The Marrano God: Abstraction, Messianicity, and Retreat in Derrida’s “Faith and Knowledge”
Abstract
:The feeling that God himself is dead is the sentiment on which the religion of modern times rests.G.W.F. Hegel, “Faith and Knowledge”1
How then to think—within the limits of reason alone—a religion which, without again becoming ‘natural religion’, would today be effectively universal? And which, for that matter, would no longer be restricted to a paradigm that was Christian or even Abrahamic?Jacques Derrida, “Faith and Knowledge”2
My aim is to offer a close reading of Derrida’s seminal essay, “Faith and Knowledge”, the sole subject of which is the analysis of ‘the religion of modern times’. Hegel, who coined this phrase in his version of Glauben und Wissen, deeply convinced that modern form of religiosity is a true novelty, was still concerned about maintaining continuity with Christian theology in its reformed, Protestant-Lutheran, denomination. Derrida, no longer sharing this concern, experiments with a new concept of a non-normative Marrano religiosity, to which he himself leans in his autobiographical writings.4 Yet his goal is the same as Hegel’s: it is to define die Religion der neuen Zeiten in the new condition of ‘globalitinization’ [mondialatinisation] as an ubiquitous presence which spreads its ‘good news’ through all the possible channels of tele-phonia and tele-vision, making everybody witness its ‘miracles’ through the medium of the globally operating ‘machine’.Claims have also been advanced to the effect that the question of Marranism was recently closed for good. I don’t believe it for a second. There are still sons—and daughters—who, unbeknownst to themselves, incarnate or metempsychosize the ventriloquist specters of their ancestors.Jacques Derrida, “Marx & Sons”3
By referring to Freud’s famous 1917 essay on Mourning and Melancholia, we can phrase the main question of Hegel’s philosophy as: can the ‘infinite grief’ ever be finished? Can it realise itself in a complete work of mourning, or must it perpetuate into infinity as an unworkable burden of melancholy? Hegel is visibly torn between the idea of the infinite process of mourning, which maintains the sacrificial scheme of the ‘death of God religion’ for ever, and the prospect of the sublation of religion into philosophical knowledge, which simultaneously ends religion/faith with its call for sacrifice and keeps it going on a higher, abstractly ontotheological form. In his own take on fides et ratio theme, Derrida points to this aporetic tension in Hegel’s logic, which makes ‘grief’ infinite (i.e., non-sublatable) and temporal (i.e., sublatable) at the same time:For the reconciliation of the individual person with God does not enter as a harmony directly, but as a harmony proceeding only from the infinite grief, from surrender, sacrifice, and the death of what is finite, sensuous, and subjective. Here finite and infinite are bound together into one, and the reconciliation in its true profundity, depth of feeling, and force of mediation is exhibited only through the magnitude of harshness of the opposition which is to be resolved. It follows that even the whole sharpness and dissonance of the suffering, torture, and agony involved in such an opposition, belong to the nature of the spirit itself, whose absolute satisfaction is the subject-matter here.6
And although Derrida does not identify with Hegel’s position, which he understands as the full sublation of religion/faith into philosophical absolute knowledge, he nonetheless is willing to pick up the Hegelian thread of the universalizing ontotheological abstraction—and then to play it out differently. Derrida’s high argument consists in the attempt to abstract, that is, to detach ‘the most serious privation of God’ from the tragic remnants of the sacrificial scheme, which linger in the notion of the ‘infinite grief’. By simultaneously continuing and correcting the Hegelian analysis of die Religion der neuen Zeit, Derrida will thus claim that the current return of the religious ‘proclaimed in every newspaper’ (FK, p. 43) or this ‘machine-like return of religion’ (FK, p. 53), which did not disappear despite all the light-therapy applied by Enlightenment, should be challenged by the Hegelian ‘feeling that God himself is dead’ resulting in the ‘harshest impiety’. Far from dismissing the religious as the bygone element of dark ages, scorched out by the modern ‘light of the day’ (FK, p. 46), Derrida throws himself straight into the Hölderlinian paradox: the coincidence of the highest danger and the growing possibility of redemption, i.e., the aporetic oscillation between ‘the most radical evil’ and the ‘promise of salvation’ (FK, p. 43), which he sees as the defining moment of the returning religion. If ‘radical abstraction’, by which religion travels today all over the globe thanks to the machine of telecommunication, spells the evil of “deracination, delocalization, disincarnation, formalization, universalizing schematization, objectification” (FK, p. 43), it is also still a possibility of a ‘new reflecting faith’ (FK, p. 49), which breaks with the dogmatic cult of any sort and opens itself to a universal moral appeal. And if the ‘harshest impiety’ brought by the Enlightenment may mean the ‘war on religion’ waged for the sake of ‘killing God’, it may also suggest a retreat to ‘the void of the most serious privation of God’, the very ‘desert in the desert’ in which there is no telling ‘what is yet to come’ (FK, p. 47): what God, living or dying, might appear on the radically emptied horizon. The proper abstraction could thus still overcome the false one, while a new form of a reflecting faith could form the ground “in whose name one would protest against” the existing form of religiosity which “only resembles the void”. This protest against the distorted forms of the modern faith, therefore, is not ventured on the grounds of knowledge, but rather on the grounds of another—withdrawn, invisible, ‘harsher’—foi originaire which Derrida wants to reveal (as much as it is possible) and defend:Infinite pain is still only a moment, and the moral sacrifice of empirical existence only dates the absolute Passion or the speculative Good Friday. Dogmatic philosophies and natural religions should disappear and, out of the greatest ‘asperity’, the harshest impiety, out of kenosis and the void of the most serious privation of God [Gottlosigkeit], ought to resuscitate the most serene liberty in its highest totality. Distinct from faith, from prayer or from sacrifice, ontotheology destroys religion, but, yet another paradox, it is also what perhaps informs, on the contrary, the theological and ecclesiastical, even religious, development of faith.(FK, p. 53; my emphasis)
