A Question of Life and Death: The Aesopic Animal Fables on Why Not to Kill
Abstract
:And now I will tell a fable (ainos) to kings who themselves too have understanding. This is how the hawk addressed the colourful-necked nightingale, carrying her high up among the clouds, grasping her with its claws, while she wept piteously, pierced by the curved claws; he said to her forcefully, ‘Silly bird, why are you crying out? One far superior to you is holding you. You are going wherever I shall carry you, even if you are a singer; I shall make you my dinner if I wish, or I shall let you go. Stupid he who would wish to contend against those stronger than he is: for he is deprived of the victory, and suffers pains in addition to his humiliations.’ So spoke the swift-flying hawk, the long-winged bird. As for you, Perses […](Trans. Glenn W. Most, see (Hesiod 2007)
1. Animal Fables as Stories
A donkey who had a sore on his back was grazing in a meadow. A raven alighted on his back and began to peck at the wound, while the donkey brayed and reared up on his hind legs in pain (algein). The donkey’s driver, meanwhile, stood off at a distance and laughed. A wolf who was passing by saw the whole thing and said to himself, ‘How unfairly we wolves are treated! When people so much as catch a glimpse of us, they drive us away, but when someone like that raven makes his move, everyone just looks at him and laughs.’
The fable shows that even before they act, dangerous people can be recognized at a distance.(Trans. Laura Gibbs)
2. Animal Antagonism and Focalisation in the Homeric Similes
On the other side Peleus’ son ran to meet him, like a lion / bent on slaughter that a whole village’s resolute men have / gathered together to kill; at first it pays them no attention and / continues on its way, but when some war-swift young man / hits it with his spear it crouches, jaws gaping, and foam / gathers around its teeth, and the brave spirit in its heart / groans, and with its tail it lashes its ribs and flanks on / both sides, and drives itself on to fight; staring-eyed, / its fury carries it straight at the men, hoping either to kill / one of them or to die itself in the forefront of the conflict. / In just this way his fury and noble spirit drove Achilles on / to come face to face with great-hearted Aeneas. (Iliad 20.164–75)(Trans. Anthony Verity)
As a lion easily crushes the bones of a swift hind’s / young fawns, when it came upon their lair and seized / them in its mighty teeth, and rips out their tender hearts; and the mother, even if she chances to be nearby, cannot / help them, because fearful trembling overcomes her limbs, / and at once she darts away through dense thickets and woodland, / in a sweating fervour to escape the powerful beast’s attack; / so no one of the Trojans could keep death from these two, / but were themselves driven in panic before Argives.(Trans. Anthony Verity)32
The goddess Artemis fled cowering and weeping, like a pigeon / that flies from a hawk’s pursuit into the hollow of a rock, a / deep cleft, because it was not its destiny to be caught; just so / Artemis fled weeping, leaving her bow and arrow where they were. (Iliad 21.493–496)(Trans. Anthony Verity)
3. Begging for Mercy
Once a wolf saw a lamb that had gone astray from the flock, but instead of rushing upon him to seize him by force, he tried to find a plausible complaint by which to justify his hostility (egklēma ekhthrēs euprosōpon). ‘Last year, small though you were, you slandered me.’ ‘How could I last year? It’s not yet a year since I was born.’ ‘Well, then, aren’t you cropping this field, which is mine?’ ‘No, for I’ve not eaten any grass nor have I begun to graze.’ ‘And haven’t you drunk from the fountain which is mine to drink from?’ ‘No, even yet my mother’s breast provides my nourishment.’ Thereupon the wolf seized the lamb and while eating him remarked: ‘You’re not going to rob the wolf of his dinner even though you do find it easy to refute all my charges.’(Trans. Ben Perry)
A cat had seized a rooster and wanted to find a reasonable pretext for devouring him (met’ eulogou aitias katathoinēsasthai). He began by accusing the rooster of bothering people by crowing at night, making it impossible for them to sleep. The rooster said that this was actually an act of kindness on his part, since people needed to be woken up in order to begin their day’s work. The cat then made a second accusation, ‘But you are also a sinner who violates nature’s own laws when you mount your sisters and your mother.’ The rooster said that this also was something he did for his masters’ benefit, since this resulted in a large supply of eggs. The cat found himself at a loss and said, ‘Even if you have an endless supply of arguments, do you think that I am not going to eat you?’(Trans. Laura (Gibbs 2002) slightly modified)41
