1. A Problem of Evil
“By the way, a Bulgarian I met lately in Moscow’, Ivan went on … ‘told me about the crimes committed by Turks and Circassians in all parts of Bulgaria through fear of a general rising of the Slavs. They burn villages, murder, outrage women and children, they nail their prisoners by the ears to the fences, leave them so till morning, and in the morning they hang them—all sorts of things you can’t imagine. People talk sometimes of bestial cruelty, but that’s a great injustice and insult to the beasts; a beast can never be so cruel as a man, so artistically cruel…. These Turks took a pleasure in torturing children too; cutting the unborn child from the mothers’ womb, and tossing babies up in the air and catching them on the points of their bayonets before their mothers’ eyes. Doing it before the mothers’ eyes was what gave zest to the amusement”.
Theisms of all stripes face the problem of reconciling the existence of a good, almighty, and omniscient God with what has been termed “evil”, such as suffering and physical and mental dysfunction. David Hume, citing the ancient philosopher Epicurus, put it this way: “Is [God] willing to prevent evil, but not able? then is he impotent. Is he able, but not willing? then is he malevolent. Is he both able and willing? whence then is evil?” (
Hume 1980, p. 63). Given God’s properties, he goes on, “Might not God exterminate all ill, wherever it were to be found, and produce all good, without any preparation or long progress of causes and effects?” (
Hume 1980, p. 70).
Traditional discussions of the problem of evil have distinguished two kinds of evil. Moral evil is all the instances of pain and suffering—physical and mental—and all states of affairs significantly disadvantageous to organisms that are caused by actions for which human agents can be held morally accountable. Natural evil, on the other hand, is all instances of pain and suffering—physical and mental—and all states of affairs significantly disadvantageous to organisms that are caused by actions for which human agents cannot be held morally accountable. A host of causes of natural evils include natural calamities, animals and insects, diseases, and genetic malfunctions (
Reichenbach 1982, p. xi).
The problem of evil is often structured as either a logical problem or an evidential problem. According to the logical version, the theist affirms an inconsistent set of propositions, namely, that God exists, God has a particular set of properties including goodness, omnipotence, and omniscience, and evil exists. J.L. Mackie wrote that these contentions, supplemented by “some quasi-logical rules connecting the terms ‘good’, ‘evil’, and ‘omnipotent’”, (
Mackie 1955, pp. 201–2) and one of the rules being an analytic, ethical principle, will establish the self-contradiction. Mackie proffers the following ethical principle: “A good omnipotent thing eliminates evil as far as it can”, and since it is omnipotent, it can eliminate all evil
1. As has been frequently pointed out, this principle is inadequate (
Plantinga 1974, pp. 17–24). The principle that Mackie needs to make his case is that “An omnipotent and omniscient thing can eliminate every evil state of affairs without losing a greater good or producing a greater evil” (
Reichenbach 1982, p. 6). For our purposes, what is important is that this principle appeals to a greater good—what is termed a morally sufficient reason —and appeals to greater goods have been made to counter Mackie’s claim
2.
According to the evidential or inductive argument, “the variety and profusion of evil in our world … provides rational support for the belief that the theistic God does not exist” (
Rowe 1979, p. 86). The argument here is that, given God’s properties and the quantity and quality of evil in the world, it is unlikely or improbable that a God who is good, omnipotent, omniscient, and loving exists. This also raises the issue of whether all evil has a justification in terms of a greater good or whether there is pointless or gratuitous evil.
Seyyed Mousavirad, along with many theists, contends that there is no gratuitous evil and that all evil has a purpose and can be justified by appealing to a greater good
3. A good and powerful God would eliminate all gratuitous evil, and a greater good would be served. Again, then, the appeal to a greater good serves an important role in addressing the problem of evil.