The abstraction of the desert can thereby open the way to everything from which it withdraws. Whence the ambiguity or the duplicity of the religious trait or retreat, of its abstraction or of its subtraction. This deserted re-treat thus makes way for the repetition of that which will have given way precisely for that in whose name one would protest against it, against that which only resembles the void and the indeterminacy of mere abstraction.(FK, p. 55)
1. The ‘Deserted Re-Treat’: Kenosis, Tsimtsum, and Khora
2. Not Kenosis, But Kenoma
Yet, Derrida’s aim is not just to ‘arrest’ the sacrificial logic of the first source, which is the cult of the unscathed pleromatic life. Having in mind the second—kenomatic—source, he also immediately asks the question: “Is a religion imaginable without sacrifice and without prayer?” (FK, p. 88). And then we almost hear, ‘under his breath’: perhaps, perhaps… Just few pages before, Derrida told us that it is ontotheology which is ‘without sacrifice and without prayer’ (FK, p. 53): the new philosophical doctrine which, in a semi-Hegelian fashion, sublates/devours the religious content in order to preserve it in the abstracted form. Another subtle gesturing towards this ‘perhaps’, seemingly in a completely different direction, lurks in the passage in which Derrida describes the challenge to the Christian ‘memory of the Passion’ posed by Judaism and Islam, the “two non-pagan monotheisms that do not accept death any more than multiplicity in God […], alienating themselves from a Europe that signifies the death of God” (FK, p. 51). This alienation, however, should not be conceived as a simple reminder that monotheism signifies a ‘faith in the living One’ (FK, p. 51), but as a prompt suggesting that the ‘death of God’ itself is not an exclusively Christian affair of the ‘tragedy of the cross’, and that it can also be thought in terms of God’s most surprising survival—of a God-in-retreat, a tsimtsem God, who is not to be mourned, but celebrated in his peculiar mode of living-on: among his followers and in the world.This mechanical principle is apparently very simple: life has absolute value only if it is worth more than life. And hence only in so far as it mourns, becoming itself in the labour of infinite mourning, in the indemnification of a spectrality without limit. It is sacred, holy, infinitely respectable only in the name of what is worth more than it and what is not restricted to the naturalness of the bio-zoological (sacrificeable)—although true sacrifice ought to sacrifice not only ‘natural’ life, called ‘animal or ‘biological’, but also that which is worth more than so-called natural life. The price of human life, which is to say, of anthropo-theological life, the price of what to remain safe (heilig, sacred, safe and sound, unscathed, immune), as the absolute price, the price of what ought to inspire respect, modesty, reticence, this price is priceless. It corresponds to what Kant calls the dignity [Würdigkeit] of the end in itself […] This dignity of life can only subsist beyond the present living being. Whence, transcendence, fetishism and spectrality; whence, the religiosity of religion. This excess above and beyond the living, whose life only has absolute value by being worth more than life, more than itself—this, in short, is what opens the space of death that is linked to the automaton (exemplarily ‘phallic’), to technics, the machine, the prosthesis: in a word, to the dimensions of auto-immune and self-sacrificial supplementarity, to this death-drive that is silently at work in every community, every auto-co-immunity, constituting it as such in its iterability, its heritage, its spectral tradition […] Religion, as a response that is both ambiguous and ambivalent is thus an ellipsis: the ellipsis of sacrifice.(FK, pp. 87–88; my emphasis)
3. The Self-Deconstructing Religion, or the Scathed Life
This is all very true: if one treats Jean-Luc Marion as the paradigmatic exponent of the religious belief which, following the long tradition of Anselm’s ontological argument, imputes the incapability to sustain any ‘wound’ to the very essence of the pleromatic godhead—then Derrida, indeed, is the radical denier of such faith. But is this the only way possible to conceive God? What if, apart from the ‘God is death’ of the absolutist theology embraced by Marion, there is also a ‘death of God’ theology which moves, according to its own self-atheologizing and self-deconstructive rhythm, away from the image of the unscathed Infinite towards the affirmation of the finite? Derrida’s critical treatment of the Hegelian–Kantian model of God’s demise complicates the dualistic picture painted by Hägglund, based on the simple opposition of the God who by definition cannot die, on the one hand, and the radical atheism which accepts the premise that whatever is alive must be mortal, on the other.If to be alive is to be mortal, it follows that to not be mortal—to be immortal—is to be dead. If one cannot die, one is dead. Hence, Derrida does not limit himself to the atheist claim that God is dead; he repeatedly makes the radically atheist claim that God is death. That God is death does not mean that we reach God through death or that God rules over death. On the contrary, it means that the idea of immortality—which according to Marion is ‘the idea that we cannot not form of God’—is inseparable from the idea of absolute death.23
