Next Article in Journal / Special Issue
Deontic Logics as Axiomatic Extensions of First-Order Predicate Logic: An Approach Inspired by Wolniewicz’s Formal Ontology of Situations
Previous Article in Journal
Corrections: Kim, T.; et al. Some Identities for Euler and Bernoulli Polynomials and Their Zeros. Axioms 2018, 7, 56
Previous Article in Special Issue
Logic of Typical and Atypical Instances of a Concept—A Mathematical Model
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

A Kotas-Style Characterisation of Minimal Discussive Logic

by
Krystyna Mruczek-Nasieniewska
*,† and
Marek Nasieniewski
*,†
Department of Logic, Nicolaus Copernicus University in Toruń, ul. Moniuszki 16/20, 87-100 Toruń, Poland
*
Authors to whom correspondence should be addressed.
These authors contributed equally to this work.
Axioms 2019, 8(4), 108; https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms8040108
Submission received: 26 August 2019 / Revised: 25 September 2019 / Accepted: 27 September 2019 / Published: 1 October 2019
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Deductive Systems in Traditional and Modern Logic)

Abstract

:
In this paper, we discuss a version of discussive logic determined by a certain variant of Jaśkowski’s original model of discussion. The obtained system can be treated as the minimal discussive logic. It is determined by frames with serial accessibility relation. As the smallest one, this logic can be treated as a basis which could be extended to richer discussive logics that are obtained by varying accessibility relation and resulting in a lattice of discussive logics. One has to remember that while formulating discussive logics there is no one-to-one determination of discussive logics by modal logics. For example, it is proved that Jaśkowski’s logic D 2 can be expressed by other than S 5 modal logics. In this paper we consider a deductive system for the sketchily described minimal logic. While formulating the deductive system, we apply a method of Kotas that was used to axiomatize D 2 . The obtained system determines a logic D 0 as a set of theses that is contained in D 2 . Moreover, any discussive logic that would be expressed by means of the provided model of discussion would contain D 0 , so it is the smallest discussive logic.

1. Introduction

Stanisław Jaśkowski’s aim was to propose a calculus that would allow for explication of inconsistent theories by means of some consistent framework. As a result Jaśkowski developed a logic denoted as D 2 that was meant to be a basis for calculus that would not lead in general to overfull set of conclusions when applied to inconsistent set of premisses. He used the scenario of a discussion as a model case. Intuitively, during discussions participants can contradict each other, but a possible external observer as well as particular participants would not conclude that everything follows from such discussion. (Some analysis on this matter can be found in [1].)
Interactions that take place between participants of a discussion are expressed formally by discussive counterparts of implication, conjunction and equivalence. Moreover, in Jaśkowski’s intuitive model, operators take only auxiliary role and modal operators are not present in the object language of the discussive logic. Such a variant seems to be natural and has been considered in [1].
Our aim is to indicate the weakest logic that arises from a natural variant of Jaśkowski model of discussion and moreover, give an adequate deductive system for such a logic.

2. D 2 and the Minimal Variant of Discussive Logic

In the original formulation, Jaśkowski considered a situation in which there is no restriction on possible reactions of participants of a discussion, in other words he considered a model, where every two participants of the discussion are connected. It corresponds to the full accessibility relation that semantically allows to determine the logic S 5 . However, it is known that not every thesis is in fact used or needed to express discussive theses. What is only used, is the so-called M-counterpart of the logic S 5 (for investigations on this notion see [2]). In various papers it has been shown (see [3,4,5,6,7]) that to be able to formulate D 2 , one can use various modal logics. (Jaśkowski’s logic was meant to be a basis for a consequence relation and also in this case there can be given other systems than S 5 which also allow to express D 2 -consequence relation (see [8]).) Moreover, one can introduce a general discussive consequence relation framework, in which D 2 would be the set of theses of one of its special cases (for details see [9]). However, this does not mean that any modal logic would be equally good to obtain D 2 .
We will keep original Jaśkowski’s meaning of discussive connectives of implication and conjunction. Jaśkowski’s discussive implication denoted here as d , is meant to be read as “if anyone states that p, then q” (see [10] p. 150, 1969), in modal terms: p q . Discussive conjunction is usually interpreted as saying “p and someone said q”, in the modal Jaśkowski’s interpretation it is read as p q . (The disjunction conjunction was introduced in the second Jaśkowski paper on discussive logic [11].) In both cases ⋄ is originally interpreted as possibility that can refer to any participant of discussion. In our interpretation it will refer only to those participants, who are connected by the accessibility relation. In particular, it means that statements of participants, who are not connected to any disputant, make the whole discussion (since we are interested in expressing what logically follows, so we ought to consider each world—or in the nomenclature of the model of the discussion—each point of view) meaningless. As Jaśkowski says, every thesis of the discussive system during its interpretation ought to be preceded by the reservation: “in accordance with the opinion of one of the participants in the discourse”, so “if a thesis is recorded in a discursive system, its intuitive sense ought to be interpreted so as if it were preceded by the symbol Pos” ([10] p. 149, 1969), which nowadays is denoted standardly by ‘⋄’. Taking into account what has been said, the minimal requirement for the considered model of discussion is that the ‘outer’ possibility ought to be ruled by a serial accessibility condition. From the formal point of view, the underlying modal logic that will be used for the formulation of the proposed variant of discussive logic, will be the deontic normal logic D. As it is known, it is semantically expressed by the class of frames with serial accessibility relation (where seriality means that for every world w there is a world v such that w R u ).
To strictly formulate the presented idea we will need two formal languages: modal and discussive.

3. Modal and Discussive Languages

Throughout the paper we will use modal formulas that are formed in the standard way from propositional letters: ‘p’, ‘q’, ‘r’, ‘s’, ‘t’, ‘ p 0 ’, ‘ p 1 ’, ‘ p 2 ’, …; truth-value operators: ‘¬’, ‘∨’, ‘∧’, ‘→’, and ‘↔’ (connectives of negation, disjunction, conjunction, material implication and material equivalence, respectively); modal operators: the necessity and possibility operators ‘□’ and ‘⋄’; and the brackets. Let For m denote the set of all modal formulas. Of course, the set For m includes the set of all classical formulas (without the use of ‘□’ and ‘⋄’), in particular the set of all classical tautologies denoted as CL. The modal language plays only an auxiliary role in the formulation of discussive logic. Its object language is built again from propositional letters, truth-value operators ‘¬’ and ‘∨’ and discussive implication ( d ), discussive conjunction ( d ) and discussive equivalence ( d ). The set of all discussive formulas is denoted by ‘ For d ’.

