Religion and International Relations Theory: The Case of “New” Historiography of Human Rights
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The “New” Historiography of Human Rights
Another important illustration of this innovative concept is the famous phrase proclaiming inalienable rights in the U.S. Declaration of Independence: “We hold these truths to be self-evident [emphasis added], that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness” (U.S. 1776). Having homed-in on this idea, Hunt raises a difficult question about the “paradox” of self-evidence. If these truths or rights are self-evident, why have they only been recognized in certain times and places. This dilemma grows in scale with the assertion that human rights have three criteria: they must be equal, natural, and universal (Hunt 2007a, p. 20). The risk for Hunt is that we may have to become rights pragmatists. Hunt’s solution revolves around the eighteenth-century concept of “sympathy” in the context of increasing appreciation of personal autonomy. She posits that rights became universal because sympathy had acquired a nearly universal place or consensus in society. Specifically, through “reading accounts of torture or epistolary novels” ordinary people developed greater levels of sympathy (Hunt 2007a, p. 33). Ultimately, “an emotional appeal…strik[ing] a chord in each person” undergirds this argument for the self-evidence of sympathy in the eighteenth century (Hunt 2007a, p. 26).The use of this term is so familiar, that there is almost no one who would not be convinced inside himself that the thing is obviously known to him. This interior feeling is common both to the philosopher and to the man who has not reflected at all.
3. New Historiography of Human Rights and International Relations Theory
3.1. IRT Constructivism and New Historiography of Human Rights
3.2. IRT Liberalism and New Historiography of Human Rights
4. IRT Liberalism Weakens New Historiography’s Analysis of Religion
4.1. New Historiography Largely Omits the 19th Century
He proceeds to apply this notion of the subject perceiving or experiencing other subjects to the level of a community. The result is a subject experiencing another subject (or “Other”), not merely as a subject, but also in relation to yet additional subjects. This multi-relational experiencing of Others is an “open plurality” of people “as subjects of possible intercommunion” or a “community of monads” (Husserl 1999, pp. 157–58). Thus, personalism’s roots have a strong relational and communal bent.If, with my understanding of someone else, I penetrate more deeply into him, into his horizon of ownness, I shall soon run into the fact that, just as his animate bodily organism lies in my field of perception, so my animate organism lies in his field of perception and that, in general, he experiences me forthwith as an Other for him, just as I experience him as my Other.
Reality is personal and is grounded in a personal and uncaused entity. Or, “personality is the key to reality” was Brightman’s succinct summary of the personalist philosophy of Bowne and Knudson (Brightman 1943, p. 42).Our choice lies between an incoherent purposeless accident, demanding an infinite regress, and therefore unknowable, or an inaccessible pantheistic cause wherein matter is wholly phenomenal; or we may choose a self-creative personality as the ground of being sustaining itself according to general uniformities discoverable in limited and partial ways within ourselves.
4.2. New Historiography Neglects the Theology and Spirituality of Christian Personalism
Thus, as early as 1920, a Christian personalist had generated a defense of universal human rights in explicitly personalist language. Moreover, Flewelling grounded his argument for inviolable human rights in theological and spiritual terms.Individualism with its exaltation of individual preferment at the expense of the many, with its ethical doctrine that whatever is useful in furthering its culture is morally right, with its scorn of the weak and helpless as beyond the pale of its care and responsibility, with its disregard and skepticism toward all spiritual values, is lined up in a great world conflict against all who believe in the inviolable human rights [emphasis added] of the least and feeblest in the social structure.
4.3. The Modernist Schema of New Historiography
Her statement takes seriously the valid objection by new school historians that a particular religious approach (e.g., Christian personalism) cannot be universally acceptable as a theory or grounding of human rights, even if that specific religious formulation assigns human rights to all people (e.g., Flewelling and Maritain). Yet, Hurd also sees the inconsistency in modernist or new school historiographic objections to religious particularity while making secularity, itself a particular view of the world, a criterion for universality.Claims to universality grounded either in the claim to have overcome religio-cultural particularities altogether, as in laicism, or to have located the key to democratic moral and political order in a particular religio-cultural heritage, as in Judeo-Christian secularism, are problematic.