Alluding to Lacan’s “Kant avec Sade”, which found a sadistic component of jouissance in a seemingly purely formal Kantian ethics, Derrida points to the libidinal surplus of enjoyment in the paradoxical pride taken in the absolute uniqueness of Christianity as the religion of the dead/killed God. The whole of Derrida’s argument hinges here (as elsewhere) on the notion of sacrifice: kenosis, even the most radical, is still God’s self-offering, and because of that, a toxic gift, which does not liberate its recipients but enslaves them by a perverse gesture of sovereignty. This is also the reason why, against Nancy’s official thesis, Christianity can never fully deconstruct itself into atheism, because it will always be kept on the leash of indebtedness and obligation; a certain bad conscience which keeps returning, more or less involuntarily, in Nietzsche, Heidegger, and Nancy, despite their explicit allegiance to the ‘innocence of becoming’. The Christian dead God can never let his people go: he will forever make them schuldig. Hence, as we have already suggested, in thinking about God-becoming-finite, we must pass beyond the traps of kenosis, which smuggles under its skandalon the idea of a cosmic catastrophe, and thus prevents from imagining God’s act of finitization as a truly free opening, beyond the economy of debt and repayment. This is precisely where tsimtsum—withdrawal/retreat, or another ‘death of God’—enters as the non-sacrificial and non-catastrophic gesture of the divine self-limitation: the gift without sacrifice: the gift of life, which releases the donné from the automatic obligation to return life to the donor.For a certain Christianity will always take charge of the most exacting, the most exact, and the most eschatological hyperbole of deconstruction, the overbid of ‘Hoc est enim corpus meum’. It will still make sacrifice of its own self-deconstruction. Hey, Sade—go for it!26
4. Hail to Impurity: The Marrano God
This passage, talking about encryption, is itself deeply cryptic, but the best way to approach it is not to dismiss it as a negative remark. In fact, it is rather an oblique appreciation of the Marrano conversos, who, only on the surface, would have lost the inner truth of their Jewish identity (even, as Derrida says in Circumfession, in the intimacy of their hearts) but, in fact, would have dispersed it, yet not in the manner of squandering and loss, but in the manner of multiplication which the Biblical topos affirms as the right thing to do, that is, as a mark of successful survival. The marrano (in Spanish, a swine) is a symbol of impurity which lost the memory of his uniqueness and betrayed loyalty to his tradition which is no longer One, but inherently plus d’Un, multiplied and dispersed also internally, contaminated to the point where it is no longer possible to tell the ownmost proper from the alien. But Marrano is also an emblem of a still life [nature morte], which locates itself in between the premodern cult of the Living God and the modern ‘death of God’ religion: seemingly dead, but—still—a life; still, quiet, restrained, self-withdrawn, and yet—still—a life. A paradoxical emblem of the ‘dead nature’: no longer natural, but yet un-dead; not a vitalist pleroma of unbound power, yet—still—some kind of denaturalized life that does not equal death, but stubbornly survives. An emblem of a survival, therefore—yet not by purification and indemnification, but by contamination, which nonetheless retains a trace of its original difference, the dim memory of the Jewish rite of Passover. Here it is, shown to you openly and plainly, on a tray. An opened pomegranate: wounded, cut through, exposing its inner flesh to the alien outside, exposing its scathedeness, wound, blessure, circumcision…28… encrypts faith and destines it to the condition of a sort of Spanish Marrano who would have lost—in truth, dispersed, multiplied—everything up to and including the memory of his unique secret. Emblem of a still life: an opened pomegranate, one Passover evening, on a tray.(FK, p. 100)
Naas says very rightly that “the [Derridean] testament questions even the testament of ash, as if the promise of ashes already promised too much” (MM, p. 242)—yet without this miracle of the promise, there would be no religion, which must always hover in between the two sources: the kenomatic khora which, left on its own slides into ‘indifference’—and the pleromatic God the Sovereign, who by his own quickening power, easily turns into a ‘monstrosity’. The Marranos occupy precisely this troubled, instable in-between.It makes way, perhaps, but without the slightest generosity, neither human nor divine. The dispersion of ashes is not even promised there, nor death given.(FK, p. 100)
5. Still Life, or the Marrano Denaturalization
If so, then its most suitable bearer would indeed be the Marrano as the universal figure of dispersion and contamination, the very opposite of the identitarian purity: the master of survival, the mischling being at home nowhere and everywhere, and the new citizen of the globalatinized empire, carrying his ‘secret’ difference within himself.34Respect for this singular indecision/oscillation or for this hyperbolic outbidding between two originarities, the order of the ‘revealed’ and the order of the ‘revealable’, is this not at once the chance of every responsible decision and of another ‘reflecting faith’, of a new ‘tolerance’?(FK, p. 59; my emphasis)
The first figure alludes to the caricature version of Judaism that is widely sported by ‘a certain Christianity’ (including Hegel and Heidegger)—the blind and mechanical antithesis towards all living physis as the unscathed source of authentic vitality—which Derrida spitefully endorses and intensifies, to the extent of denying the properly ‘separated’, even the blood line, proper name, and proper memory. The truly ‘sundered’ and ‘separated’ one would thus be the Marrano, ultimately and decisively cut from any form of the unscathed that necessarily populate all revealed religions. But to be truly ‘separated’ also means to be able to live on in the condition of permanent Zerrissenheit, to be for ever indifferent to the temptation of counter-fetishization, i.e., to the last remnants of the animistic magic looking for the substitutes of the lost vital sacred—even if, following the Lacanian ‘inverted ladder of desire’, this replacement is to be found in the dead machine, the mechanical death-drive that is itself incapable of dying. The Marrano type of survival, stubbornly living on in the contaminated and compromised realm between Life and Death, Eros and Thanatos—these two giant powers of the pure and unscathed, which always threaten our singular finite lives—is offered by Derrida, as if on a tray, as a modest possibility of salvation. For all of us.1. Violent sundering, to be sure, from the radicality of roots (Entwürzelung, Heidegger would say…) and from all forms of original physis, from all the supposed resources of a force held to be authentically generative, sacred, unscathed, ‘safe and sound’ (heilig): ethnic identity, descent, family, nation, blood and soil, proper name, proer idiom, proper culture, and memory. 2. But also, more than ever, the counter-fetishism of the same desire inverted, the animist relation to the tele-technoscientific machine, which then becomes a machine of evil, and of radical evil, but a machine to be manipulated as much as to be exorcised.(FK, p. 91; my emphasis)