Basics of Normal Modal Logics

A normal modal logic is a set M For m that fulfils the following conditions:
  • C L M ,
  • M is closed under modus ponens ( mp ), uniform substitution ( us ) and necessitation rule ( rn ):
    if φ and ( φ ψ ) belong of M , so does ψ .
    if φ M then s ( φ ) M ,
    if φ M then φ M ,
  • M contains formulas ( df ) and (K)
    p ¬ ¬ p
    ( p q ) ( p q )
    As it is known, every normal modal logic contains the following formulas
    ( p q ) ( p q )
    ( p q ) ( p q )
    ( p q ) ( p q )
    D is the smallest normal logic containing (D):
    p p
Standardly, K is the smallest normal modal logic and S 5 : = K T 5 , that is, S 5 is the smallest normal modal logic containing (T) and (5), where
p p
p p

4. Discussive Logics

In the original formulation every two participants are connected one to another—in fact, for the explication of discussive implication one reads: ‘if anyone states that p’. The same idea is applied for the modality that is corresponding to possibility expressing the point of view of an external observer. Hence, Jaśkowski’s discussive logic D 2 is defined by means of S 5 as follows:
D 2 : = { A For d : i 1 ( A ) S 5 } ,
where i 1 is a translation of discussive formulas into the modal language, that is, i 1 is a function from For d into For m such that:
  • i 1 ( a ) = a , for any propositional letter a,
  • for any A , B For d :
    (a)
    i 1 ( ¬ A ) = ¬ i 1 ( A ) ,
    (b)
    i 1 ( A B ) = i 1 ( A ) i 1 ( B ) ,
    (c)
    i 1 ( A d B ) = i 1 ( A ) i 1 ( B ) ,
    (d)
    i 1 ( A d B ) = i 1 ( A ) i 1 ( B ) .
    (e)
    i 1 ( A d B ) = ( i 1 ( A ) i 1 ( B ) ) ( i 1 ( B ) i 1 ( A ) ) .
One can also consider a more general case. Let S be any normal modal logic. Now, we can define
D S : = { A For d : i 1 ( A ) S } .
We easily see that in the case where there is no formula of the form ( A ) that would belong to a given modal logic S, then we have D S = . In particular, for any modal logic S that is determined by a class of Kripke frames, whose accessibility relation does not fulfil seriality condition, we obtain D S = . (We use standard results from modal logic, for details see for example, References [12,13].) Of course, if for a given normal modal logic S, we have ( D ) S , then D S . It is known (see Reference [6]) that one can consider various accessibility relations but the resulting discussive logic would be still the same. By definition, D S 5 = D 2 . We easily see that
Fact 1.
For any modal logics S 1 and S 2 , if S 1 S 2 , then
D S 1 D S 2
By induction on the complexity of a formula φ For m , we can obtain:
Fact 2.
For every φ For m , there is A For d such that i 1 ( A ) φ K .
In this paper we focus on the case where in the condition (4), D is taken as the modal system S. We denote the resulting system as D 0 . Thus, by definition
D 0 : = { A For d : i 1 ( A ) D } .
In the context of the definition of D 0 , first, let us observe that:
Lemma 1.
For any A , A 1 , , A n For d and any variables a 1 , …, a n ,
( i 1 ( A ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , , a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) = i 1 ( A ( a 1 / A 1 , , a n / A n ) ) D .
Proof. 
The proof goes by induction on the complexity of a formula A.
For the initial case, let A = a i . We have: ( i 1 ( a i ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , …, a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) = i 1 ( A i ) = i 1 ( a i ( a 1 / A 1 , …, a n / A n ) ) . If A is a variable that does not belong to { a 1 , , a n } , we have ( i 1 ( A ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , …, a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) = A = i 1 ( A ( a 1 / A 1 , …, a n / A n ) ) .
For the inductive step assume that inductive hypothesis holds for B and C. For the case of discussive conjunction observe that the following equations hold: ( i 1 ( B d C ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , …, a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) = ( i 1 ( B ) i 1 ( C ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , …, a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) = ( i 1 ( B ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , …, a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) ( i 1 ( C ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , …, a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) . Using inductive hypothesis and features of substitution, we have ( i 1 ( B ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , …, a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) ( i 1 ( C ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , , a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) = ( i 1 ( B ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , …, a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) ( ( i 1 ( C ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , , a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) ) = i 1 ( B ( a 1 / A 1 , , a n / A n ) ) i 1 ( C ( a 1 / A 1 , …, a n / A n ) ) = i 1 ( ( B ( a 1 / A 1 , …, a n / A n ) d C ( a 1 / A 1 , , a n / A n ) ) ) = i 1 ( ( B d C ) ( a 1 / A 1 , , a n / A n ) ) .
Similarly, also the proofs for ¬, ∨, d and d are straightforward. □
Fact 3.
The set D 0 is closed under substitution and modus ponens with respect to d .
Proof. 
Let A D 0 and A B D 0 , that is i 1 ( A ) D and i 1 ( A B ) D , so ( i 1 ( A ) i 1 ( B ) ) ) D , by the distributivity of ⋄ with respect to → i 1 ( A ) i 1 ( B ) D , but by normality i 1 ( A ) D , hence i 1 ( B ) ) ) D and by definition (4), B D 0 .
Assume now that A D 0 , that is i 1 ( A ) D . Let us consider a result of uniform substitution s ( A ) into A of formulas A i for variables in A, where 1 i n , for some n, that is, s ( A ) = A ( a 1 / A 1 , , a n / A n ) , where a i are all variables in A. By Lemma 1 we know that i 1 ( s ( A ) ) = ( i 1 ( A ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , , a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) . Since D is a logic, so it is closed on substitution, so also ( i 1 ( A ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , , a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) D . But the following equations hold ( i 1 ( A ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , , a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) = ( i 1 ( A ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , , a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) ) = i 1 ( s ( A ) ) , therefore s ( A ) D 0 . □

A Comparison with Some Classical Theses

As one can easily see, none of the classical cases given below belong to D 0 , although each of these formulas belong to D 2 . To stress discussive interpretation we use the formulas from For d .
p d p p d p q p d q d p p d ( q d ( p d q ) ) ( p d ( q d r ) ) d ( ( p d q ) d ( p d r ) ) ( p d q ) d ( ( q d r ) d ( p d r ) ) ¬ ¬ p d p p d ¬ ¬ p
Each of these formulas can be rejected semantically. We use standard completeness theorem with respect to Kripke semantics for the logic D. As an example, let us consider the fifth formula, known as Frege syllogism. One can easily see that the respective translation:
( ( p ( q r ) ) ( ( p q ) ( p r ) ) )
is not a thesis of D, so the formula ( p d ( q d r ) ) d ( ( p d q ) d ( p d r ) ) does not belong to D 0 . Similarly one falsifies the other cases.