In response to the problem of evil, some philosophers have chosen to offer a defense. A defense shows that there is no contradiction or inconsistency because a possible greater good might be invoked to defuse the antitheist argument
4. In contrast to a theodicy, which seeks to suggest a plausible, justifying reason for God bringing about or allowing suffering, a defense does not make any claim regarding whether this is an actual reason or not; only a possible defusing reason is offered. Often this is given in terms of a greater good such as free will (
Plantinga 1974, pp. 29–34), although skeptical theists offer an alternative reasoning, contending that we would have no way of knowing what God’s reasoning might be
5. Mousavirad does not adopt a skeptical theist or cognitive limitation defense but rather develops a greater good theodicy by appealing to a morally sufficient reason. His proposal is that traditional greater good theodicies have failed and need to be supplemented by giving a reason for there being evil in the world in the first place. The greater good he invokes is that evil will be compensated in the afterlife
6.
2. Compensation Theodicy
Addressing a compensation theodicy, Dostoevsky writes through his character Ivan,
“Yet,… in the final result I don’t accept this world of God’s and, although I know it exists, I don’t accept it at all. It’s not that I don’t accept God, you must understand; it’s the world created by Him I don’t and cannot accept.… I believe like a child that suffering will be healed and made up for, that all the humiliating absurdity of human contradictions will vanish like a pitiful mirage,… that at the moment of eternal harmony, something so precious will come to pass that it will suffice for all hearts, for the comforting of all resentments, for the atonement of all the cries of humanity, of all the blood they’ve shed; that it will make it not only possible to forgive but to justify all that has happened with men—but though all that may come to pass, I don’t accept it. I won’t accept it”.
Ivan can understand the compensation theodicy, maybe even think that it makes sense, at least from a child’s perspective, but he cannot accept it. And why not?
“Tell me. I challenge you—answer. Imagine that you are creating a fabric of human destiny with the object of making me happy in the end, giving them peace and rest at least, but that it was essential and inevitable to torture to death only one tiny creature—a baby beating its breast with its fist, for instance—and to found that edifice on its unavenged tears, would you consent to be the architect on those conditions?... And can you admit the idea that men for whom you are building it would agree to accept their happiness on the foundation of the unexpiated blood of a little victim? And accepting it would remain happy for ever?”
Ivan rejects a justification for suffering that appeals to a compensating greater good in an afterlife. Addressing the instances of evil that we have already mentioned, Ivan says, “I must have justice, or I will destroy myself. And not justice in some remote infinite time and space, but here on earth, and that I could see myself” (
Dostoyevsky 2009, Book 5, chp. 4). Happiness in the afterlife cannot be constructed on the back of suffering in this life.
Although he does not reference Dostoyevsky’s presentation (and although there is some doubt that Ivan’s reflections reflect Dostoyevsky’s own view (
McCullough 2018, pp. 206–7)) but rather derives his view from a Muslim theological background, in a recent article, Seyyed Mousavirad invites us to reconsider a greater good theodicy of compensation, one that attempts to address Ivan’s concern with placing the justification for evil in the afterlife. Mousavirad contends that not only are all evils justified in that God compensates the sufferer in an afterlife, but because the evils we experience produce some good, God has reason for bringing about or allowing evils in the first place (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 211).
3. Weak and Strong Versions of the Compensatory Theodicy
Mousavirad distinguishes between what he terms weak and strong versions of the compensation theodicy. According to the weak version, natural and moral evils experienced are justified because God compensates for them in an afterlife of bliss. God provides the sufferer such an abundance of “pleasure and bounties in heaven that [the sufferer] feels that these pleasures and bounties are far greater than the pain and suffering he endured in the world” (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 212).
This theodicy is present in Islamic thought.
7 For example, Suleiman Hani writes, “One facet of Islamic theodicy is that one second in Paradise eliminates an entire lifetime’s worth of hardship and suffering, and the first moment is Paradise is so overwhelmingly blissful that it
erases the potent memories and pain of prior adversity…. Suffering is never absolute and suffering certainly never outweighs the good that is rewarded to the one who suffers” (
Hani 2022)
8.
Victor Shammas advances a similar compensation theodicy. “The problem of evil withers away once we frame earthly evils, plentiful as they may appear, within their proper context of a potentially limitless, eternal bliss in Heaven…. [It is] a sort of optical illusion, a deceptive sleight of hand forced upon us by sensuous earthly reality and our corporeal state of being” (
Shammas 2019). For him, the very weightiness and enormity of eternal bliss tip any scale that compares earthly suffering to the afterlife—a grain of sand compared to the vast expanse of the Sahara. Paradise is the great reward for the heroic struggle.
