. Malden: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Heglar, Mary Annaïse. 2019. Home Is Always Worth It. Available online: https://medium.com/@maryheglar/home-is-always-worth-it-d2821634dcd9 (accessed on 5 June 2022).
- Heidegger, Martin. 1993. Der Spiegel Interview. In The Heidegger Controversy: A Critical Reader. Edited by Richard Wolin. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Henning, Meghan. 2020. Apocalyptic Literature. In The Cambridge Companion to the Bible and Literature. Edited by Calum Carmichael. Cambridge Companions to Religion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Himmelfarb, Martha. 2010. The Apocalypse: A Brief History. Hoboken: Wiley. [Google Scholar]
- Hughes, Aaron W. 2014. Rethinking Jewish Philosophy: Beyond Particularism and Universalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Ezra, Abraham ben Me’ir. 1988. Ibn Ezra’s Commentary on the Pentateuch. Translated by H. Norman Strickman. New York: Menorah Pub. Co., vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Jaffee, Martin S. 2001. One God, One Revelation, One People: On the Symbolic Structure of Elective Monotheism. Journal of the American Academy of Religion 69: 753–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jonas, Hans. 1984. The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jonas, Hans. 1996. Matter, Mind, and Creation: Cosmological Evidence and Cosmogonic Speculation. In Mortality and Morality: A Search for Good after Auschwitz. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jonas, Hans. 2001. Contemporary Problems in Ethics from a Jewish Perspective. In Judaism and Environmental Ethics: A Reader. Lexington: Lexington Books. [Google Scholar]
- Kavka, Martin. 2014. Catastrophes: A History and Theory of an Operative Concept. In Ending Time and Again in Ruins: Catastrophe and Its Discontents in Jewish Theology. Edited by Lebovic Nitzan and Killen Andreas. Berlin: De Gruyter Oldenbourg. [Google Scholar]
- Kay, Jeanne. 2001. Concepts of Nature in the Hebrew Bible. In Judaism and Environmental Ethics: A Reader. Lanham: Lexington Books. [Google Scholar]
- Kishik, David. 2018. The Book of Shem: On Genesis before Abraham. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Latour, Bruno. 2017. Facing Gaia: Eight Lectures on the New Climatic Regime. Translated by Catherine Porter. Hoboken: Wiley. [Google Scholar]
- Latour, Bruno. 2018. Down to Earth: Politics in the New Climatic Regime. Translated by Cathy Porter. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Levenson, Jon D. 2012. Inheriting Abraham: The Legacy of the Patriarch in Judaism, Christianity, and Islam. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Levinas, Emmanuel. 2004. On Buber. In Levinas and Buber: Dialogue and Difference. Edited by Matthew Calarco and Maurice Friedman Peter Atterton. Pittsburgh: Dusquene University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Magid, Shaul. 2015. Hasidism Incarnate: Hasidism, Christianity, and the Construction of Modern Judaism. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Margolin, Ron. 2008. Hans Jonas and Secular Religiosity. In The Legacy of Hans Jonas. Leiden: Brill, pp. 231–58. [Google Scholar]
- Midrash, Rabbah. 1983. Genesis. Translated by Harry Mordecai Freedman. Edited by Maurice Simon and Harry Mordecai Freedman. London: Soncino Press, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Moyn, Samuel. 2018. Not Enough: Human Rights in an Unequal World. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ngai, Sianne. 2012. Our Aesthetic Categories: Zany, Cute, Interesting. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Poma, Andrea. 2006. Unity of the Heart and Scattered Self: A Postmodern Reading of Buber’s Doctrine of Evil. In New Perspectives on Martin Buber. Edited by Michael Zank. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. [Google Scholar]
- Schwarzschild, Steven S. 2001. The Unnatural Jew. Lexington: Lexington Books. [Google Scholar]
- Scodel, Harvey, and Hans Jonas. 2003. An Interview with Professor Hans Jonas. Social Research 70: 339–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Seidenberg, David Mevorach. 2015. Kabbalah and Ecology: God’s Image in the More-Than-Human World. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Serres, Michel, and Bruno Latour. 1995. Conversations on Science, Culture, and Time. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. [Google Scholar]
- Shaviro, Steven. 2014. The Universe of Things: On Speculative Realism. Posthumanities. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sloterdijk, Peter. 2011. Bubbles. Los Angeles: Semiotext(e). [Google Scholar]
- Tirosh-Samuelson, Hava, Aaron W. Hughes, and Eliot Wolfson. 2015. Interview with Elliot R. Wolfson. Leiden: Brill, pp. 195–244. [Google Scholar]
- Tirosh-Samuelson, Hava. 2020. Human Flourishing and History: A Religious Imaginary for the Anthropocene (in English). Journal of the Philosophy of History 14: 382–418. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- White, Lynn. 1967. The Historical Roots of Our Ecologic Crisis. Science 155: 1203–7. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Wolfson, Elliot R. 1994. Through a Speculum That Shines: Vision and Imagination in Medieval Jewish Mysticism. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfson, Elliot R. 1995. Circle in the Square: Studies in the Use of Gender in Kabbalistic Symbolism. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfson, Elliot R. 1996. From Sealed Book to Open Text: Time, Memory, and Narrativity in Kabbalistic Hermeneutics. In Interpreting Judaism in a Postmodern Age. Edited by Steven Kepnes. New York: NYU Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfson, Elliot R. 2000. Gazing beneath the Veil: Apocalyptic Envisioning the End. In Reinterpreting Revelation and Tradition: Jews and Christians in Conversation. Edited by Hayim Goren Perelmuter and John Pawlikowski. London: Sheed & Ward. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfson, Elliot R. 2005. The Body in the Text: A Kabbalistic Theory of Embodiment. The Jewish Quarterly Review 95: 479–500. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wolfson, Elliot R. 2008. Judaism and Incarnation. In Christianity in Jewish Terms. New York: Basic Books. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfson, Elliot R. 2011. A Dream Interpreted within a Dream: Oneiropoiesis and the Prism of Imagination. New York: Zone Books. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfson, Elliot R. 2012. Textual Flesh, Incarnation, and the Imaginal Body: Abraham Abulafia’s Polemic with Christianity. In Studies in Medieval Jewish Intellectual and Social History. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfson, Elliot R. 2015. Occultation of the Feminine and the Body of Secrecy in Medieval Kabbalah. In Elliot R. Wolfson: Poetic Thinking. Edited by Hava Tirosh-Samuelson and Aaron W. Hughes. Leiden: Brill, pp. 35–68. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfson, Elliot R. 2019. Heidegger and Kabbalah: Hidden Gnosis and the Path of Poiēsis. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Yaffe, Martin. 2001. Introduction. In Judaism and Environmental Ethics: A Reader. Lexington: Lexington Books. [Google Scholar]
- Zupančič, Alenka. 2018. The Apocalypse Is (Still) Disappointing. S: Journal of the Circle for Lacanian Ideology Critique 11: 16–30. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Atlas, D. The Ark and Other Bubbles: Jewish Philosophy and Surviving the Disaster. Religions 2022, 13, 1152. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13121152
Atlas D. The Ark and Other Bubbles: Jewish Philosophy and Surviving the Disaster. Religions. 2022; 13(12):1152. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13121152
Chicago/Turabian StyleAtlas, Dustin. 2022. "The Ark and Other Bubbles: Jewish Philosophy and Surviving the Disaster" Religions 13, no. 12: 1152. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13121152
APA StyleAtlas, D. (2022). The Ark and Other Bubbles: Jewish Philosophy and Surviving the Disaster. Religions, 13(12), 1152. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13121152