4. ‘A War against Each Other Among All Animals’
Anthos is at war with the horse: the horse drives it out of the pasture, for the anthos forages in grass, and has white film on its eyes and does not see sharply: it mimics the horse’s voice and scares him by flying at him; and he drives it away, but whenever he catches it he kills it. The anthos lives beside river and marshes; its colour is beautiful and it lives well.(Trans. D.M. Balme)
5. Humans as a Threat to Other Animals
6. Concluding Words
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Adrados, Francisco Rodriguez. 1999. History of the Graeco-Latin Fable. Volume One: Introduction and from the Origins to the Hellenistic Age. Translated by Leslie A. Ray. This edition has been revised and updated by the author and Gert-Jan van Dijk. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Arnott, Geoffrey. 2007. Birds in the Ancient World from A to Z. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Barringer, Judith M. 2001. The Hunt in Ancient Greece. Baltimore & London: John Hopkins University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Clarke, Michael. 1995. Between Lions and Men: Images of Hero in the Iliad. Greek Roman and Byzantine Studies 36: 137–60. [Google Scholar]
- Calder, Louise. 2011. Cruelty and Sentimentality: Greek Attitudes to Animals 600–300 BC (Studies in Classical Achaeology V). Oxford: Archaeopress. [Google Scholar]
- Clayton, Edward. 2008. Aesop, Aristotle, and Animals: The Role of Fables in Human Life. Humanitas 21: 179–200. [Google Scholar]
- Cohoon, J. W. 1939. Dio Chrysostom Discourses 12-30. Translated by J. W. Cohoon. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dijk, Gert-Jan van. 1997. Ainoi, Logoi, Muthoi. Fables in Archaic, Classical and Hellenistic Greek Literature. With a Study of the Theory and Terminology of the Genre. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Dombrowski, Daniel A. 2014. Philosophical Vegetarianism and Animal Entitlements. In The Oxford Handbook of Animals in Classical Thought and Life. Edited by Gordon L. Campbell. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 535–55. [Google Scholar]
- Eitler, Pascal. 2014. Doctor Dolittle’s Empathy. In Learning How to Feel: Children’s Literature and Emotional Socialization, 1870–1970. (Emotions in History). Edited by Ute Frevert, Pascal Eitler, Stephanie Olsen, Uffa Jensen, Margrit Pernau, Daniel Brückenhaus, Magdalena Beljan, Benno Gammerl, Anja Laukötter, Bettina Hitzer and et al. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 74–93. [Google Scholar]
- Fraser, Anthony Ferguson. 2012. Feline Behaviour and Welfare. Wallingford: CABI. [Google Scholar]
- French, Roger. 1994. Ancient Natural History. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Gibbs Laura, trans. 2002, Aesop’s Fables. (Oxford World’s Classics). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Gilhus, Ingvild Saelid. 2006. Animals, Gods, and Humans: Changing Attitudes to Animals in Greek, Roman and Early Christian Ideas. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Halliwell, Stephen. 2008. Greek Laughter: A Study of Cultural Psychology from Homer to Early Christianity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Harel, Naama. 2009. The Animal Voice behind the Animal Fable. Critical Animal Studies 7: 9–21. [Google Scholar]
- Hesiod. 2007. Theogony. Works and Days. Testimonia. (Loeb Classical Library, 57). Translated and Edited by Most Glenn W.. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Herman, David. 2012. Toward a Zoonarratology: Storytelling and Species Difference in Animal Comics. In Narrative, Interrupted: The Plotless, the Disturbing and the Trivial in Literature. Berlin and Boston: De Gruyter, pp. 93–119. [Google Scholar]
- De Jong, Irene. 2014. Narratology & Classics: A Practical Guide. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kennedy, George A. 2003. Progymnasmata: Greek Texbooks of Prose Composition and Rhetoric. Leiden: Society of Biblical Literature. [Google Scholar]
- Korhonen, Tua. 2017. The Birds Point of View in Aristophanes’ Birds. In Human and Animal in Ancient Greece: Empathy and Encounter in Classical Literature. Edited by Tua Korhonen and Erika Ruonakoski. London: I.B. Tauris, pp. 144–59. [Google Scholar]
