3.1. Tariq Ramadan: A Liberal Laïcité for All
Let us begin with Tariq Ramadan, who was the most prolific Islamic voice on
laïcité in the recent decades. Ramadan, a Swiss Muslim intellectual of Egyptian origin, was born in Geneva in 1962. His father, Said Ramadan (d. 1995), was the leader of the Muslim Brotherhood in Europe, and his grandfather, Ḥasan al-Bannā (d. 1949), is the founder of the Muslim Brotherhood in Egypt, in 1928. Ramadan benefited from a double education. On the one hand, he received an Islamic education at the Islamic Centre of Geneva, which is a religious and political centre of the Muslim Brotherhood, run by his family, becoming exposed to Islamism and the ideology of the Muslim Brotherhood. Ramadan also briefly pursued a traditional curriculum of Islamic knowledge at al-Azhar University in Egypt between 1992 and 1994. On the other hand, Ramadan studied philosophy and French literature in Switzerland, obtaining a PhD in Arabic and Islamic studies at the University of Geneva.
18 Between the mid-1990s and 2017, T. Ramadan was a key figure in French Islam, delivering hundreds of lectures and preaches, founding a number of associations and institutes and connecting influential networks of Islamic action and ideas; several allegations of rape and sexual violation in 2017 discredited him within Muslim communities, especially since 2020, when he was charged with rape. Ramadan published over 25 books in French, elaborating his views on
laïcité in four books
: Les musulmans dans la laïcité: responsabilités et droits des musulmans dans les sociétés occidentales (1994),
Mon intime conviction (2009),
Au péril des idées (2015) and
L’urgence et l’essentiel (2017).
As early as 1994, Tariq Ramadan published
Les musulmans dans la laïcité, the most influential Islamic book on
laïcité in France to date. Therein, Ramadan put forward the idea that, in the Muslim tradition, a harmony exists between the power of the State and the authority of religion as well as between religion and science. However, the domains of politics, science and religion remained autonomous and evolved in a different and more harmonious history in Islam compared to Christian Europe. Such differences in the relation between religion and public life can be seen in the daily practice of Islam (collective prayers, almsgiving, pilgrimage, etc.), which implies expressing religion in the public space (
Ramadan [1994] 1998, pp. 77–126). Ramadan infers from this historical outline the right for Muslims to be treated as communities with a different history than that Europeans had with the Church.
In
Les musulmans dans la laïcité, Ramadan maintains that “the neutrality of the secular space is not in danger if we accept differences and if we adopt an indifferent attitude towards religions in the public space. There could be a danger if we encourage exclusions or compartmentalisation because in the long run it produces exactly the opposite of the desired effect.” (
Ramadan [1994] 1998, p. 208). Ramadan adds that the current application of
laïcité, whether ill-intentioned or well-intentioned, “casts anathema in the name of neutrality and declares a war that creates its own trenches” (
Ramadan [1994] 1998, p. 208). That is,
laïcité wages a societal war against Muslims, pushing them to isolate and reject French society. Ramadan calls for an open
laïcité which revises its rigid separation between religion and public space to include the way Muslims live differently in the nexus between private and public spaces, as they express these differences in their claims about wearing the headscarf, for instance, while respecting the spirit of
laïcité, which is open to affirmed identities and mutual recognition (
Ramadan [1994] 1998, pp. 213–17).
Thus, Ramadan centres his argument on the right to difference and the obligation of the French state to equalise between religions. Islam’s presumable difference from other religions (Christianity, in particular) should make the French state reconsider how it perceives religion and public space so that Muslims are treated as they are, since their religious identity involves also public expressions; failing to do so means punishing them for their difference and discriminating against them. To equalise between religions, the French state ought to seek a way of positively co-existing with Muslims practicing their religion in the public space, thus reshaping the strict neutrality in religious public expression.