6. A New Alexandria, or the Marrano Universalism
Neither the ‘natural religion’ of one universal human nature nor the ‘revealed religion’ of a particular chosen nation (first Jewish, then European–Christian), this newly thought religion is still ‘abstract’, staying close to the source of revealability itself. Yet, its abstraction is to be conceived in a different way than in Kant’s formalism or Hegel–Kojève’s universal sublation in one global ‘religion of the Spirit’, in which “the moral law inscribes itself at the bottom of our hearts like a memory of the Passion” (FK, p. 50). Although close to the revealable ‘desert in retreat’, the new religion is not contentless: it urges its believers to ‘wander away from their origins’ and to engage in the universalizing process, for, as Derrida says, “in uprooting the tradition that bears it, in atheologizing it, this abstraction, without denying faith, liberates a universal rationality and political democracy that cannot be dissociated from it” (FK, p. 57; my emphasis). The link between abstraction, in which the content retreats from presence, and liberation is absolutely crucial here: just as the Christian ‘memory of the Passion’ hinders the abstraction, by indebting the creatures with the moral call to self-sacrifice—the Marrano ‘memory of Passover’, a dim remembrance of Exodus, liberates creation in a truly emancipatory gesture of khorein/Seinlassen/tsimtsum, which then becomes a blue-print for all further liberations: the universal rationality and political democracy to come, which, as Derrida says in Rogues, will eventually have been ‘like the khora of the political’.40How then to think […] a religion which, without again becoming ‘natural religion’, would today be effectively universal? And which, for that matter, would no longer be restricted to a paradigm that was Christian or even Abrahamic?(FK, p. 53)
7. Conclusions
On the bottom without bottom of an always virgin impassibility, khora of tomorrow in languages we no longer know or do not yet speak. This place is unique, it is the One without name.(FK, p. 100)
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Abraham, Nicolas, and Maria Torok. 1994. The Shell and the Kernel. Edited and Translated by Nicholas T. Rand. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Benjamin, Walter. 2003a. The Task of the Translator. In Selected Writings. Edited by Howard Eiland and Michael W. Jennings. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Benjamin, Walter. 2003b. On Language as Such of Man and the Language of Man. In Selected Writings. Edited by Howard Eiland and Michael W. Jennings. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Bielik-Robson, Agata. 2014. Jewish Cryptotheologies of Late Modernity. Philosophical Marranos. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Bielik-Robson, Agata. 2017a. Burn After Reading: Derrida, the Philosophical Marrano. In Divisible Derridas. Edited by Victor E. Taylor and Stephen Nichols. Colorado: Davies Publication Group (Emergence), pp. 51–70. [Google Scholar]
- Bielik-Robson, Agata. 2017b. God of Luria, Hegel, Schelling: The Divine Contraction and the Modern Metaphysics of Finitude. In Mystical Theology & Continental Philosophy. Edited by David Lewin, Simon D. Podmore and Duane Williams. London and New York: Routledge, pp. 32–30. [Google Scholar]
- Cixous, Helene. 2007. The Stranjew Body. In Judeities. Questions for Jacques Derrida. Edited by Joseph Cohen and Raphael Zagury-Orly. Translated by Bettina Bergo, and Michael B. Smith. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1981. Dissemination. Translated by Barbara Johnson. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1986a. Glas. Translated by John P. Leavey, and Richard Rand. Lincoln and London: Nebraska University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1986b. Fors. In Wolf Man’s Magic Word: A Cryptonymy. Translated by Nicholas Rand. Minneapolis: Minnesota University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1993. Circumfession. In Jacques Derrida and Geoffrey Bennington, Jacques Derrida. Translated by Geoffrey Bennington. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1995a. The Gift of Death. Translated by David Willis. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1995b. On the Name. Translated by John P. Leavey. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1996. Archive Fever. A Freudian Impression. Translated by Eric Prenowitz. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1999. Marx and Sons. In Ghostly Demarcations. A Symposium on Jacques Derrida’s “Specters of Marx”. Edited by Michael Sprinker. Translated by G. M. Goshgarian. London: Verso. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 2002. Faith and Knowledge. The Two Sources of ‘Religion’ at the Limits of Reason Alone. In Acts of Religion. Translated by Gil Anidjar. New York and London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 2005a. On Touching—Jean-Luc Nancy. Translated by Christine Irizarry. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 2005b. Rogues. Two Essays on Reason. Translated by Pascale-Anne Brault. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 2005c. Sovereignties in Question. The Poetics of Paul Celan. Translated by Thomas Dutoit, and Outi Passanen. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 2007. Abraham, The Other. In Judeities. Questions for Jacques Derrida. Edited by Joseph Cohen and Raphael Zagury-Orly. Translated by Bettina Bergo, and Michael B. Smith. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hägglund, Martin. 2008. Radical Atheism. Derrida and the Time of Life. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1975. Aesthetics. Lectures on Fine Art. Translated by Thomas Malcolm Knox. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1976. Phenomenology of Spirit. Translated by Arnold Vincent Miller. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1977. Faith and Knowledge. Translated by Walter Cerf, and Henry Silton Harris. Albany: SUNY Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lacan, Jacques. 1989. Ecrits. A Selection. Translated by Alan Sheridan. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Naas, Michael. 2008. Derrida from Now on. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Naas, Michael. 2012. Miracle and Machine. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nancy, Jean-Luc. 2008a. Corpus. Translated by Richard Rand. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nancy, Jean-Luc. 2008b. Dis-Enclosure. The Deconstruction of Christianity. Translated by Bettina Bergo. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rosenzweig, Franz. 1985. The Star of Redemption. Translated by William W. Hallo. Notre Dame and London: University of Notre Dame Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sherwood, Yvonne. 2014. Specters of Abraham. In Judaism in Contemporary Thought: Traces and Influence. Edited by Agata Bielik-Robson and Adam Lipszyc. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Scholem, Gershom. 1973. Zehn Unhistorische Sätze über Kabbala. In Judaica 3, Studien Zur Jüdischen Mystik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Scholem, Gershom. 1976. On Jews and Judaism in Crisis. Selected Essays. Edited by Werner Dannhauser. New York: Schocken Books. [Google Scholar]
- Scholem, Gershom. 1995. The Messianic Idea in Judaism. And Other Essays on Jewish Spirituality. New York: Schocken Books. [Google Scholar]
- Strauss, Leo. 2013. On Tyranny: Corrected and Expanded Edition, Including the Strauss-Kojève Correspondence. Translated by Victor Gourevitch. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Yovel, Yirmiyahu. 2009. The Other Within. The Marranos: Split Idenity and Emerging Modernity. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfson, Elliott. 2006. Alef, Mem, Tau. Kabbalistic Musings on Time, Truth, and Death. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
1 | |
2 | (Derrida 2002, p. 53). Later on as FK. |
3 | |
4 | Take, for instance, his famous declaration from Circonfession written in 1991, three years before the first draft of “Foi et Savoir”: “I am a kind of Marrano of French Catholic Culture, and I also have my Christian body, inherited from St. Augustine… I am one of those Marranos who, even in the intimacy of their own hearts, do not admit to being Jewish” (Derrida 1993, p. 160). On the significance of Derrida’s Marrano declaration see: Helene Cixous, “The Stranjew Body” (Cixous 2007, p. 55); Yvonne Sherwood, “Specters of Abraham”, (Sherwood 2014); my introduction to Jewish Cryptotheologies of Late Modernity: Philosophical Marranos (Bielik-Robson 2014) and “Burn After Reading: Derrida, the Philosophical Marrano” (Bielik-Robson 2017a). |
5 | I will apply a similar rule in regard to the symphony of Derrida’s commentators and choose one reader, Michael Naas, who devoted the whole book to Derrida’s “Faith and Knowledge”: Miracle and Machine (Naas 2012), later on as MM. Nass, however, makes little of Hegel’s presence in Derrida’s essay on religion, despite the borrowing of the title. In his “Observation on Hegel”, Naas admits that it is always possible that Derrida is hiding his major influence, but “a lot of interpretative work would need to be done to make this case, and even more would need to be done to show that Derrida was trying, in ‘Faith and Knowledge’, to intervene in the debate between Kant and Hegel. In his attempt to understand the nature of religion today, Derrida had other things in view. For instead of ending his text with a reference to the speculative Good Friday, he concludes with an equally dramatic reference to violence, to ashes, to the massacre at Chatila, and to ‘an open pomegranate, one Passover evening, on a tray’” (MM, p. 310). While not disagreeing with Naas, I would like to challenge his dismissal of Hegel, and demonstrate that Derrida constantly refers to Hegel in order to subvert, but to also supplement his ‘memory of the Passion’ with a different memory of a different mourning, violence, and ashes: a Marrano testimony of the forced loss of God, which created a different kind of memory and commemoration. |
6 | |
7 | Although the very term—tsimtsum—by which the 16th century kabbalist, Isaac Luria, denotes the ‘contraction of God’, does not appear explicitly in Derrida’s essay (which can also be seen as a typically Marrano manoeuvre of covering up the traces), there is one early text, testifying to his profound knowledge of the theme: “Dissemination”, devoted to Philippe Soller’s novel Nombres, where Derrida states that the idea of tsimtsum is “linked to the mythology of Louria” (as he pronounces his name according to the French usage) (Derrida 1981, p. 344). Derrida was also highly aware of the importance of the divine ‘retreat’ in the work of Lévinas. |
8 | This version of tsimtsum, in which God ‘takes in his breath’ and restricts his glory for the sake of something else to emerge, derives already from Isaiah, as described by Elliott Wolfson in his interpretation of one of the bahiric texts: “The notion of withdrawal, itself withdrawn and thus not stated overtly, is a secret that is exegetically derived from the verse lema‘an shemi a’arikh appi u-tehillati ehetam lakh le-vilti hakhritekha, ‘For the sake of my name I will postpone my wrath and my glory I will hold in for you so that I will not destroy you’ (Isa 48:9). The plain sense of the prophetic dictum relates to divine mercy as expressed as God’s long-suffering, the capacity to restrain his rage. The expression tehillati ehetam, literally ‘my glory I will hold in’, is parallel to a’arikh appi, ‘I will postpone my wrath’. One may surmise that at some point in ancient Israel, the notion of a vengeful god yielded its opposite, the compassionate god who holds in his fury” (Wolfson 2006, pp. 132–33). |