- Lamarque, Pierre. 1990. Narrative and Invention: The Limits of Fictionality. In Narrative in Culture: The Uses of Storytelling in the Science, Philosophy, and Literature. Edited by Christopher Nash. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Lefkowitz, Jeremy B. 2014. Aesop and Animal Fable. In The Oxford Handbook of Animals in Classical Thought and Life. Edited by Gordon L. Campbell. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 1–23. [Google Scholar]
- Lonsdale, Steven H. 1990. Creatures of Speech: Lion, Herding, and Hunting Similes in the Iliad. (Beiträge zur Altertumskunde, Band 5). Stuttgart: Teubner. [Google Scholar]
- Marvin, Garry, and Susan McHugh. 2014. Routledge Handbook of Human-Animal Studies. London & New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Perry, Ben Edwin. 1952. Aesopica A Series of Texts Relating to Aesop or Ascribed to Him. Vol. 1: Greek and Latin Texts. Urbana: University of Illinois Press. [Google Scholar]
- Perry, Ben Edwin. 1965. Babrius and Phaedrus. Newly edited and newly translated into English, together with historical introduction and a comprehensive survey of Greek and Latin fables in the Aesopic tradition (Loeb Classical Library, 436). London: Heinemann and Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Peterson, Rolf O., and Paolo Ciucci. 2003. The Wolf as Carnivore. In Wolves: Behavior, Ecology and Conservation. Edited by L. David Mech and Luigi Boitani. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 111–51. [Google Scholar]
- Pusey, Anne, and Marisa Wolf. 1996. Inbreeding Avoidance in Animals. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 11: 201–06. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rahn, Helmut. 1953. Tier und Mensch in der Homerischen Auffassung der Wirklichkeit. Paideuma 5: 277–97. [Google Scholar]
- Rahn, Helmut. 1954. Tier und Mensch in der Homerischen Auffassung der Wirklichkeit. Paideuma 7/8: 431–80. [Google Scholar]
- Rothwell, Kenneth S., Jr. 2007. Nature, Culture and the Origins of Greek Comedy: A Study of Animal Choruses. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ruonakoski, Erika. 2017. Reading Ancient Greek Literature through Phenomenology. In Human and Animal in Ancient Greece: Empathy and Encounter in Classical Literature. Edited by Tua Korhonen and Erika Ruonakoski. London: I.B. Tauris, pp. 8–41. [Google Scholar]
- Sampson, Michael C. 2012. A Note on Archilochus Fr. 177 and the Anthropomorphic Façade in Early Fable. The Classical Quarterly 62: 466–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Simons, John. 2002. Animals Rights and the Politics of Literary Representation. Basingstoke, Wiltshire: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Steiner, Deborah. 2010. Framing the Fox: Callimachus Second Iamb and its Predecessors. Journal of Hellenic Studies 130: 97–107. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Teittinen, Jouni. 2015. Passing the Cattle Car: Anthropomorphism, Animal Suffering, and James Agee’s A Mother’s Tale. In Affect, Space, and Animals. Edited by Jopi Nyman and Nora Schurman. London: Routledge, pp. 151–62. [Google Scholar]
- Tilg, Stefan. 2014. Apuleius’ Metamorphoses: A Study in Roman Fiction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Verity, Anthony. 2011. Homer: The Iliad. Translated by Anthony Verity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- West, Martin L. 2003. Homeric Hymns, Homeric Apocrypha, Lives of Homer. (Loeb Classical Library, 496). Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Zafiropoulos, Christos A. 2001. Ethics in Aesop’s Fables: The Augustana Collection. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
1 | On Human-Animal Studies, see, for example, (Marvin and McHugh 2014). |
2 | Stefan Tilg argues that the original Greek story of this metamorphosis into a donkey is from the first century CE (Tilg 2014, pp. 2–3). However, the story itself could be earlier. |
3 | The only extant animal epic from antiquity is The Battle of Frogs and Mice (Batrachomyomachia). On animal and bird epics, see (West 2003, pp. 229–37). |
4 | |
5 | On ancient theories of fable and its functions, see (Dijk 1997, pp. 38–78). Dijk mentions persuasive, didactic, comical, and aetiological functions of fables (Dijk 1997, pp. 38–78). |
6 | By the notion of ‘animal sensitive’, I mean not only an awareness of ethical issues concerning animals, but simply the awareness of animals, in addition to their function and role in human cultures. |