5. A Kotas Style Deductive System for the Smallest Discussive Logic

We will characterise a discussive logic being a result of the given variant of the discussive model; that is in the case that the relation is serial and no other condition is assumed as regards accessibility relation. We will give an adequacy result for the given deductive system.
We will adopt a method of Kotas (see Reference [14]) that was used for indicating the way in which D 2 could be axiomatized. (There are other axiomatisations of D 2 . In Reference [15] there is an axiomatisation of discussive logic but in a version with left discussive conjunction. For not so straight history of axiomatisation of D 2 see References [16,17].) The same method was used inter alia in Reference [1] to axiomatize a variant of D 2 with modal operators.
Let us use the following notation:
( A i ) denotes ϕ , for ( A i ) denoting ϕ
- S = { A For m : A S }
- S is called an M-counterpart of S (see Reference [5] (p. 70)). By definitions, for any normal logic S D :
S - S
It is known that (see Reference [5] (p. 68)):
Fact 4.
- D = D
Consider the following axiomatisation of CL:
p ( q p )
( p ( q r ) ) ( ( p q ) ( p r ) )
p q p
p q q
p ( q p q )
p p q
q p q
( p q ) ( ( r q ) ( p r q ) )
( p q ) ( p q )
( p q ) ( q p )
( p q ) ( ( q p ) ( p q ) )
( ¬ p ¬ q ) ( q p )
and formulas
( p ¬ ¬ p )
( ( p q ) ( p q ) )
( p p )
( p p )
( p p )
Let Ω : = { ( A i ) : 1 i 12 } { ( df ), ( K ), ( D )} and let Ω 1 : = { ( A i ) : 1 i 12 } { ( df ), ( K ), ( T ), ( 5 )}
Let us recall a theorem that allows to formulate S 5 syntactically with the use of the above mentioned formulas and rules.
Fact 5
([14]).
1. 
S 5 is the smallest set including Ω 1 and closed under ( us ) and the following rules:
φ , ( φ ψ ) ψ
φ φ
φ φ
2. 
S 5 is the smallest set including Ω 1 and closed under ( us ), ( mp ) and ( rn ).
3. 
- S 5 is the smallest set including Ω 1 and closed under ( us ), ( mp ), ( rn ), ( rn ) and ( rp ):
φ φ
But in a quite similar way, one can formulate the logic D. Let D denote the smallest set including Ω and closed under substitution, ( rn ), ( mp ), ( rp ) and ( mp )
φ , ( φ ψ ) ψ
We will follow a custom used for modal logics of calling elements of D theses of a deductive system. So D is the set of theses with respect to a deductive system ⊩ determined by the given axioms ( A i ) : 1 i 12 and rules ( rn ), ( mp ), ( mp ), ( rp ) and an substitution.
Lemma 2.
D = D .
Proof. 
We show that D D . First, by the standard formulation of D and ( rn ) we see that Ω D —it is enough to use necessitation for respective axioms of D. Besides by (8), D is closed on ( rp ). We will prove that D is closed on ( mp ). Assume that φ , ( φ ψ ) D . By ( rn ), φ D , while by (D), we have ( φ ψ ) D hence using (3) we obtain φ ψ D . Thus, by modus ponens ψ D and by (8), ψ D . The fact that D is closed on ( mp ) follows by axiom (K) and modus ponens. Finally, D is closed on ( rn ) by necessitation.
For the reverse direction let us assume that φ D . We can consider a proof φ 1 ,…, φ k = φ of φ in the standard axiomatisation of D. First observe that by ( mp ) and A i , where, 1 i 12 we obtain ψ , for any classical tautology ψ — it is enough to consider a prove of ψ and the basis of the system with { A i : 1 i 12 } as axioms, with modus ponens and substitution as rules of inference and next precede every element of the proof by □ and observe that the obtained sequence φ 1 ,…, φ k is a proof of ψ on the basis of the given system of D . Second, we see that any other axiom of D preceded by □ becomes an axiom of D ; besides, rules of ( rn ) and ( mp ) correspond respectively to necessitation and modes ponens in the original proof of φ . Hence, using induction on the length of the proof we see that φ has a mentioned proof in D . We extend the sequence φ 1 ,…, φ k = φ to infer φ . By ( D) we have ( φ φ ) and so using ( mp ) and φ we get φ , hence by ( rp ) we infer φ .
Let us finally add that both sets are closed in substitution. □
In Reference [14] two translations were considered. i 1 is a natural version of the first one adjusted to the considered here language. The translation i 2 : For m For d given below is a version of i 2 defined in Reference [14] where the case of ⋄ is added:
  • i 2 ( a ) = a , for any propositional letter a,
  • for any φ , ψ For m :
    (a)
    i 2 ( ¬ φ ) = ¬ i 2 ( φ ) ,
    (b)
    i 2 ( φ ) = ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ¬ i 2 ( φ ) ) ,
    (c)
    i 2 ( φ ) = ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( φ ) ,
    (d)
    i 2 ( φ ψ ) = i 2 ( φ ) i 2 ( ψ ) ,
    (e)
    i 2 ( φ ψ ) = ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( φ ) ¬ i 2 ( ψ ) ) ,
    (f)
    i 2 ( φ ψ ) = ¬ i 2 ( φ ) i 2 ( ψ ) ,
    (g)
    i 2 ( φ ψ ) = ¬ ( ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( φ ) i 2 ( ψ ) ) ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( ψ ) i 2 ( φ ) ) ) .
The below Lemma is being proved similarly as Lemma 4.2 in Reference [1].
Lemma 3.
For any φ For m , i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) φ D .
Proof. 
The proof goes by induction on the complexity of a given formula.
If φ is a variable, we have i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) = φ , thus the thesis holds trivially.
Assume that the inductive thesis holds for formulas simpler than a given formula. Firstly, we have i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ψ ) ) = i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) i 2 ( ψ ) ) = i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) i 1 ( i 2 ( ψ ) ) . Thus, i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ψ ) ) ( φ ψ ) D , by CL. Similarly by definition, i 1 ( i 2 ( ¬ φ ) ) = i 1 ( ¬ i 2 ( φ ) ) = ¬ i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) , so the required equivalence holds by CL.
For the case of □, we have: i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) = i 1 ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ¬ i 2 ( φ ) ) ) = ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) ) , so the required equivalence holds by normality, in particular, by CL, extensionality and due to the fact that ¬ ¬ p p K .
For the case of ‘⋄’, we have: i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) = i 1 ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( φ ) ) = ( ¬ p p ) i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) so again, the required equivalence holds by normality.
Secondly, by CL and due to the following equations and equivalences, the inductive thesis holds for ‘∧’, ‘→’ and ‘↔’.