9 | On the significance of the Lurianic heritage, especially for German Idealism, see my “God of Luria, Hegel, Schelling: The Divine Contraction and the Modern Metaphysics of Finitude” (Bielik-Robson 2017b). |
10 | Jacques Derrida, “Abraham, The Other” (Derrida 2007, p. 33). Michael Naas also notices Derrida’s ‘jewgreek–greekjew’ tendency to produce a dense interference of the two idioms, for instance, in the description of his tallith in “A Silkworm of One’s Own” which brings it close to khora: “… and, finally, the tallith, the white tallith, as what belongs to the ‘night, the absolute night’ also resembles khora as ‘the place of absolute exteriority’, the ‘nocturnal source’ of both religion and science. The tallith is thus, in some sense, another name for khora, the place that gives place and has no name that is absolutely proper to it” (MM, pp. 231–32). |
11 | In Naas’ great comment: “Before any social or political space, it [khora] would join or link singularities by saying simply, in an infinitely low voice, and in the name of another tolerance, Space Available” (MM, p. 182). Yet, in fact, in order for it to speak with such a ‘low voice’ (bat kol), or to simply speak at all, it already must be partly ‘appropriated’ by a certain messianic tradition which decides to interpret its passive ‘letting-things-be’ as an at least vestigially active ‘making-place’, i.e., to turn its indifference into generosity. In this domain, therefore, everything is contaminated: there is no pure source of ‘revealability’, and no pure abstraction of ‘messianicity’. |
12 | |
13 | |
14 | |
15 | Derrida’s take on the Marrano secret as simultaneously attacking the religious sovereignty and realizing that the messianic message goes indeed hand in hand with Gershom Scholem who, in his studies on the Marrano theology, wrote: “The psychology of the ‘radical’ Sabbatians was utterly paradoxical and ‘Marranic’. Essentially its guiding principle was: Whoever is as he appears to be cannot be a true ‘believer’. In practice this means the following: The ‘true faith’ cannot be a faith which men publicly profess. On the contrary, the ‘true faith’ must always be concealed. In fact, it is one’s duty to deny it outwardly, for it is like a seed that has been planted in the bed of the soul and it cannot grown unless it is first covered over. For this reason every Jew is obliged to become a Marrano” (Scholem 1995, p. 109; my emphasis). |
16 | As Hegel himself observed in Phenomenology of Spirit, calling the ‘facile’ Trinitarian synthesis ein eitles Spiel: “Thus the life of God and divine cognition may well be spoken of as disporting of Love with itself; but this idea sinks into mere edification, and even insipidity, if it lacks the seriousness, the suffering, the patience, and the labour of the negative. In itself, that life is indeed one untroubled equality and unity with itself, for which otherness and alienation, and the overcoming of alienation, are not serious matters” (Hegel 1976, p. 11). This objection, uttered mostly against Schelling’s notion of the self-healing Absolute, marks a significant change in Hegel’s theological views. Before, i.e., at the stage of “Christianity and Its Fate”, he would still maintain the idea of the holy as das unverletzte Leben, ‘life unharmed’—the obvious prototype for Derrida’s vie indemne—which excludes by definition any moment of negativity: lack, suffering, or death. It is only in the mature middle phase, when he composes Phenomenology, that he opens himself to another possibility: of fully and seriously admitting ‘the terrible thought that God himself is dead’ and that negativity is not just an attribute of the profane, but also a most holy affair. |
17 | The objection that the ‘wound’ sustained by the Father is merely a dokos, a ‘facade’, all too easily healed in the Trinitarian play, appears often in Derrida’s writings, most of all in Glas (where it is leveled against Hegel’s romantic conception of the self-healing and scarless wounds of the Spirit), as well as in Dissemination, where the Trinitarian play is contrasted with the ‘real’ crisis in the godhead, resulting in the ‘real’ dispersion of beings, and calling for the ‘real’ messianic action. In Trinity, therefore, the ‘death of God’, in which the Father loses his breath/Spirit/ruah, remains merely apparent, because the Father “loses his breath in sustaining, retaining, idealizing, reinternalizing, and mastering his seed”. In consequence, the crisis is quickly ‘mastered’, as it “would be acted out […] between father and son alone: aitoinsemination, homoinsemination, reinsemination” (Derrida 1981, p. 45). Whereas, the eponymous dissemination is a ‘real’ loss of integrity, unity, and safety of the divine which gives itself over to the risk, empties itself out completely, without a remainder, and opens itself to the irreversible process of alienation. |
18 | |
19 | |
20 | |
21 | |
22 | |
23 | (Hägglund 2008, p. 8). The paradox of the deadening idemnification is a frequent subject of Abraham and Torok’s reflections on the en-cryption, cryptonymy, and cryptophoria, also commented on by Derrida in his preface to their Wolf Man’s Magic Word: “A crypt, people believe, always hides something dead. But to guard it from what? Against what does one keep a corpse intact, safe both from life and from death, which could both come in from the outside to touch it? And to allow death to take no place in life?” (Derrida 1986b, p. xxi). Indeed, “day in day out, the crypt itself remains unscathed” (Abraham and Torok 1994, p. 152; my emphasis). The ‘shell’, therefore, i.e., the wall that creates the crypt, not only deadens/oppresses the ‘kernel’, which lies there deposited, but also protects it and guards in its hiddenness—which, for Derrida, is precisely the dialectical model for the relation between Knowledge (shell) and Faith (kernel). |