Mousavirad rejects this weak version of the compensation theodicy on the grounds that it fails to provide a reason for God bringing about or allowing evil in the first place. Instead, he constructs what he terms a strong compensation theodicy, according to which all evils are justified in that God compensates individuals for them in an afterlife and they produce some good here and now. Producing good here and now provides a reason for God bringing about or allowing evils in the first place: evils are necessary for there to be good (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 216). It is not that the evils necessarily produce good for the individual sufferer or that the good outweighs the evil. Rather, in this life, each evil produces some good, and consequently, God’s allowance of the evil is thereby shown to be purposeful. This version of his compensation theodicy thus invokes a version of the greater good argument in that the goods produced here and now and the eternal goods dispensed in the afterlife together justify the presence and experience of evil in this life. In effect, he holds that this theodicy preserves both God’s
justice in that evils are compensated for in the Hereafter and God’s purposefulness and
wisdom in bringing about or allowing evil in that evils produce some good in this life (
Mousavirad 2022, pp. 213–14).
4. Premise 1: All Evil Produces Good
In defending his theodicy, Mousavirad invokes three premises. First, he contends that “Evils have some good, and the existence of these evils is necessary to attain these goods; thus, these evils are not futile, even if the good within evils do (sic) not outweigh evils” (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 214). I take this to be a universal claim about evils; otherwise, evils that fail to produce good would be gratuitous, and, on his account, there are no gratuitous evils.
For Mousavirad, it is good (and necessary for there to be good) that there be evil in this world, for good cannot be realized without evil. “The existence of evils is required for some goods” (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 215). However, though this is true, from thinking that “the existence of evils is required for some goods” it does not follow logically that
all evils produce some good, such that no evil is futile, as Mousavirad claims (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 221). Although Mousavirad assumes that all evil is meaningful, such a contention is not obviously true; indeed, I think it is dubious. However, whether gratuitous evils exist is a contentious issue that we cannot pursue here (
Wykstra 1984, pp. 73–94).
5. Premise 2: Compensation as Justice
For his second premise, Mousavirad contends that “Since the suffering and harms of evils will be compensated in the afterlife, they are just and fair” (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 214) He contends that compensation produces justice, such that God is justified in bringing about or allowing evils because God compensates sufferers for the evils in the afterlife.
Premise 2, whereby compensation establishes “justice and fairness”, invokes a problematic concept of justice in terms of consequences. Suppose that A kidnaps B, subjecting B to painful torture and other forms of degradation. At the same time, A promises B that when A releases B, A will compensate B for B’s pain and suffering. One surely cannot contend that A’s treatment of B is just and fair on the grounds that A compensates B for the evil done to B. No matter how A compensates B, the actions of A are morally unjustified. To see this, one might ask how much should A pay B for the maltreatment: one thousand euros; one hundred thousand; one million? The abducted and tortured B might rightly reply that nothing can compensate him for what A did to him
9.
Mousavirad considers this objection and replies that the above example applies to the weak compensation theodicy but not to his strong compensation theodicy, for, as he notes, by adding to compensation in the afterlife producing some good in this life, the evil is shown to have purpose and thereby is justified. The good need not exceed the evil. All that is required for the evil action (and evildoer) to be fair and just is that the sufferer be compensated
and that some good in this life result from the evil action (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 216).
It might be remarked that this still is suspect since A might intend evil for B and only incidentally or accidentally produce good out of the evil. That is, although A actually intends evil and by chance some good results (since all evil, according to Mousavirad, results in good), for Mousavirad A’s actions would remain justified. It would seem that intentions should matter in determining the justice of actions.
Suppose, however, we add both the intention to produce good and the production of some good to our above story. Suppose that A says that what A is doing in this kidnapping and torture is giving B the opportunity for soul-building. A kidnaps B, subjects B to painful torture, and tells B that he is doing B a favor because A’s intent is to improve B’s character. For when A is finished with his torture, B will have the opportunity to develop more fortitude, patience, and empathy with other sufferers, and indeed, B will be able to see the good that this made possible. And not only that, A will compensate B for his troubles. Thus, both of Mousavirad’s conditions are met: the action produces good, and B is compensated.