7 | |
8 | Naama Harel discusses the Aesopic fables in her essay as translations and also deals with such classic modern fables as George Orwell’s Animal Farm (Harel 2009). |
9 | (Lefkowitz 2014, p. 2). Others, like Edward Clayton and C. Michael Sampson have introduced the same kind of interpretation. See (Clayton 2008, pp. 180, 196; Sampson 2012, pp. 473–74). |
10 | Deborah Steiner interprets ‘The Hawk and The Nightingale’ as an expression of rivalry between different kinds of poetics, see (Steiner 2010, p. 107). The hawk has also been interpreted to represent a divine instrument. On the different interpretations of this fable see (Dijk 1997, pp. 127–34). The antagonism between hawk and nightingale is the topic in two other Aesopic fables, Perry 4 and 567. |
11 | On the Mesopotamian fable and its influence on Greek fable, see (Adrados 1999, pp. 287–306); on the agonistic ethos in the Aesopic fables, see (Zafiropoulos 2001). |
12 | On fables and Homeric similes, see (Dijk 1997, p. 125). According to Rodriguez Adrados, who has compared the fable with many other genres of archaic Greek literature, the typical situation of agonistic confrontation in the Iliadic similes, like a lion attacking a herd of cattle or a fold of sheep, ‘provide the basis for fables from the Classical Age and collections’. Adrados does not, however, clarify what he means by ‘the basis’ (Adrados 1999, p. 198). |
13 | |
14 | On the terminology of the Greek fable, see (Adrados 1999, pp. 3–16; Dijk 1997, pp. 79–89). |
15 | The grammarian Theon of Alexandria, who lived in the first century CE, defined a fable as ‘a fictitious story picturing or reminding one of (eikonizein) reality’ (Dijk 1997, pp. 47–48, 408; Adrados 1999, p. 23). |
16 | I am using the index system of Ben Perry’s (Perry 1952). On fable collections, see (Adrados 1999, pp. 48–136). |
17 | One of the first collections was composed during the third century BCE in Alexandria by Demetrius of Phalerum, the one-time student of Aristotle’s philosophical school. Demetrius’ (now lost) collection could have been in use until late antiquity. On Demetrius’ collection, see (Dijk 1997, pp. 410–97, 540; Adrados 1999, p. 23). |
18 | On writing fables as part of the rhetorical exercises (Progymnasmata), see (Kennedy 2003). |
19 | These four features of narratives—time, structure, voice, and point of view—are listed by Peter Lamarque. See (Lamarque 1990, p. 131). |
20 | (Dijk 1997, p. 114); On different kinds of narrator–character combinations in fables, see (Dijk 1997, pp. 373–74) and on different formal schemes, see (Adrados 1999, pp. 35–36). |
21 | This kind of character is called survenant by the fable scholar M. Nøjgaard (1964–7). See (Dijk 1997, pp. 9, 373). |
22 | The term epimythium (plural: epimythia) denotes that the moral of the story is given at the end. The moral can also be given at the beginning, when it is called promythium. The latter case was probably the earlier practice, originating in the days when fables were collected and when the moral functioned as a kind of title for the fable (Perry 1965. pp. xv–xvi). |
23 | |
24 | A similar but much later fable in Latin is ‘The Wolf, The Crow and the Sheep’ (Perry 670). See also ‘The Well-meaning Wolves’ (Perry 676). Both are from the codex Bruxellenses 536 from the 14th century, including fables from late antiquity. |
25 | |
26 | Aristotle was the first to discuss fables theoretically in his Rhetoric (2.20.1393b8–94a9). In Aristotle’s view, the fable (mythos) is a good instrument of persuasion and he tells two animal fables (‘The Stag, the Horse and the Man’ and ‘The Fox and the Lice’) to prove their usability in political speeches, especially in those directed towards the common people. |
27 | Sometimes fables remind one of mirabilia, stories of the strange ways of animals, a genre which Aristotle made good use of in his zoological works, and later writers like Plinius, Plutarch, Aelian, and Athenaeus developed them as an ingredient in their works on animals. Miraculous stories of animals were part of natural histories depicting the wonders of nature, but they also included stories of unique incidences and individual animals. The Aristotelean corpus included falsely attributed work belonging to the mirabilia genre: On Marvellous Things Heard. On this genre and the paradoxographers, see, e.g., (French 1994, pp. 299–303). |
28 | (Rahn 1953, p. 288; Rahn 1954, pp. 452, 466–67). According to Rahn, human beings are not seen as ‘rein menschlich’. |