24 | For Derrida, the true Gelassenheit, therefore, is the art of “abandoning God who abandons himself”: not an attempt to cling to him, not even to grasp him—just “not give anything to God, not even Adieu, not even to his name… This is how I sometimes understand the tradition of Gelazenheit, the serenity that allows being without indifference, let’s go without abandoning, unless it abandons without forgetting or forgets without forgetting” (Derrida 1995b, pp. 73, 84; my emphasis). He also calls this position, after Leibniz, an ‘almost-atheism’ (Derrida 1995b, p. 83). In a moment, we shall see that this paradoxical ‘forgetting without forgetting’ that leads to the ‘almost-atheism’ characterizes the Marrano ‘memory of the Passover’, constituting a Derridean alternative to the Hegelian ‘memory of the Passion’. |
25 | See (Nancy 2008a) as well as (Nancy 2008b). |
26 | (Derrida 2005a, p. 60; my emphasis). |
27 | Naas comments: “It is precisely those discourses of life that believe they can exclude death, those that believe they can return to a life protected from corruption, that often lead to the worst possible violence, the most nightmarish scenes of death and destruction—all fed by the phantasm of a life greater than life, the dream, in short, of a miracle that can do without the machine” (MM, p. 196). |
28 | In French, the title of the section is ‘… et grenades’: a phrase which involves an ambivalence lost in the English translation, but which was well spotted by Michael Naas, who in Derrida from Now on writes: “While the latter context [which I have just analysed—ABR] justifies the translation of grenades by ‘pomegranates’, its context here, in the midst of a text on religion and science, faith and violence, is not so determined as to exclude the other meaning of grenades in French, namely, ‘grenades’. Indeed, Derrida appears to have lobbed this word into the middle of the fifty-two sections of “Faith and Knowledge” in order to gather or, rather, disperse many of the themes of the phantasm that we have been following throughout this essay, in order to evoke all the tensions between, precisely, faith and knowledge, nature and culture, the pomegranate of religion and the grenade of techno-science, a symbol of female fertility, of life-giving seed, on the one hand, and an image of masculine violence, of shrapnel-casting death, on the other, the blood-red pomegranate of Persephone, on the one hand, and the army-green hand-held machine of technoscience, on the other” (Naas 2008, p. 205, later on as DFNO). The intimate link between pomegranates and grenades can thus be deconstructed, but it cannot be fully deactivated: whenever the kenomatic source comes into the presence of a revealed religion and its techniques of maintaining this presence in the media machine, the innocent fruit hardens into a potential weapon. |
29 | |
30 | This awakening is a cryptotheological theme of Derrida’s essay on Joyce, Ulysses Gramophone, where God, implicitly compared to a writer who relinquishes the right of control over his work, pours himself into the creation and then releases it, by leaving only his consenting signature: Yes, yes. |
31 | Again, it is Michael Naas who seems particularly attentive to Derrida’s gnomic, cryptic, and simultaneously hyper-condensed Marrano imagery, which deliberately avoids full articulation. While commenting on the pomegranate ‘still life’, he states that “faith would be a Marrano that eludes this putative self-presence (like a crypt within ontotheology) and opens this seemingly indivisible identity (like a cut pomegranate) […] Faith would thus be encrypted like a Marrano within religion, given a chance to circulate within a religion only on the condition of hiding or being concealed within it […] Faith would be encrypted in ontotheology in this way, sublimated, one might say, forced underground, forced to go by other names or go about in other guises, able to reveal its true identity only to other members of the same secret community […] But the Marrano Derrida is evoking here would be a Marrano, even to this secret community, a Marrano of Marranos, then, a secret even for or to those in on the secret, not unlike the desert within the desert that is khora. It is in this sense that we must understand why Derrida refers to himself not only as ‘a sort of Marrano of French Catholic culture’ but, in an untranslatable French phrase, as le dernier des juifs, that is, as the ‘last of the Jews’, ‘the least of the Jews’, but also ‘the most Jewish of Jews’, the most because the least, the least became the most, the first because the last, and so on” (MM, pp. 232–33; my emphasis). |
32 | |
33 | See Naas commenting on this ontologistic rule of presence: “The sacred or the holy is related not just to sovereign power but to an exuberant, fecund force capable of bringing to life in a spontaneous and automatic way. The phallus effect or the fecund belly rises up of its own accord, self-seeding and self-bearing—like an Immaculate Conception” (DFNO, p. 204). This is how every revealed religion, precisely because of the moment of coming-into-light, necessarily must result in the repression of the kenomatic source for the sake of the visible and monstrable, which automatically tends to assume aspects of pleromatic vitality. |
34 | The Marrano context of the modern ‘reflecting faith’ as being secretly internalized and suppported only by the ‘inner heart’, itself also prone to forgetting, was spotted very aptly by Yirmiyahu Yovel: “For them [Marranos] authentic religion had been desinstitutionalized and privatized…, depending on the inner heart as its almost sole support. There were, of course, supporting fragments of memory and custom, and the sense of secret fraternity… In the end, and all along, the person had to face the most important religious truths—decisions about value, and about personal fate in this and the next world—within a private ‘inner forum’”. This could indeed be a good portrait of Derrida as the Marrano: grappling with the imperatives of the ‘inner heart’ (in constant polemical reference to Paul and Augustine); resorting to supporting accessories like tallith (as in “Silkworm”); having a sense of secret fraternity (including even frere Heidegger, as in On Spirit: Heidegger and The Question); bearing witness to the most singular idiosyncrasy that is a secret, even to itself (as in Archive Fever); and the play between the ‘inner forum’ and the ‘fors/fortress’ of the crypt, in which the Marrano secret has been deposited (as in “Fors”, written as a preface to Abraham and Torok’s famous book on cryptophoria); and finally, faithful to the ‘encrypted’ Jewish God, who comes to haunt the living as a reverant or ghost/phantom, and who is not ‘resurrected daily’, as in Hegel, but merely evoked as a spectre (as in Specters of Marx). Yovel himself admits it by calling Derrida’s ‘non-Jewish Jewishness’ the very epitome of the Marrano experience consciously turned into a universal condition, where the split, non-integral and unfinished identity becomes a paradigm of the modern subject which, precisely because of that, can only be described in terms of a meta-identitarian remnant (le derniere des Juifs): “Derrida considered himself a non-Jewish Jew and a kind of Marrano. He identified in his Jewishness all the marks of dualities and disintegrated identity that his philosophy ascribed to the human condition in general” (Yovel 2009, pp. 88, 367; my emphasis). |