Again, however, it is clear that adding good intentions, the possibility of soul-building, and the good of B being able to make a free choice in responding to the torture does not make the painful acts A inflicts on B “just and fair”. No matter how A compensates B, the actions of A are morally unjustified, if for no other reason than that B never gave A consent to attempt to improve B’s character. Meeting these two conditions of producing some good and providing compensation fails to justify A’s actions toward B.
Furthermore, Mousavirad claims that his theory has an advantage over other greater good theodicies in that, on his consequentialist theory, the good produced by the evil in this life not only need not be equal to or greater than the evil experienced, but it also need not be experienced by the person suffering the evil. He takes this as a virtue over other greater good theodicies, which he says often struggle to show that evil results in a greater good for the sufferer. This option, I suggest, is pernicious. Suppose, in our example, that A says to B that A’s actions toward B are justified because A wants to improve the opportunity for D, E, and F to improve their character by developing empathy and that B will be compensated in the end. When A posts pictures of the torture on the internet, D, E, and F will be outraged and thus choose to strengthen their moral character. However, such a scenario, even when combined with compensation, in no way justifies the actions of A, for now B is being treated only as a means to the end of goods for C, D, and E.
In short, Mousavirad’s second premise is seriously flawed. Compensation in the afterlife, no matter how great, even combined with producing some good here and now, does not show that the evils imposed are “just and fair”.
6. Confusing Compensation with Justice
Mousavirad considers an objection raised by Maitzen that there is a difference between compensation and justification. Maitzen writes, “Without such a [necessary] connection [between the suffering experienced and the compensation], the good may
compensate for the suffering but can’t
morally justify God’s permission of it. Consider an analogy to our ordinary moral practice. My paying you money after harming you may compensate for my harming you, but it doesn’t justify my harming you. Only something like the necessity of my harming you in order to prevent your harming me or an innocent third party has a chance of justifying my behavior: some necessary connection must hold between the harm and the benefit” (
Maitzen 2009, p. 110).
In reply, Mousavirad contends that this objection holds against a weak compensation theodicy but fails to affect his theodicy since the evils experienced produce some goods in this life (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 224). But this reply fails to answer the objection, for although, in his view, evils are necessary for there to be good, he does not establish that a particular evil is necessary for there to be a particular good. Although there may be a connection between specific evils and particular goods with regard to some cases of soul building (the virtue of resisting temptation occurs in the context of temptation), he does not establish any universal, necessary connection between specific evils suffered and specific compensation. Evils produce goods on their own account, but they may do so
per accidens or as a by-product. In the present, the goods that result could have been achieved in other ways than by the evil action or event, especially if they affect other persons or are natural evils. In our example, D, E, and F could have had the opportunity to become more empathetic without B having to suffer torture. Moreover, regarding the afterlife, he gives us no reason to think that there is a necessary connection between the pleasure given and the evil suffered. He writes that “God gives him so much pleasure and bounties in Heaven that he feels that these pleasures and bounties are far greater than the pain and suffering he endured in this world” (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 212). For example, in Muslim accounts, the believer’s death is rewarded in the afterlife with verdant gardens, trees bearing fruits, brocaded couches, and the pleasure of virgins (“Ar-Rahman: The Merciful”,
Qu’ran 2022, chp. 55). But there is no necessary or organic connection between the pleasure and bounty and the evil suffered; at most, it is a quantitative connection
10. Moreover, a benevolent God could provide the bliss that Mousavirad describes without the person experiencing any suffering at all. In short, if compensation or the goods to be realized are to be justified, they must be connected necessarily and organically to the wrong done to the individual.
In short, Premise 2 fails to provide an adequate account of justice and fairness and thus does not provide the needed justification for the evil suffered.
8. Animal Suffering
In addressing gratuitous evil, Mousavirad refers to William Rowe’s widely referenced case, wherein a fawn caught in a forest fire suffers terribly before it dies. He contends that although this suffering may seem pointless, some good comes from it now and that it will be compensated for in the afterlife. It is “inevitable and necessary” (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 219). Indeed, “more evils are necessary to achieve more goods”, such that more evils (and correspondingly more goods) are better than fewer evils and fewer goods.