For ‘∧’: i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ψ ) ) = i 1 ( ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( φ ) ¬ i 2 ( ψ ) ) ) = ¬ ( ¬ i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) ¬ i 1 ( i 2 ( ψ ) ) ) . But, of course, ¬ ( ¬ i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) ¬ i 1 ( i 2 ( ψ ) ) ) ( i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) i 1 ( i 2 ( ψ ) ) ) D .
For the case of ‘→’: i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ψ ) ) = i 1 ( ¬ i 2 ( φ ) i 2 ( ψ ) ) = ¬ i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) i 1 ( i 2 ( ψ ) ) . But ¬ i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) i 1 ( i 2 ( ψ ) ) i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) i 1 ( i 2 ( ψ ) ) D .
For ‘↔’: i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ψ ) ) = i 1 ( ¬ ( ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( φ ) i 2 ( ψ ) ) ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( ψ ) i 2 ( φ ) ) ) ) = ¬ ( ¬ ( ¬ i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) i 1 ( i 2 ( ψ ) ) ) ¬ ( ¬ i 1 ( i 2 ( ψ ) ) i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) ) ) . However, ¬ ( ¬ ( ¬ i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) i 1 ( i 2 ( ψ ) ) ) ¬ ( ¬ i 1 ( i 2 ( ψ ) ) i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) ) ) ( i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) i 1 ( i 2 ( ψ ) ) ) D . □
Due to Fact 4, we also have a connection similar to the relation between D 2 and - S 5 :
Lemma 4.
1. 
For any A For d : A D 0 iff i 1 ( A ) D .
2. 
For any φ D , we have i 2 ( φ ) D 0 .
3. 
If φ D and φ ψ D , then ψ D .
Proof. 
Ad 1. Let A D 0 . By the definition of D 0 it means that i 1 ( A ) D , that is, i 1 ( A ) - D . Thus, by Fact 4, i 1 ( A ) D .
If i 1 ( A ) D , then by necessitation and ( D ), i 1 ( A ) D , so A D 0 .
Ad 2. Let φ D , that is, φ D . Then, by Lemma 3 and extensionality for D, we have i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) D . Thus, i 2 ( A ) D 0 .
Point 3 is obvious. □
To make the following consideration easier to follow, for A , B For d , let us denote the formula ¬ A B as A c B , and ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ¬ A ) as d A , ( ¬ p p ) d A as d A , and d ( A c B ) ) , that is ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ¬ ( ¬ A B ) ) as A d B .
Let D 0 be the consequence relation determined by the set i 2 ( Ω ) and the following formulas:
i 2 ( i 1 ( q d r ) ) d ( q d r )
( i 2 ( i 1 ( q d r ) ) d ( q d r ) )
( i 2 ( i 1 ( q d r ) ) d ( q d r ) )
( ( q d r ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( q d r ) ) )
( ( q d r ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( q d r ) ) )
( ( q d r ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( q d r ) ) )
as axioms together with substitution and the following rules:
d A ( A d B ) d B
( d mp str ) A ( A d B ) B
d A d d A
( rp d ) d A A
The proof of the following lemma is straightforward by induction on the complexity of a modal formula φ .
Lemma 5.
Let φ, ψ 1 , …, ψ n be modal formulas and ψ be a result of substitution of ψ 1 , …, ψ n respectively for atoms a 1 , …, a n in φ. Then the formula i 2 ( ψ ) equals the result of substitution of i 2 ( ψ 1 ) , …, i 2 ( ψ n ) for atoms a 1 , …, a n in i 2 ( φ ) .
Directly from definitions and used notation, we have:
Fact 6.
For any φ, ψ For m
1. 
i 2 ( ( φ ) ) = d ( i 2 ( φ ) ) ,
2. 
i 2 ( ( φ ) ) = d ( i 2 ( φ ) ) ,
3. 
i 2 ( ( φ ψ ) ) = i 2 ( φ ) d i 2 ( ψ ) .
Lemma 6.
1. 
For any φ CL , we have D 0 d i 2 ( φ ) .
2. 
For any φ D , we have D 0 i 2 ( φ ) .
Proof. 
Ad 1. Assume that φ CL . Then there is a proof χ 1 , …, χ n , of φ = χ n on the basis of (A1)–(A12), ( mp ) and substitution. Consider the sequence d i 2 ( χ 1 ) , …, d i 2 ( χ n ) . By induction on the length of the sequence one can see that it is a proof on the basis of D 0 , since its elements are either elements of i 2 ( Ω ) or arise by the application of ( d mp str ) or substitution. For the case of substitution it is enough to use Lemma 5 and apply the substitution of i 2 ( ψ 1 ) , …, i 2 ( ψ m ) for a 1 , …, a m in d i 2 ( χ i ) , if in the initial proof a substitution of formulas ψ 1 , …, ψ m for atoms a 1 , …, a m in χ i was applied.
Ad 2. Assume that φ D . Then there is a proof χ 1 , …, χ n of φ , in the sense of the consequence relation ⊩. Consider i 2 ( χ 1 ) , …, i 2 ( χ n ) , ( d i 2 ( χ n ) d d i 2 ( χ n ) ) , d i 2 ( χ n ) , i 2 ( χ n ) = i 2 ( φ ) . By induction on 1 i n , by the point 1 of this lemma and Fact 6, we can easily show that D 0 i 2 ( χ i ) , that is, D 0 d i 2 ( χ i ) , while ( d i 2 ( χ n ) d d i 2 ( χ n ) ) is an instance of i 2 ( D ), d i 2 ( χ n ) follows from i 2 ( χ n ) and ( d i 2 ( χ n ) d d i 2 ( χ n ) ) by ( d mp str ); and i 2 ( φ ) follows from d i 2 ( χ n ) by ( rp d ). □
Thus, we obtain that:
Fact 7.
The following formulas are theses with respect to D 0 :
( i 2 ( i 1 ( ¬ p ) ) d ¬ p )
( i 2 ( i 1 ( p q ) ) d p q )
Proof. 
For (9), observe that ( i 2 ( i 1 ( ¬ p ) ) d ¬ p ) = d ( i 2 ( i 1 ( ¬ p ) ) c ¬ p ) = d ( ¬ p c ¬ p ) = d i 2 ( ¬ p c ¬ p ) . So (9) follows by Lemma 6.1.
For (10), one can see that ( i 2 ( i 1 ( p q ) ) d p q ) = d ( i 2 ( i 1 ( p ) i 1 ( q ) ) c p q ) = d ( i 2 ( i 1 ( p ) ) i 2 ( i 1 ( q ) ) c p q ) = d ( p q c p q ) . So again, the condition is obtained by Lemma 6.1. □
The above fact can be extended for the case of any formulas used instead of p and q. Moreover, it can be generalised to any compound formula which results in the below Lemma. Its proof goes similarly as the proof of Reference [1] (Fact 4.6). However, there are essential changes for the case of discussive operators, so we present it for the sake of completeness of considerations.
Fact 8.
For any A For d ,
D 0 d ( i 2 ( i 1 ( A ) ) c A )
D 0 d ( A c i 2 ( i 1 ( A ) ) ) .
Proof. 
The proof goes simultaneously for both theses by induction on the complexity of a formula A. The case of atoms follows by Lemma 6.1.
Assume that the inductive hypothesis holds for any formula of complexity smaller than the complexity of A. That is, for the following cases A = ¬ B , A = B C , A = B d C , A = B d C and A = B d C , where B , C For d we assume that:
D 0 ( i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) d B ) , D 0 ( i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) d C ) , D 0 ( B d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) , D 0 ( C d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) .
in other words
D 0 d ( i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) c B ) ,
D 0 d ( i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) c C ) ,