29 | |
30 | The famous stallion simile, which occurs twice in the Iliad (6.506–14 and 15.263–268), depicts the stallion’s exultant gallop. All translations of Homer’s Iliad in this paper are by Anthony Verity. See (Verity 2011). |
31 | Fables can play with the differences in animal bodies, like in the fable ‘The Fox and the Stork’, where one animal cannot enjoy the food served by the other—the stork cannot lick the broth from the low bowl or the fox eat from the narrow-mouthed jug (Phaedrus 1.26). |
32 | The frame of the simile is the following: Achilles formerly captured two sons of King Priam, Isos, and Antiphon, when they were herding the king’s cattle on Mount Ida, but then he gave them up as a ransom. In this scene, Agamemnon kills these warrior princes like the lion kills the fawns. Hector is not there to rescue his young brothers. The absence of Hector is compared with the absence of the mother hind, but the fear of the mother hind simulates the fear of the Trojans. |
33 | |
34 | |
35 | |
36 | On wolves in ancient Greek iconography and literature, see (Calder 2011, pp. 67–69). Aelian states that wolves are extremely fierce and they might even eat one another (On the Characteristics of Animals 7.20). |
37 | In this simile, Achilles’ men, the Myrmidons, are compared to wolves, which are depicted as ‘eaters of raw flesh, whose hearts are full of unbelievable strength’. They have killed a stag and tear it apart, their muzzles are gory. After that, they go in a pack to the river to drink and have eaten so much that they ‘belch forth clots of blood’ (Iliad, 16.162). |
38 | Wolves may cache food for times when prey are scarce, but ‘surplus killing’ may happen when prey is abundant. See, for example, (Peterson and Ciucci 2003, p. 144). |
39 | Syntipas 6 (404), see (Perry 1952, p. 531). On the ideology behind hunting in antiquity, see (Barringer 2001). |
40 | On the Augustana version of this fable, see (Clayton 2008, pp. 179–80). Clayton interprets this fable to point to the difference between humans and other animals: justice does not matters to animals and the wolf enacts here ‘a parody of justice’ (Clayton 2008, p. 195). |
41 | Gibbs translates the last line as ‘Well, even if you have an endless supply of arguments, I am still going to eat you anyway!’ The elaborate epimythium of this fable states: ‘The fable shows that when someone with a wicked nature has set his mind on committing some offence, he will carry out his evil acts openly even if he cannot come up with a reasonable excuse.’ See also Perry 122, in which a cock tries to persuade humans (thieves) not to kill him. |
42 | One reason for this behaviour is that it ensures that the prey is weak enough to be killed (Fraser 2012, pp. 35–36, 57–58). |
43 | On the so-called inbreeding avoidance hypothesis, see, for instance, (Pusey and Wolf 1996, p. 202). |
44 | (Adrados 1999, pp. 174–75; Zafiropoulos 2001, pp. 125–26). Examples of these kinds of fables are ’The Kid and the Wolf’, in which a kid asks a wolf to play the flute in order that she can dance her death dance before the wolf kills her. The piping sends hounds to the spot and the kid is rescued (Perry 97). |
45 | The war between mice and weasels was the topic of animal epics and fables. See Perry 165, Syntipas 51 (see Perry 1952, p. 546) and Phaedrus 4.6. |
46 | Aristotle discusses flesh-eaters in the seventh Book of the Study of Animals using the usual word sarkophaga (zōa)—not the word zōophaga. See, for instance, 7.594b18 (lion). |
47 | (Arnott 2007, pp. 14–15) s.v. anthos. |
48 | (Arnott 2007), s.v. aigithios. The description of the anthos/aigithios and other stories of animal friendships and enmities are later copied by Pliny (Natural History 10.95) and Aelian (On the Characteristics of Animals 5.48). |
49 | Aristotle is naturally referring here to Egyptian animal cults. Although there were no animal cults in Greece, some animals were in a way protected as sacred animals to gods (like Apollo’s doves in Delphi). On gods linked to specific animals, see (Gilhus 2006, pp. 93–95). |
50 | Aristotle is here presenting the idea that the best men in the polis are outside the law, like gods. Laws are made for citizens, which are equal, but the ‘lions’ in the polis are above/below the average citizens. After that, Aristotle moves on to discuss the ostracismus, the institution which made it possible to get rid of unpopular rulers—unpopular ‘lions’. Aristotle mentions that the fable of the hares and the lions was told by Antisthenes. We may suppose that Antisthenes, the founder of the Cynic School, has told the fable in order to advocate the philosophy that ‘might makes right’. |
51 | (Steiner 2010, p. 104). Steiner also suggests that Archilochus’ fable functions as a subtext for Callimachus’ (fragmentally preserved) second Iamb (from the third century BCE), where a fox and a swan complain that Zeus’ rule is not fair—thus implying that it is not like the rule of his father Cronus, which guaranteed peace and harmony for all animals and not just for humans. (Steiner 2010, pp. 97–99, 102). |
52 | The camel asks for bull-like horns (Perry 117; Syntipas 59, see (Perry 1952, p. 549)), and in a later fable, a hare asks the supreme god for horns like those of a stag (Perry 658). See also ‘Jupiter and the Goats‘ (Phaedrus 4.17). In the Latin later fable, it is the lion as king of the animals, not Zeus or Jupiter, who dispenses justice by ordering that a wolf be hanged for eating sheep (Perry 596). |
53 | The Ryland papyrus contains remnants of a collection of fables, five in all. (Adrados 1999, pp. 54–60). |
54 | Birds detect a man sowing flax seed, and then the seed sprouts. On both occasions, the swallow warns other birds that the men would make nets by braiding flax strings, but they ignore her. Therefore, birds live in constant danger of being trapped by nets. The swallow, however, decides to leave the other birds and live close to humans. The fact that swallows live near humans is also pointed out in the fable ‘The Swallow and the Nightingale‘ (Perry 277, also told by Babrius 12): the nightingale declines the swallow‘s offer to live with humans by referring to her former tragic life as a human, a reference to the myth of Procne, Philomela, and Tereus. The swallow alludes to the same myth in ‘The Crow and the Boastful Swallow‘, by asserting that she is the daughter of the King of Athens (Perry 377). |
55 | Dio Chrysostom Discourse 12.7–10 (= Perry 437); see also Discourse 72.14–16 (= Perry 437a). See also (Adrados 1999, pp. 34–5). Translation of Dio’s text is based on J. W. Cohoon’s translation (1939). See (Cohoon 1939). |
56 | The first were Magnes’ Birds and Pherecrates’ Ant-men. Crates’ Animals (Thēria) in the 420s BCE was followed by Aristophanes’ The Birds in 410 BCE, and later Archippus’ Fishes (c. 402 BCE). On animal choruses, see (Rothwell 2007). |
57 | In Crates’ Animals, animals complain that humans eat them and in Archippus’ Fishes one fish-eating character is thrown into the sea to be eaten by fishes. (Rothwell 2007, pp. 199, 190–91). |
58 | (Korhonen 2017, pp. 144–58). The definition of empathy is Erika Ruonakoski’s (Ruonakoski 2017, p. 40). |
59 | In Greek myths, animals usually did not talk human language, but there were some humans, like the seer Teiresias, who could understand animal languages. In the Iliad, Achilles’ divine horse Xanthus is bestowed with the gift of human speech at a critical moment (Iliad 19.400–423). But it was a special occasion, a present by the goddess Hera, not an ability of this divine animal in general. Poets sometimes used a certain rhetorical device, the so-called prosopopoeia (‘making a mask’, speaking as another person), like Theognis, the lyric poet from the sixth century BCE: he has a few lines in which the lyric speaker is a mare (Theognis 257–60). |
60 | Although animals in modern animal sensitive children’s literature, like the rabbits Hazel and Fiver in Watership Down, seem to be much more humanised than the animals in ancient fables (the rabbits have names, for instance), they also preserve their animal specificity, e.g., the societal structure of rabbits. |
61 | |
62 | On the ancient ideas that the introduction of meat eating coincided with the moral decline of mankind, see, for instance, (Dombrowski 2014, pp. 536–37). |
© 2017 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Korhonen, T. A Question of Life and Death: The Aesopic Animal Fables on Why Not to Kill. Humanities 2017, 6, 29. https://doi.org/10.3390/h6020029
Korhonen T. A Question of Life and Death: The Aesopic Animal Fables on Why Not to Kill. Humanities. 2017; 6(2):29. https://doi.org/10.3390/h6020029
Chicago/Turabian StyleKorhonen, Tua. 2017. "A Question of Life and Death: The Aesopic Animal Fables on Why Not to Kill" Humanities 6, no. 2: 29. https://doi.org/10.3390/h6020029
APA StyleKorhonen, T. (2017). A Question of Life and Death: The Aesopic Animal Fables on Why Not to Kill. Humanities, 6(2), 29. https://doi.org/10.3390/h6020029