The suffering fawn is a case of natural evil and creates some specific problems for a compensation theodicy. First, will the fawn be compensated in an afterlife? If not, a compensation theodicy might account for human suffering but would not account for animal suffering, and hence not all evil, including much natural evil (
McCullough 2018, p. 210). One could reply that non-humans do not suffer, but this would be a dubious contention that Mousavirad does not propose. If the fawn will be compensated (and later Mousavirad hints in a footnote that this may be so (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 222)), how would a fawn be compensated in an afterlife? Would it be aware that it was being compensated for the suffering it underwent? If the fawn is unaware that it is being compensated for its suffering, in what sense would compensating for the fawn terrible suffering be a case of justice and fairness? Is not awareness of compensation a necessary condition for justice to be served for an individual? When a family is compensated for a wrongful death in an airplane crash, it is the family and not the victim that gets compensation for the loss. In short, a compensation theodicy is problematic when it addresses nonhuman suffering or natural evil.
9. Creating More Horrendous Evils
Even more problematic is Mousavirad’s contention that God not only is morally permitted to bring about horrendous evil, but God also ought to do so since “the more horrendous the evil, the more good will be produced (even if this evil does not lead to the greater good as a whole)” (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 220). He says that “the theory of compensation works only when severe and horrendous evils are unavoidable, but I believe that there is this inevitability and necessity” (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 219). For one thing, Mousavirad contends that supposing there are two worlds, W1 where 60% evil produces 40% good and W2 where 30% evil produces 20% good, God should bring about W1 because it results in more good. We are again presented with a pernicious account of justice when he says that we should do a greater quantity and quality of horrendous evil so that more good will result. Moreover, on his theodicy, the good need not equal or surpass the evil; all that is necessary is
some good result. But then the amount or intensity of the horrendous evil has no connection with the quantity and quality of the good that results. So long as some good results and the sufferers are compensated, evil is justified. But if all that is necessary is that
some good result, horrendous evil is likely unjustified, for less evil might do just as well to create some good.
However, not only would this view be a miscarriage of justice by justifying the various horrendous genocides of the last centuries on the grounds that they (allegedly) produced more good and that the victims will be compensated in Paradise, but it would imply that there should have been even more of these horrendous evils and their kin, that an increase would be just and fair. Doing more and worse evil so that (some) good results for the victims or maybe only for others is morally unacceptable. It would mean, for example, that A would be justified in making things worse for B so that B (or someone else) has the opportunity to develop a bit more patience, fortitude, and courage. Bringing about more non-equivalent good does not justify creating more evil.
10. Treating People as Means Only and Not as Ends
Finally, as we have already noted, Mousavirad’s theory is objectionable in that it treats people only as means and not as ends who are intrinsically valuable in themselves. Consider Mousavirad’s example where “God creates a disabled infant for a parent to be tested and spiritually perfected through their free will” (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 221). Mousavirad justifies this on the grounds that “it is not cruel to the infant, since God will compensate all of its hardships and sufferings” (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 221). This follows from his two points regarding justification: for justification, so long as evil will be compensated, just some good in this life is enough, and this good need not be for the individual sufferer (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 211). But in this instance, the infant is treated solely as a means for the good of the parent. Surely, the parents could develop some good without the infant being disabled, for example, by being given the privilege of raising a child with all its usual challenges.
In fact, inflicting unwilling and underserved suffering on one person to benefit another violates the central Kantian principle that one should never treat people merely as means but also as intrinsically valuable ends in themselves. Mousavirad does not reference Kant, but it would seem that even with reference to Kant aside, this moral principle should play a significant role regarding how we morally should treat people. Mousavirad indirectly affirms this when he argues that God must compensate in the afterlife the very individuals who have suffered and not others (
Mousavirad 2022, p. 212). Indeed, if treating people merely as means were acceptable, we would not even have to construct a theodicy to establish or protect God’s goodness. Any (mis)treatment of humans brought about or allowed by God would not have to be justified at all, for we could treat people however we wanted so long as some good (and not necessarily superseding good) resulted and they eventually got rewarded.