D 0 d ( B c i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) ,
D 0 d ( C c i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) .
For the case of ‘¬’ let us notice that D 0 d i 2 ( p q ) ( ¬ q ¬ p ) , by Lemma 6(1), that is, D 0 ( ( p c q ) d ( ¬ q c ¬ p ) ) . So, since ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) = i 2 ( i 1 ( ¬ B ) ) , using the substitution p / B , q / i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) , (15) and ( d mp str ), we get:
D 0 d ( i 2 ( i 1 ( ¬ B ) ) c ¬ B ) .
Similarly, using the substitution p / i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) , q / B , (13) and ( d mp str ) we obtain:
D 0 d ( ¬ B c i 2 ( i 1 ( ¬ B ) ) ) .
For the case of ‘∨’ notice that D 0 d ( i 2 ( p q ) ( r s ) ( ( p r ) ( q s ) ) ) , by Lemma 6(1), that is, D 0 d ( ( p c q ) c ( ( r c s ) c ( ( p r ) c ( q s ) ) ) ) or equivalently
( p c q ) d ( ( r c s ) c ( ( p r ) c ( q s ) ) )
is a thesis with respect to D 0 . Thus, since i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) = i 2 ( i 1 ( B C ) ) , using the substitution p / i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) , q / B , r / i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) , s / C into (17), by (13) and ( d mp str ), we get:
D 0 d ( ( i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) c C ) c ( ( i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) c ( B C ) ) )
that is,
D 0 ( i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) c C ) d ( ( i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) c ( B C ) )
And again, by (14) and ( d mp str ), we obtain:
D 0 d i 2 ( i 1 ( B C ) ) c ( B C ) .
Similarly, using the substitution p / B , q / i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) , r / C , s / i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) , to (17), we obtain:
( B c i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) d d ( ( C c i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) c ( ( B C ) c ( i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ) )
hence, by (15) and ( d mp str ), and again by (16) and ( d mp str ) we get:
D 0 d ( B C ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( B C ) ) .
For the case of ‘ d ’ first let us observe that
i 2 ( i 1 ( B d C ) ) = i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) i 1 ( C ) ) =
¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) = ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ) .
Hence by (B1) and definitions of i 1 and i 2 we get D 0 ¬ ( ¬ q ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d r ) ) d ( q d r ) . While by (C1), similarly we obtain: D 0 ( q d r ) d ¬ ( ¬ q ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d r ) ) . Therefore, by substitution we obtain
D 0 ¬ ( ¬ B ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d C ) ) d ( B d C )
and
D 0 ( B d C ) d ¬ ( ¬ B ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d C ) )
Notice that ( ( t q ) ( ( r s ) ( t r q s ) ) ) D , so by Lemma 6(2) and Fact 6, D 0 d ( i 2 ( ( p q ) ( ( r s ) ( t r q s ) ) ) ) , that is,
D 0 ( t c q ) d ( ( r d s ) c ( ¬ ( ¬ t ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d r ) ) c ¬ ( ¬ q ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d s ) ) ) ) .
By substitution: t / i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) , q / B , r / i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) , s / C , (13) and ( d mp str ), we get:
d ( ( i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) d C ) c ( ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ) c ¬ ( ¬ B ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d C ) ) ) )
But by ( d rn ) applied to (14) we have
D 0 d ( i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) d C )
Therefore, again by ( d mp str ):
d ( ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ) c ¬ ( ¬ B ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d C ) ) )
But by Lemma 6(1) we have
D 0 ( p c q ) d ( ( q c r ) c ( p c r ) ) ,
so by substitution p / ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ) , q / ¬ ( ¬ B ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d C ) ) and r / ( B d C ) , using ( d mp str ) we obtain:
d ( ( ¬ ( ¬ B ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d C ) ) c ( B d C ) ) c ( ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ) c ( B d C ) ) )
that is,
( ¬ ( ¬ B ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d C ) ) c ( B d C ) ) d ( ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ) c ( B d C ) )
Thus, from (19) using ( d mp str ) we infer
d ( ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ) c ( B d C ) )
what is the required formula due to the observation (18).
For the reverse implication, using (21) but substituting t / B , q / i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) , r / C , s / i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) and next appyling (15) and ( d mp str ) we infer
d ( ( C d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) c ( ¬ ( ¬ B ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d C ) ) c ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ) ) )
While applying ( d rn ) for (16) we obtain
D 0 d ( C d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) )
Thus, by ( d mp str ):
d ( ¬ ( ¬ B ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d C ) ) c ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ) )
Using an instance of (22), where p / ( B d C ) , q / ¬ ( ¬ B ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d C ) ) and r / ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ) , by (20) and ( d mp str ), and then thanks to the above formula and again ( d mp str ) we obtain
d ( ( B d C ) c ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ) )
which is the required formula by the observation (18).
The case of ‘ d ’. By definitions, we have:
i 2 ( i 1 ( B d C ) ) = i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) i 1 ( C ) ) = ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) )
Thus, by (B2) and (C2) we have
¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d q ) r d ( q d r ) )
( q d r ) d ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d q ) r
So by substitution we have
¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d B ) C d ( B d C ) )
( B d C ) d ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d B ) C
Let us notice that ( ( q r ) ( q r ) ) K D . Hence, by Lemma 6(2): D 0 i 2 ( ( ( q r ) ( q r ) ) ) , that is, by definition of i 2 and by Fact 6:
D 0 d ( d d ( q c r ) c d ( d q c d r ) ) .
or equivalently
D 0 d d ( q c r ) d d ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d q ) c ( ( ¬ p p ) d r ) ) .