5. Implications for Religion and International Relations Theory
5.1. Implications for IRT Realism
5.2. Implications for IRT Liberalism
5.3. Implications for IRT Constructivism
6. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Barnett, Michael. 2011. Another Great Awakening: International Relations Theory and Religion. In Religion and International Relations Theory. Edited by Jack L. Snyder. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 91–114. [Google Scholar]
- Bowne, Borden P. 2017. Personalism. Warsaw: Andesite Press. [Google Scholar]
- Brightman, Edgar S. 1943. Personality as a Metaphysical Principle. In Personalism in Theology: A Symposium in Honor of Albert Cornelius Knudson. Edited by Edgar S. Brightman. Boston: Boston University Press, pp. 40–63. [Google Scholar]
- De Tavernier, Johan. 2009. The Historical Roots of Personalism: From Renouvier’s Le Personnalisme, Mounier’s Manifeste au service du personnalisme and Maritain’s Humanisme intégral to Janssens’ Personne et Société. Ethical Perspectives 16: 361–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- di Giovanni, George, and Paolo Livieri. 2020. Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. [Google Scholar]
- Dirksen, Kevin M., and Paul Schotsmans. 2012. The historical roots of personalism: Borden Parker Browne and the Boston tradition on personal identity and the moral life. Bijdragen 73: 388–403. [Google Scholar]
- Donnelly, Jack. 2000. Realism and International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dorrien, Gary J. 2003. The Making of American Liberal Theology: Idealism, Realism, and Modernity, 1900–1950. Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press. [Google Scholar]
- Doyle, Michael W. 1986. Liberalism and World Politics. American Political Science Review 80: 1151–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dunne, Tim, and Marianne Hanson. 2009. Human Rights in International Relations. In Human Rights: Politics and Practice. Edited by Michael E. Goodhart. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Duranti, Marco. 2012. The Holocaust, the legacy of 1789 and the birth of international human rights law: Revisiting the foundation myth. Journal of Genocide Research 14: 159–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Duranti, Marco. 2017. The Conservative Human Rights Revolution: European Identity, Transnational Politics, and the Origins of the European Convention. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Flewelling, Ralph T. 1920. Bergson and Personal Realism. Nashville: The Abingdon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Forsythe, David P. 2017. Human Rights in International Relations, 4th ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Glendon, Mary Ann. 2002. A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 1st ed. New York: Random House. [Google Scholar]
- Haynes, Jeffrey. 2021. Religion and International Relations: What Do We Know and How Do We Know It? Religions 12: 328. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Henkin, Louis. 2000. Human Rights: Ideology and Aspiration, Reality and Prospect. In Realizing Human Rights. Edited by Samantha Power and Graham Allison. New York: St. Martins Press, pp. 3–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hoffmann, Stefan-Ludwig. 2016. Human Rights and History. Past & Present 232: 279–310. [Google Scholar]
- Hunt, Lynn. 2007a. Inventing Human Rights: A History, 1st ed. New York: W.W. Norton & Co. [Google Scholar]
- Hunt, Lynn. 2007b. The Paradoxical Origins of Human Rights. In Human Rights and Revolutions, 2nd ed. Edited by Jeffrey N. Wasserstrom, Lynn Hunt, Greg Grandin and Marilyn B. Young. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, pp. 3–20. [Google Scholar]
- Hurd, Elizabeth S. 2011. Secularism and International Relations Theory. In Religion and International Relations Theory. Edited by Jack L. Snyder. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, Edmund. 1999. The Essential Husserl: Basic Writings in Transcendental Phenomenology, Illustrated, ed. Edited by Donn Welton. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, Edmund, and Michael Dummett. 2001. Logical Investigations. Edited by Dermot Moran. Translated by J. N. Findlay. London: Routledge, Volume 1. [Google Scholar]
- Jackson, Robert H. 1946. The Case against The Nazi War Criminals: Opening Statement for the United States of America, 1st ed. New York: A.A. Knopf. [Google Scholar]
- Jacobi, Friedrich H. 1995a. Concerning the Doctrine of Spinoza. In The Main Philosophical Writings and the Novel Allwill. Edited by George di Giovanni. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jacobi, Friedrich H. 1995b. David Hume on Faith or Idealism and Realism. In The Main Philosophical Writings and the Novel Allwill. Edited by George di Giovanni. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press. [Google Scholar]
- James, Patrick, ed. 2011. Religion, Identity, and Global Governance: Ideas, Evidence, and Practice, Illustrated ed. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, Scholarly Publishing Division. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel. 2004. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics: That Will Be Able to Come Forward as Science: With Selections from the Critique of Pure Reason, Revised ed. Translated by Gary Hatfield. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Keohane, Robert O. 2005. After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy, Revised ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Keys, Barbara J. 2014. Reclaiming American Virtue: The Human Rights Revolution of The 1970s. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kohák, E. 1997. Personalism: Towards a Philosophical Delineation. The Personalist Forum 13: 3–11. [Google Scholar]
- Lauren, Paul G. 2011. The Evolution of International Human Rights: Visions Seen, 3rd ed. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lotze, Hermann, and George T. Ladd. 1887. Outlines of the Philosophy of Religion. London: R. D. Dickinson. [Google Scholar]
- Lotze, Hermann, Elizabeth Hamilton, and Emily E. C. Jones. 1885. Microcosmus: An Essay Concerning Man and His Relation to the World. Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark. [Google Scholar]
- Maritain, Jacques. 1952. The Range of Reason. New York: Scribner. [Google Scholar]
- Milbank, Jacques. 2020. The Last Christian Settlement: A Defense and Critique, in Debate with Samuel Moyn. In Christianity and Human Rights Reconsidered. Edited by Sarah Shortall and Daniel Steinmetz-Jenkins. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mounier, Emmanuel. 1955. The Spoil of the Violent, First British ed. West Nyack: Cross Currents. [Google Scholar]
- Mounier, Emmanuel. 1989. Personalism. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. [Google Scholar]
- Moyn, Samuel. 2010. The Last Utopia: Human Rights in History. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Moyn, Samuel. 2014. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights of 1948 in the History of Cosmopolitanism. Critical Inquiry 40: 365–84. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moyn, Samuel. 2015. Christian Human Rights. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. [Google Scholar]
- Moyn, Samuel. 2020. Preface. In Christianity and Human Rights Reconsidered. Edited by Sarah Shortall and Daniel Steinmetz-Jenkins. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1941. The Christian faith and the world crisis. Christianity and Crisis 1: 4–6. [Google Scholar]
- Nuremberg Charter. 1945. Available online: https://www.un.org/en/genocideprevention/documents/atrocity-crimes/Doc.2_Charter%20of%20IMT%201945.pdf (accessed on 23 December 2021).
- Renaud, Terrence. 2017. Human Rights as Radical Anthropology: Protestant Theology and Ecumenism in the Transwar Era. The Historical Journal 60: 493–518. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schmiesing, Kevin. 2000. A History of Personalism. Available online: https://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=1851661 (accessed on 23 December 2021).
- Shortall, Sarah, and Daniel Steinmetz-Jenkins, eds. 2020. Christianity and Human Rights Reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Snyder, Jack. 2009. One World, Rival Theories. Foreign Policy 145: 52. [Google Scholar]
- Snyder, Jack L., ed. 2011. Religion and International Relations Theory. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sullivan, David. 2018. Hermann Lotze. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. [Google Scholar]
- Waltz, Kenneth N. 1979. Theory of International Politics. Reading: Addison-Wesley Pub. Co. [Google Scholar]
- Waltz, Kenneth N. 2008. Realism and International Politics. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Waltz, Kenneth N. 2010. Theory of International Politics. Long Grove: Waveland Press. First published in 1979. [Google Scholar]
- Waltz, Kenneth, and Stephen M. Walt. 2018. Man, the State, and War: A Theoretical Analysis, Anniversary ed. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wendt, Alexander. 1999. Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Zubovich, Gene. 2020. William Ernest Hocking and the Liberal Protestant Origins of Human Rights. In Christianity and Human Rights Reconsidered. Edited by Sarah Shortall and Daniel Steinmetz-Jenkins. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 139–57. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Williams, A.L. Religion and International Relations Theory: The Case of “New” Historiography of Human Rights. Religions 2022, 13, 39. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13010039
Williams AL. Religion and International Relations Theory: The Case of “New” Historiography of Human Rights. Religions. 2022; 13(1):39. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13010039
Chicago/Turabian StyleWilliams, Andrew Lloyd. 2022. "Religion and International Relations Theory: The Case of “New” Historiography of Human Rights" Religions 13, no. 1: 39. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13010039
APA StyleWilliams, A. L. (2022). Religion and International Relations Theory: The Case of “New” Historiography of Human Rights. Religions, 13(1), 39. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13010039