In his
Mon intime conviction (2009), Ramadan shifts the focus of his argument and claims that “nothing in
laïcité was opposed to a free and autonomous practice of Islam” (
Ramadan 2009, p. 162). He advocates the strict application of the French law on secularism (1905), “in its letter and spirit, in an egalitarian way for all citizens, Muslims or not” (
Ramadan 2009, p. 162). He then distinguishes between the 1905 law on separation of the state and church, and the current
laïcité, which is in his view a sectarian and fundamentalist form of secularism, the purpose of which is the rejection (and the hope of disappearance) of religion (
Ramadan 2009, p. 162). Ramadan believes that such secularism is dogmatic, adopted by militant atheism, and that this ideology “hides something”, namely its will to colonise religions (
Ramadan 2009, p. 162).
Six years later, Ramadan debated
laïcité with the French prominent sociologist and philosopher Edgar Morin in their book
Au péril des idées (2015). Ramadan made a distinction between
laïcité (
separation of state and church) and
laïcisme (the ideology of secularisation of society). Ramadan embraces
laïcité as a product of Renaissance, humanism and separation of powers, which aims at “the institutionalization of religious diversity through the autonomy and neutrality of the state to protect a public space based on the acceptance of diversity and the universal so that religion would not have the last word on politics, and the diversity of beliefs, thus preserving the freedom to think and/or believe” (
Ramadan and Morin 2015, p. 17). Conversely, Ramadan maintains that
laïcisme has transformed
laïcité into “a full-scale attack on religion and its presence in society, a means to remove the visibility of religion from public life” (
Ramadan and Morin 2015, p. 17).
In
Au péril des idées, Ramadan further develops the view that
laïcité is a historical process of separation of Church and State against “the ideology that uses the means of secularism to combat religion” (
Ramadan and Morin 2015, p. 17). While state secularism preserves diversity in the public space, militant secularism closes this space and disqualifies religious thought. This is all the more the case, Ramadan asserts, when militant secularism targets Muslims and accuses their visibility in public life of calling into question the neutrality of the public space (
Ramadan and Morin 2015, p. 17). Thus, Muslims are taken as troublemakers whose presence brings back the religious when it was thought to have disappeared from the public space (
Ramadan and Morin 2015, p. 18).
Ramadan makes another distinction between secular thought and secularist ideology. By secular thought, he means “the founding principle of separation of powers without wanting to make religion disappear, defending diversity and neutrality of space” (
Ramadan and Morin 2015, p. 18). Conversely, secularist ideology is “militant anti-religious thought which established itself as a new religion excluding all others, with its dogmas, its principles, its rituals and even its excommunications” (
Ramadan and Morin 2015, p. 18). Behind secularist ideology, Ramadan sees militant atheism, the purpose of which is to end the era of religion and its visibility (
Ramadan and Morin 2015, p. 18). Accordingly, Muslims are but challenges to this secularist ideology through their claims about the headscarf, the mosques, the minarets, the oriental “Muslim” names, etc. (
Ramadan and Morin 2015, p. 18). It is not Muslims’ fault, Ramadan sustains, that they preserve religious visible signs and that this visibility refuses to disappear or to be annihilated for the source of the problem is neither Islam, nor Muslims, nor even religions, “but a misunderstanding of secularism” (
Ramadan and Morin 2015, p. 19).
Ramadan reiterated in
Au péril des idées what he uttered in his
Mon intime conviction, namely that “Muslims have no problem with the application of secularism (as strict separation of state and religion) in its letter and in its spirit, completely and equally but have a problem with its current application as a kind of entrenched fort, a machine for exclusion” (
Ramadan and Morin 2015, pp. 20–21). This is, however, a change from his initial position, which was to criticise the strict separation of state and religion, calling rather to an open secularism, more flexible with regard to expressing religion in the public space. In both cases, his demand for equality and inclusion of Muslims in French society did not change.
For Ramadan, the only way for Muslims and non-Muslims to live together in France today is “to apply secularism fully, with a view to equality, justice and openness” (
Ramadan and Morin 2015, p. 183). In his view, what is at work in France is not the classical-liberal
laïcité of the early twentieth century, which is positive, open and respectful of diversity but a narrow, restrictive, cowering, fearful, dogmatic and non-negotiable way of thinking about secularism, especially in public institutions of education (
Ramadan and Morin 2015, p. 183). Consequently, the new
laïcité has “adopted a restrictive definition of neutrality and, more seriously, of the notion of freedom of conscience to counter the new visibility of Islam” (
Ramadan and Morin 2015, p. 183).