so by substitution q / B , r / i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) , we obtain that
d d ( B c i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) d d ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d B ) c ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) ) .
is a thesis of D 0 . Applying ( d rn ) to (15) we get d d ( B c i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) , hence by ( d mp str ) we infer
d ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d B ) c ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) ) .
By a substitution q / C , r / i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) in (26) and by ( d rn ) applied for (16) instead of (15) and finally by ( d mp str ) we obtain:
d ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d C ) c ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ) .
As one can see, ( ( q t ) ( ( r s ) ( ( t r ) ( q s ) ) ) ) K D . Hence by Lemma 6(2) we obtain
( ( ( ¬ p p ) d q ) c ( ( ¬ p p ) d t ) ) d ( ( r c s ) c ( ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d t ) c r ) c ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d q ) c s ) ) )
Now, we use the substitution: q / B , t / i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) , r / i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) , s / C and applying ( d mp str ) to (5) we infer
( i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) c C ) d ( ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) c ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d B ) c C ) )
and next by ( d mp str ) applied to (14) we have
( ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) d ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d B ) c C )
But by (23) it means that
D 0 i 2 ( i 1 ( B d C ) ) d ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d B ) c C )
Now, we use (22), (24) and the above formula and act similarly as in the case of ‘ d ’, we conclude that:
D 0 i 2 ( i 1 ( B d C ) ) d ( B d C ) .
For the reverse implication we apply the following substitution to (29): q / i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) , t / B , r / C , s / i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) and we receive:
( ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) c ( ¬ p p ) d B ) ) d d ( ( C c i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) c ( ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d B ) c C ) c ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ) )
Similarly as (5) we obtain d ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) c ( ( ¬ p p ) d B ) ) . Hence, applying ( d mp str ) to (31) we infer
( C c i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) d ( ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d B ) c C ) c ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) )
So again by ( d mp str ) and (16) we obtain
( ( ( ¬ p p ) d B ) c C ) d ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) )
So acting as previously, by (22), (25), (23) and ( d mp str ) we obtain
D 0 d ( B d C ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( B d C ) ) .
For the case of ‘ d ’ notice that by Lemma 6(1), D 0 d ( i 2 ( ( p q ) ( ( q p ) ( p q ) ) ) ) , that is, D 0 d ( ( p c q ) c ( ( q c p ) c ¬ ( ¬ ( p c q ) ¬ ( q c p ) ) ) ) . Thus, by substitutions, inductive hypotheses (13), (14), (15), (16) and applying ( d mp str ) and definition of i 2 we get:
d ¬ ( ¬ ( B c i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) ¬ ( i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) c B ) )
d ¬ ( ¬ ( C c i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ¬ ( i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) c C ) )
Hence, by the use of the following thesis of K D :
( ( r s ) ( ( t q ) ( ( r s ) ( ( ( q s ) ( s q ) ) ( ( t r ) ( r t ) ) ) ) ) ) ,
by Lemma 6(2), Fact 6, (33), ( d mp str ) and substitution r / C , s / i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) , t / B , q / i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) we get:
d ( d ¬ ( ¬ ( B c i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) ¬ ( i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) c B ) ) c ( d d ¬ ( ¬ ( ¬ C i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) C ) ) c ( ¬ ( ( ¬ d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ¬ d ( d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) ) c ¬ ( ¬ ( d B c C ) ¬ d ( d C c B ) ) ) ) )
By the result of application of ( d rn ) to (33) and again ( d mp str ) we infer
d ( d d ¬ ( ¬ ( ¬ C i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ¬ ( ¬ i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) C ) ) c ( ¬ ( ( ¬ d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ¬ d ( d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) ) c ¬ ( ¬ ( d B c C ) ¬ d ( d C c B ) ) ) )
Now we twice apply ( d rn ) to (33) and again use ( d mp str ), as a result we get:
d ( ¬ ( ¬ ( d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ¬ d ( d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) ) c ¬ ( ¬ ( d B c C ) ¬ d ( d C c B ) ) ) .
Thus, since by definitions of the functions i 1 and i 2 , ¬ ( ¬ ( d i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) ) ¬ d ( d i 2 ( i 1 ( C ) ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( B ) ) ) ) = i 2 ( ( i 1 ( B ) i 1 ( C ) ) ( i 1 ( C ) i 1 ( B ) ) ) = i 2 ( i 1 ( B d C ) ) , we get:
d ( i 2 ( i 1 ( B d C ) ) c ¬ ( ¬ ( d B c C ) ¬ d ( d C c B ) ) ) .
From axiom (B3) we obtain:
d ( ¬ ( ¬ ( d B c C ) ¬ d ( d C c B ) ) c ( B d C ) ) .
Thus, again by a substitution to i 2 ( ( p q ) ( q r ) ( p r ) ) and the application of ( d mp str ), we get:
D 0 d i 2 ( i 1 ( B d C ) ) c ( B d C ) .
Similarly we show:
D 0 d ( B d C ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( B d C ) ) .
By induction on the complexity of formulas, we obtain (11) and (12). □
Theorem 1.
The set of theses with respect to the consequence relation D 0 equals D 0 .
Proof. 
Let A D 0 . By Lemma 4, i 1 ( A ) D . Thus, by Lemma 2, there is a proof χ 1 , …, χ n = i 1 ( A ) such that for each i { 1 , , n } , χ i is one of the formulas ( A1)–( A12), ( df⋄), ( D), ( K) or χ i is a result of the application of substitution, ( rn ), ( mp ), ( mp ), ( rp ), for some formulas preceding χ i in the sequence. Let us consider the following sequence of formulas i 2 ( χ 1 ) , …, i 2 ( χ n 1 ) , i 2 ( i 1 ( A ) ) , d ( i 2 ( i 1 ( A ) ) c A ) , A. By induction on i we see that the fragment of the sequence i 2 ( χ 1 ) , …, i 2 ( χ n ) = i 2 ( i 1 ( A ) ) is a proof in the given axiomatic system, while the formula d ( i 2 ( i 1 ( A ) ) c A ) is a thesis of the system, by Fact 8. So the formula A completes the proof as a result of application of the rule ( d mp str ) to two preceding formulas. Thus, D 0 A