35 | |
36 | See most of all (Strauss 2013). |
37 | See (Rosenzweig 1985), especially Part 3, “Redemption”. |
38 | Perhaps, it is precisely this ‘different Christianity’ which has not yet revealed its essence, of which Derrida speaks in the Gift of Death about his reflections on Jan Patocka’s Heretical Essays (Derrida 1995a, pp. 6–7). |
39 | There is a myriad of meanings of the Derridean use of the term ‘machine’, and Michael Naas is very good at listing them, but there is one which he omits, and which seems to play a crucial role in Derrida’s essay on religion. For, if miracle is indeed ‘breath’ (ruah, souffle) and life of faith, then machine is law and ritual: the pattern of repetition, in which faith confirms itself in the worldly conditions. However, it is precisely this pattern of repetition which rendered Jewish religion susceptible to the accusation of a ‘mechanical obedience’, which started with Saint Paul and culminated in Hegel’s Early Theological Writings: one of the tenets of Derrida’s essay is to deconstruct this objection levelled from the angle of the ‘genuine faith’ or the purely spiritual Innerlichkeit. The paradox of this ‘authenticity’ is that while it derives from the ‘religion of the death of God’, it nonetheless restores God to pure life in the inner shrine of the soul: as I have shown, the Hegelian ‘infinite mourning’ (which, being infinite, cannot ever become the complete work of mourning) makes God ‘resurrect daily’ in the nostalgic effort to compensate for the scandal of his sacrificial death. Whereas Derrida’s Marrano argument is that there is nothing to mourn or compensate for: God has died for the world to make it possible—make the ‘space available’—and there is no need to repent for it; God has given up on the singular miracle of his life, so that the machine of being could go on; or, in yet other words, God has abandoned his unique idiom for the sake of the strange institution called reality. ‘Authenticity’, and ‘pure faith’, therefore, would be the internalized variation on the unscathed unverletztes Leben, which, being the force of pure life, is also the force of pure death. And since this equation—pure life is the same as pure death—is also a Hegelian formula, one can also read Derrida’s essay as a Hegelian correction of Hegel himself, who, otherwise a dialectical thinker of universal contamination, has to be made free of this one phantasmatic blind spot of ‘purity’: his theologically driven, Lutheran, investment in sola fide, ‘pure faith’. As Naas very rightly comments: “Hence faith and knowledge, religion and science, the miracle and the machine, must be thought together as a single possibility, a single possibility that divides or fissures already at the origin. They are not the same thing, but they cannot be thought separately. Both are possible only on the basis of a ‘testimonial deus ex machina’, which always already betrays and displays the duplicity of origins, a deus that from the beginning becomes deux, at once miracle and machine” (MM, p. 166). |
40 | |
41 | It must, therefore, be emphasized that, for Derrida, the tallith is not a symbolic part of the sacramental whole, where the external elements of liturgy complement the internal element of faith. It is not an external symbol of the internal faith, where the two form an integral cotemporaneous totality. Derrida’s tallith is detached and ‘abstracted’ from its religious context, and functions as a mnemonic device, the role of which is to remind of the almost-forgotten, by-gone, and concealed God. In that sense, it is rather a Benjaminian allegory, taken out of the ‘tradition in ruins’, than a living sacramental symbol. |
42 | |
43 | See (Benjamin 2003a, p. 257). For Benjamin, the translation works as die Ergänzung, or the completion, where it is simultaneously a contaminating and completing agent, gesturing towards the elusive totality of the ‘pure language’—the living lingua adamica that Benjamin talks about in his essay “On Language as Such of Man and the Language of Man”—which can only be partly reflected in the fragmented languages of the ‘post-Babelian’ condition: “All higher language is a translation of lower ones, until in ultimate clarity the word of God unfolds, which is the unity of this movement made up of language” (Benjamin 2003b, p. 74). |
44 | See (Yovel 2009, p. 61), where the Marrano is described as the first modern “type [of man] that lives beyond the spheres of conventional belief and mentality”. |
© 2018 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Bielik-Robson, A. The Marrano God: Abstraction, Messianicity, and Retreat in Derrida’s “Faith and Knowledge”. Religions 2019, 10, 22. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10010022
Bielik-Robson A. The Marrano God: Abstraction, Messianicity, and Retreat in Derrida’s “Faith and Knowledge”. Religions. 2019; 10(1):22. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10010022
Chicago/Turabian StyleBielik-Robson, Agata. 2019. "The Marrano God: Abstraction, Messianicity, and Retreat in Derrida’s “Faith and Knowledge”" Religions 10, no. 1: 22. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10010022
APA StyleBielik-Robson, A. (2019). The Marrano God: Abstraction, Messianicity, and Retreat in Derrida’s “Faith and Knowledge”. Religions, 10(1), 22. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10010022