In 2017, Ramadan published
L’urgence et l’essentiel, a second debate that opposed him to Edgar Morin. In this book, Ramadan calls to adopt “a less ideological interpretation of secularism against religion and more egalitarian and normative towards religions, all religions” (
Ramadan and Morin 2017, p. 151). French fundamentalist secularists, Ramadan continues, “are perverting secularism, using it as a weapon against religions and above all as a weapon to stigmatize Islam” (
Ramadan and Morin 2017, p. 151). Therefore, the optimal scenario for Muslims would be that the French state applies secularism for everyone and without discrimination (
Ramadan and Morin 2017, p. 151). The problem, then, lies in the dogmatic and fundamentalist readings of secularism and their anti-Islamic agenda as they strive to eliminate any religious visibility of Muslims in the public space. Ramadan condemned the French state because it failed to “apply
laïcité, equally to all religions, making it an instrument that disparages Islam as if Islam had an intrinsic problem with secularism” (
Ramadan and Morin 2017, p. 150).
It is hard to accept the premise that Ramadan wants to ensure respect for secularism (
Ramadan and Morin 2017, p. 171). His view is rather instrumentalist and should be understood as an Islamic quest for autonomy within French society equally to other religions. His criticism of the French
laïcité as applied today stems from what he perceives to be inequality and discrimination against Islam, whose visibility challenges the French state. It is also difficult to follow his call for the application of the classical-liberal
laïcité of early twentieth century. Secularisation has transformed French society in the last hundred years and changed in the process; there is no way to turn back the wheel of time.
In general, Ramadan evolved from demanding an open laïcité, which includes Muslims with their different history of relations between religion and politics, to emphasise the cleavage between a liberal and militant laïcité. Beginning with his book Mon intime conviction (2009), his position consists of uttering a double critique of the current laïcité as applied by the French state: 1. It is anti-religious rather than neutral, aiming at eliminating any expression of religion in the public space contrary to the classical doctrine of secularism of separating state and religion as stipulated in the 1905 law. 2. It discriminates against Muslims because it targets them specifically through a series of new laws on religious signs in schools and the public space, hindering their rights to express their religious identity and to practice their religion. Thus, according to his account, Muslims are victims of a fundamentalist laïcité, while the French state fails to protect their rights as citizens.
A missing link in Ramadan’s argument is the responsibility of Muslims to acclimatise to laïcité as other religions did in recent times. In a public space shared by all citizens of various faiths, it is also an obligation for every religion, independently from the demands made by militant secularists or the French state policies, to respect other religions, philosophies and opinions in the public space.
3.2. Ghaleb Bencheikh: Laïcité, Freedom and Equal Treatment
Ghaleb Bencheikh is a Franco-Algerian Islamologist and a widely recognised reformist and Sufi intellectual and leader. El Hocine was born in 1960 in Jeddah (Saudi Arabia); he is the son of Sheikh Abbas Bencheikh el Hocine, rector of the Grand Mosque of Paris from 1982 to 1989. He holds a doctorate in physics, graduated from the University of Paris 6 in 1990 and has also studied philosophy at the University of Paris 1. He is the author of numerous books, including
Petit manuel pour un islam à la mesure des hommes (
Bencheikh 2018),
Le Coran expliqué pubpished in 2018,
Juifs, chrétiens et musulmans:
«Ne nous faites pas dire n’importe quoi!» (with Philippe Haddad and Jacques Arnould), published in 2008,
Lettre ouverte aux islamistes (with Antoine Sfeir published in the same year and
La laïcité au regard du Coran published in 2005. Bencheikh developed his ideas on
laïcité in two books:
La laïcité au regard du Coran (
Bencheikh 2005) and
Petit manuel pour un islam à la mesure des hommes published in 2018. Moreover, he produced and hosted the programme
Questions d’islam on the radio station France Culture and presented the programme
Islam on France TV on Sunday mornings from 2000 to 2019. He is a member of the
Conseil des sages de laïcité as well as a guest speaker at colloquia and conferences in France and abroad, often on the subject of secularism as it relates to the problems of Muslims today. He is also President of the World Conference of Religions for Peace–France. On 13 December 2018, he was elected President of the
Fondation de l’Islam de France, where he succeeds Jean-Pierre Chevènement. The
Fondation de l’Islam de France is one of the leading state organisations entrusted by the French state to shape Islam in France.
19In
La laïcité au regard du Coran, Bencheikh blames Islamism for spreading the “false idea” that Islam is religion and state (
Bencheikh 2005, pp. 35–38), arguing that the separation of worldly and spiritual orders has been validated in Islamic political history since the beginning of Islam; the Koran itself being the basis of secular neutrality as it does not preach any political doctrine (
Bencheikh 2005, p. 57) was the condition for the emergence of a double authority: the spiritual authority of the Prophet and the worldly authority of the rulers (
Bencheikh 2005, p. 60). This premise is quite different from Ramadan’s, who although distinguishes political power from religious authority argues for an active role of religion in the public space and does not see Islam as only a spirituality. Bencheikh goes further and negates any “Islamic legislation” since all legislation is positive and human crafted by jurists out of their interpretation of religious texts and adaptation to various historical contexts (
Bencheikh 2005, pp. 75–83). Bencheikh also calls Muslims to reject the punishment of apostasy and to embrace religious freedom as principle (
Bencheikh 2005, pp. 85–109). Conversely, Bencheikh considers
laïcité as a facilitator of co-existence in pluralist societies
, criticising the evolution of
laïcité into a doctrine that claims to replace or compete with religions (
Bencheikh 2005, p. 117). For him, as long as
laïcité ensures that political power is neutral and does not interfere in religious affairs and religious affairs do not intervene in politics, Islam and
laïcité can be compatible (
Bencheikh 2005, p. 117). Eventually, Muslims in France should be given time to adapt to
laïcité the same way the Catholic Church took time to become used to it (
Bencheikh 2005, p. 118).
Bencheikh’s
Petit manuel pour un islam à la mesure des hommes starts with a similar premise to that uttered in
La laïcité au regard du Coran (2005): that the crisis of modern Islam is caused by the intermingling of religion and politics. That is why secularism is vital. However, he seems more balanced between his critique of Muslims and of the French
laïcité in his later book than in his earlier one. In
Petit manuel pour un islam à la mesure des hommes, Bencheikh understands
laïcité as the common framework of any reference to a transcendence that allows all citizens, as members of the City, to freely choose their metaphysical orientations (
Bencheikh 2018, p. 103). Thus,
laïcité ensures the organisation of the city is a neutral and exclusively human enterprise. Bencheikh also adopts a concept of secularism as a legal principle without ideological thickness or doctrinal density, borrowing from Aristide Briand the following formula: “secularism is a law that guarantees the free exercise of faith as long as faith does not claim to dictate the law” (
Bencheikh 2018, p. 96). He insists a great deal on the neutral character of secularism as a condition for individual freedom of expression, whether from an ethical, religious or convictional point of view, to allow the free exercise of worship in compliance with the legislation in force and guaranteeing the fact of believing or not believing but, above all, of being able to change belief (
Bencheikh 2018, p. 97). However, similarly to Ramadan, Bencheikh is wary of secularism of combat and of the total desacralisation of human life (
Bencheikh 2018, p. 100).
For Bencheikh, there is no reason to approach
laïcité as a problem of incompatibility or compatibility between Islam and secularism since secularism is a principle of neutrality; the latter is always compatible with Islam for it is a legal principle that only needs to be applied (
Bencheikh 2018, p. 42). Previously, Bencheikh argued for the compatibility between Islam and secularism from the history of Islam and from across the various modern experiences of Muslims. In his
Petit manuel pour un islam à la mesure des hommes, he not only denies the relevance of the problem of compatibility/incompatibility between Islam and secularism but also considers secularism to be the ideal horizon for all Muslim societies (
Bencheikh 2018, p. 109). Bencheikh deems it unnecessary to justify secularism in Islam theologically (which is logical after all). Yet, he does not hesitate to announce that a form of secularism existed in Islam as early as the seventh century when the Umayyad Empire was born as a political power distinct from religious authority (
Bencheikh 2018, p. 75). Bencheikh still believes that the lines between the temporal and the sacred in Islam are quite clear, following Olivier Carré’s thesis in
L’Islam laïque: ou le retour à la grande tradition, that Islam was secular most of the time, which many Islamologists would probably argue against (
Carré 1993, p. 62).
20 One of the arguments that could undermine this thesis is that, even if religious and political elites were distinct most of the time, Islamic empires applied Islamic law as state law and hired religious authorities as judges and governors, and therefore, it cannot be said that the temporal was separate from the sacred.
Bencheikh seems to be torn between the ideal and the reality of
laïcité, with the ideal being his belief in secularism as a neutral space and citizenship as an end in itself, which is compatible with a spiritual Islam. As he puts it, “the ideal of
laïcité is that of equality between all citizens, freedom, particularly of conscience, and above all the guarantee of the exercise of religion” (
Bencheikh 2018, p. 103). As for the reality of
laïcité, it is that of the refusal of many Muslims to accept secularism, which paradoxically feeds the followers of militant secularism. It is too simplistic to think that secularism is rejected in Muslim communities in France and in Muslim societies only because of Islamic fundamentalism and political demagogy, as Bencheikh asserts (
Bencheikh 2018, p. 109). The political and religious history of Muslim societies (including the relationship between elites and authority figures) diverges from the political and religious history of France and European societies; this presupposes distinct societal demands on the relationship between religion and politics.
In contrast to his earlier thoughts on
laïcité (
Bencheikh 2005) in which the focus was on the responsibility of Muslims to adhere to philosophical modernity, recently, (
Bencheikh 2018) Bencheikh moved to clearly strike a balance between the difficulty of
laïcité to include Muslims and the uneasiness of the latter to embrace
laïcité because of the Islamist influence. Bencheikh underlines
laïcité as freedom, which Ramadan does not do although both agree to consider it as a framework of neutrality and equality between citizens and religions. Ramadan and Bencheikh differ only in the attitude they require from Muslims; while Ramadan asks them to proudly participate as Muslims in the French society, without adhering to secular or liberal thought, Bencheikh is critical of some of Muslim traditional beliefs and practices and requires Muslims to embrace secular and liberal thinking in order to live in a secular society. Both Ramadan and Bencheikh generally take a position in favour of an equalising liberal
laïcité that is neutral and inclusive of Muslims rather than anti-religious and anti-Islamic. In contrast to Ramadan who is embedded with the idea of an autonomous Muslim society (under the influence of the Muslim Brotherhood), even in France, Bencheikh pushes for a French society in which Muslim spirituality is but a dimension of citizenship.
3.3. Latifa Ibn Ziaten: Laïcité and the Right to Difference and Equality
Latifa Ibn Ziaten is a French-Moroccan activist, born in 1960 in Tétouan in northern Morocco; she has lived in France since 1977. Ibn Ziaten is the mother of Imad Ibn Ziaten, the first soldier assassinated in Toulouse by the terrorist Mohammed Merah in 2012. That same year, she founded the Imad Association for Youth and Peace, campaigning against Islamic radicalisation through educational and solidarity projects that try to decompartmentalise part of the isolated Muslim youth which refuses to integrate in the French society. Ibn Ziaten has published three books:
Mort pour la France in 2013,
Dis-nous Latifa, c’est quoi la tolérance? in 2016 and
Laïcité et islam: mission possible? (together with R. Adnani and J. L. Bianco).
21Latifa Ibn Ziaten perceives secularism as an instrument capable of guaranteeing the freedom of beliefs and opinions as well as the difference of identities and the equality of citizens before the law (
Ibn Ziaten et al. 2019, p. 13). She maintains that each country has its own history and reason for endorsing secularism in its constitution or not (
Ibn Ziaten et al. 2019, p. 44). She refuses to recognise the Christian religion as a value in the European Constitution; she does not accept either the idea of a privileged relationship between the French Republic and the Catholic religion and demands cultural and spiritual diversity as well as the neutrality of the State in order to ensure freedom and equal treatment to different religions (
Ibn Ziaten et al. 2019, p. 58). Additionally, Ibn Ziaten believes that secularism can secure the proper coexistence of diversity and pluralism in France (
Ibn Ziaten et al. 2019, p. 75).
In her view, Muslim youth in France does not understand the definition of secularism and thinks that it only concerns a part of the French population (
Ibn Ziaten et al. 2019, p. 16). According to Ibn Ziaten, Muslim youth believes that the French state does not take Islam into account and so it feels rejected, associating
laïcité with dismissal of Muslims (
Ibn Ziaten et al. 2019, p. 16). Ibn Ziaten asserts that this perspective is wrong since “secularism is for everyone, including for Muslims and the French Republic should consider individuals as citizens above all, regardless of their religious or convictions, and this is what makes it possible to live in France together on an equal footing” (
Ibn Ziaten et al. 2019, p. 36). As she puts it, “undermining secularism in any political process would alter our common good” (
Ibn Ziaten et al. 2019, p. 16). She adds that “the State must remain religiously neutral to prevent discrimination. It is important, especially since the terrorist attacks that have affected the French people, and sometimes divided them; it is important to find solutions that unite them and allow them to live together, in peace, and that the motto
Liberté, Égalité, Fraternité be a true call to a fairer nation” (
Ibn Ziaten et al. 2019, p. 38).
Ibn Ziaten emphasises diversity and equality as the basis of building a tolerant French society. Thus, she asserts that “equality goes through this spirit of balance despite the differences. France, from its secular spirit, still has a long way to go to achieve tolerance. Harmony within this nation requires an effort to accept our differences” (
Ibn Ziaten et al. 2019, p. 18). Consequently, the solution for her is not to ban the expression of Islam in the public space but to allow all religions the expression of their faiths in dress, food, etc. (
Ibn Ziaten et al. 2019, p. 18). This is the way, according to her, to achieve recognition of differences, and in this manner, “everyone would gain recognition through their differences, without locking themselves into a community spirit or feeling frustrated that their needs cannot be met” (
Ibn Ziaten et al. 2019, p. 18).
In a similar manner to Ramadan, Ibn Ziaten infers from Muslim cultural difference the right to express religiosity in the public space and considers the rejection of the Muslim exception in this regard as exclusion. Her discourse differs from Ramadan and Bencheikh in that it is rights-based and does not claim any theological or historical justification about Islam. She is worried about laïcité as a tool of exclusion if used to discount Muslims from showing their religious identity in the public space. In her perspective, Muslims, as a social group, ought to have the right to be equally treated and granted the right to live as Muslims in French society. Equality for her means to be included in the social fabric as citizens/Muslims; laïcité is the process which makes that possible through neutrality (and so Muslim citizens are accepted as they are). Her argument is also significantly different from those made by Ramadan and Bencheikh in that she does not criticise militant secularists or Islamists. She still believes in the French State as an institution capable of securing neutrality and equality for Muslims.
In sum, whereas Ramadan is concerned with the application of a strict neutrality of the secular state in respect to religious affairs in line with a classical liberal sense of laïcité and Bencheikh tends to highlight the role of the secular state as guarantee of religious freedom, Ibn Ziaten underlines diversity and the right of Muslims to difference in a plural French society, which then justify Muslim claims about expressing religion in the public space. However, the three Muslim leaders discussed here share a key discursive feature, namely that they stress the element of equality. Ramadan demands a liberal laïcité to protect Muslims from discrimination in the public space. Bencheikh believes laïcité allows Muslims to live their religion equally to all other citizens. Finally, Ibn Ziaten perceives laïcité as a recognition mechanism of differences granted to all, including to Muslims.