Now, for the reverse direction, assume that for a given formula A there is a proof C 1 , …, C n = A of the formula A within the considered deductive system. By the definition of D 0 , it is enough to prove that for any i { 1 , , n } , i 1 ( C i ) D or, equivalently, i 1 ( C i ) D .
Firstly, let us consider the case of axioms. Suppose that C i i 2 ( Ω ) . For the case ( A1)–( A12) that is, when C i = i 2 ( φ ) , for some φ CL D —it is enough to apply Lemma 6(2). Then i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) φ D , by Lemma 3. Therefore, by Lemma 4(3), i 1 ( i 2 ( φ ) ) = i 1 ( C i ) D . In the case of other axioms from the set i 2 ( Ω ) , we act similarly.
Ad(B1): i 1 ( d ( i 2 ( i 1 ( q d r ) ) c ( q d r ) ) ) = i 1 ( d ( i 2 ( q r ) c ( q d r ) ) ) = i 1 ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ¬ ( ¬ ( ¬ q ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d r ) ) c ( q d r ) ) ) ) = ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ ( ¬ ( ¬ q ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) r ) ) c ( q r ) ) ) . But ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ ( ¬ ( ¬ q ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) r ) ) c ( q r ) ) ) ( ( q r ) c ( q r ) ) belongs to D. Thus, (B1) D 0 , thanks to Lemma 4.
Ad (B2): i 1 ( d ( i 2 ( i 1 ( q d r ) ) c ( q d r ) ) ) = i 1 ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ¬ ( ( ( ¬ p p ) d q c r ) c ( q d r ) ) ) ) = ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ ( ( ( ¬ p p ) q c r ) c ( q r ) ) ) . However, ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ ( ( ( ¬ p p ) q c r ) c ( q r ) ) ) ( ( q c r ) c ( q r ) ) is a thesis of D. Thus, (B2) D 0 , by Lemma 4.
Ad (B3): i 1 ( d ( i 2 ( i 1 ( q d r ) ) c ( q d r ) ) ) = i 1 ( d ( i 2 ( ( q r ) ( r q ) ) c ( q d r ) ) ) = i 1 ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ¬ ( ¬ ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d q c r ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ( ( ¬ p p ) d r c q ) ) ) c ( q d r ) ) ) ) = ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ ( ¬ ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) q c r ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ( ( ¬ p p ) r c q ) ) ) c ( ( q r ) ( r q ) ) ) ) . Notice that ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ ( ¬ ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) q c r ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ( ( ¬ p p ) r c q ) ) ) c ( ( q r ) ( r q ) ) ) ) ( ( q c r ) ( r c q ) c ( ( q r ) ( r q ) ) ) . Thus, (B3) belongs to D 0 , similarly, by Lemma 4.
Ad (C1): i 1 ( d ( ( q d r ) c i 2 ( i 1 ( q d r ) ) ) ) = ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ ( ( q r ) c ¬ ( ¬ q ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) r ) ) ) ) . Thus again, (C1) D 0 .
Ad (C2): i 1 ( ( q d r ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( q d r ) ) ) = ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ ( ( q r ) c ( ( ¬ p p ) q c r ) ) ) . Hence (C2) D 0 .
Ad (C3): i 1 ( ( q d r ) d i 2 ( i 1 ( q d r ) ) ) = ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ ( ( ( q r ) ( r q ) ) c ¬ ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) q c r ) ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ( ( ¬ p p ) r c q ) ) ) ) ) . As one can see (C3) D 0 .
Ad ( d mp str ). Assume that d A and d ( A c B ) belong to D 0 , that is, i 1 ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ¬ A ) ) and i 1 ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ¬ ( A c B ) ) ) are theses of D. By Fact 4 equivalently, ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ i 1 ( A ) ) ) D and ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ ( i 1 ( A ) c i 1 ( B ) ) ) ) D , in other words i 1 ( A ) D and ( i 1 ( A ) c i 1 ( B ) ) D , hence of course i 1 ( B ) D . Equivalently, ¬ ¬ i 1 ( B ) D and ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ i 1 ( B ) ) D , but by definition of i 1 , ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ i 1 ( B ) ) = i 1 ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ¬ B ) , hence also i 1 ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ¬ B ) ) D , therefore d B D 0 .
Ad ( d mp str ). Suppose that A and d ( A c B ) belong to D 0 , that is, i 1 ( A ) and i 1 ( d ( A c B ) ) belong to D; and so ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ ( ¬ i 1 ( A ) i 1 ( B ) ) ) ) D . Therefore, ( i 1 ( A ) i 1 ( B ) ) D and by Fact 4: ( i 1 ( A ) i 1 ( B ) ) D . Hence i 1 ( B ) D , so B D 0 . by definition of D.
Ad ( d rn ): Let d A D 0 , that is, i 1 ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ¬ A ) ) D ; and in other words ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ i 1 ( A ) ) ) D . But this means that i 1 ( A ) D and by Fact 4, also i 1 ( A ) D . Hence by necessitation i 1 ( A ) D , so again by necessitation and (D) also i 1 ( A ) D . Equivalently, ¬ ¬ ¬ ¬ i 1 ( A ) D . This can be rewritten as ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) ¬ i 1 ( A ) ) ) D . That is i 1 ( ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ¬ ¬ ( ( ¬ p p ) d ¬ A ) ) ) D . Hence i 1 ( d d A ) D , that is, d d A D 0 .
Ad ( rp d ): Let d A D 0 , that is, i 1 ( ( ¬ p p ) d A ) D , equivalently ( ¬ p p ) i 1 ( A ) D ,; and so i 1 ( A ) D . Then by Fact 4, also i 1 ( A ) D ; and so A D 0 .
Finally, we consider the case of substitution. Assume that A belongs to D 0 , that is, i 1 ( A ) is a thesis of D. Now, let us consider a substitution of formulas A 1 ,…, A n for variables a 1 ,…, a n in A. Let us also consider i 1 ( A ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) , …, a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) the result of substitution of i 1 ( A 1 ) ,…, i n / A n for variables a 1 ,…, a n in i 1 ( A ) . By Lemma 1 the following holds: ( i 1 ( A ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) ,…, a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) = i 1 ( A ( a 1 / A 1 ,…, a n / A n ) ) . Since D as a modal logic is closed on substitution, ( i 1 ( A ) ) ( a 1 / A 1 ,…, a n / A n ) D , but by the last equation and the features of substitution, ( i 1 ( A ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) ,…, a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) = ( ( i 1 ( A ) ) ( a 1 / i 1 ( A 1 ) ,…, a n / i 1 ( A n ) ) ) = i 1 ( A ( a 1 / A 1 ,…, a n / A n ) ) . By definition of D 0 , it means that A ( a 1 / A 1 ,…, a n / A n ) D 0 . □

6. Conclusions

We gave a syntactic characterisation of the minimal discussive logic. This is as an initial step in our investigations on other variants of discussive logics obtained by other cases of relations that connect participants of a discussion.

Author Contributions

Conceptualization, K.M.-N. and M.N.; formal analysis, K.M.-N. and M.N.; investigation, K.M.-N. and M.N.; methodology, K.M.-N.; validation, K.M.-N.; writing—original draft preparation, K.M.-N. and M.N.; writing—review and editing, K.M.-N. and M.N.; supervision, M.N.; funding acquisition, M.N.

Funding

The authors of this work benefited from support provided by Polish National Science Centre (Narodowe Centrum Nauki), grant number 2016/23/B/HS1/00344.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Mruczek-Nasieniewska, K.; Nasieniewski, M.; Pietruszczak, A. A modal extension of Jaśkowski’s discussive logic D2. Log. J. IGPL 2019, 27, 451–477. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Błaszczuk, J.J.; Dziobiak, W. An axiomatization of Mn-counterparts for some modal logics. Reports Math. Log. 1976, 6, 3–6. [Google Scholar]
  3. Furmanowski, T. Remarks on discussive propositional calculus. Studia Log. 1975, 34, 39–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  4. Błaszczuk, J.J.; Dziobiak, W. Remarks on Perzanowski’s modal system. Bull. Sect. Log. 1975, 4, 57–64. [Google Scholar]
  5. Perzanowski, J. On M-fragments and L-fragments of normal modal propositional logics. Rep. Math. Log. 1975, 5, 63–72. [Google Scholar]
  6. Nasieniewski, M.; Pietruszczak, A. A method of generating modal logics defining Jaśkowski’s discussive logic D2. Studia Logica 2011, 97, 161–182. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  7. Nasieniewski, M.; Pietruszczak, A. On the weakest modal logics defining Jaśkowski’s logic D2 and the D2-consequence. Bull. Sect. Log. 2012, 41, 215–232. [Google Scholar]
  8. Nasieniewski, M.; Pietruszczak, A. A method of generating modal logics defining Jaśkowski’s discussive D2-consequence. In Logic, Reasoning & Rationality; Weber, E., Wouters, D., Meheus, J., Eds.; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2014; Volume 5, pp. 95–123. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Urchs, M. On the role of adjunction in para(in)consistent logic. In Paraconsistency: The Logical Way to the Inconsistent, Proceedings of the Second World Congress on Paraconsistency, São Paulo, Brazil, May 12–19, 2000; Carnielli, W.A., Coniglio, M.E., Loffredo D’Ottaviano, I.M., Eds.; Marcel Dekker: New York, NY, USA, 2002; pp. 487–499. [Google Scholar]
  10. Jaśkowski, S. Rachunek zdań dla systemów dedukcyjnych sprzecznych. Studia Societatis Scientiarum Torunensis 1948, 1, 57–77, (In English: Propositional calculus for contradictory deductive systems. Studia Logica 1969, 24, 143–157, doi:10.1007/BF02134311. A propositional Calculus for inconsistent deductive systems. Log. Log. Philos. 1999, 7, 35–56, doi:10.12775/LLP.1999.003.). [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Jaśkowski, S. O koniunkcji dyskusyjnej w rachunku zdań dla systemów dedukcyjnych sprzecznych. Studia Societatis Scientiarum Torunensis 1949, 1, 171–172, In English: On the discussive conjunction in the propositional calculus for inconsistent deductive systems. Log. Log. Philos. 1999, 7, 57–59, doi:10.12775/LLP.1999.004.). [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Bull, R.A.; Segerberg, K. Basic Modal Logic. In Handbook of Philosophical Logic; Gabbay, D.M., Guenthner, F., Eds.; D. Reidel Publishing Company: Dordrecht, Holland, 1984; Volume 3, pp. 1–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  13. Segerberg, K. An Essay in Classical Modal Logic; Uppsala Universitet: Uppsala, Sweded, 1971; Volume 1–2. [Google Scholar]
  14. Kotas, J. The axiomatization of S. Jaśkowski’s discussive system. Studia Logica 1974, 33, 195–200. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  15. da Costa, N.C.A.; Dubikajtis, L. On Jaśkowski discussive logic. In Non-Classical Logics, Model Theory and Computability; Arruda, A.I., da Costa, N.C.A., Chuaqui, R., Eds.; North-Holland: New York, NY, USA, 1977; pp. 37–56. [Google Scholar]
  16. Ciuciura, J. A new real axiomatization of the discursive logic D2. In Handbook of Paraconsistency; Beziau, J.Y., Carnielli, W., Gabbay, D.M., Eds.; College Publications: London, UK, 2007; pp. 427–437. [Google Scholar]
  17. Omori, H.; Alama, J. Axiomatizing Jaśkowski’s Discussive Logic D2. Studia Logica 2018, 106, 1163–1180. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Mruczek-Nasieniewska, K.; Nasieniewski, M. A Kotas-Style Characterisation of Minimal Discussive Logic. Axioms 2019, 8, 108. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms8040108

AMA Style

Mruczek-Nasieniewska K, Nasieniewski M. A Kotas-Style Characterisation of Minimal Discussive Logic. Axioms. 2019; 8(4):108. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms8040108

Chicago/Turabian Style

Mruczek-Nasieniewska, Krystyna, and Marek Nasieniewski. 2019. "A Kotas-Style Characterisation of Minimal Discussive Logic" Axioms 8, no. 4: 108. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms8040108

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop