The Calculus of Names—The Legacy of Jan Łukasiewicz
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Logic of Names and Traditional Logic
2.1. The Logic of Names
• | Every S is a P | (universal affirmative) |
• | Some S is a P | (particular affirmative) |
• | No S is a P | (universal denial) |
• | Some S is not a P | (particular denial) |
- ‘Every S is a P’ is true if and only if the extension of the name S is included in the extension of the name P;
- ‘Some S is a P’ is true if and only if the names S and P have a common referent;
- ‘No S is a P’ is true if and only if the extensions of the names S and P are disjoint;
- ‘Some S is not a P’ is true if and only if the name S has a referent that is not a referent of the name P.
2.2. Traditional Logic
• | Every S is a P ∴ Some S is a P | subalternation |
• | Every S is a P ∴ Some P is an S | conversion per accidens |
• | No S is a P ∴ Some S is not a P | subalternation |
• | No S is a P ∴ Some P is not an S | conversion per accidens |
• | Every S is a P ∴ It is not the case that no S is a P | contrariety |
• | It is not the case that some S is a P ∴ Some S is a P | subcontrariety |
• | Every M is a P, Every S is a M ∴ Some S is a P | Barbari |
• | Every M is a P, Every M is a S ∴ Some S is a P | Darapti |
• | Every P is a M, Every M is a S ∴ Some S is a P | Bamalip |
• | No M is a P, Every S is a M ∴ Some S is not a P | Celaront |
• | No P is a M, Every S is a M ∴ Some S is not a P | Cesaro |
• | Every P is a M, No S is a M ∴ Some S is not a P | Camestros |
• | Every P is a M, No M is a S ∴ Some S is not a P | Calemos |
• | No M is a P, Every M is a S ∴ Some S is not a P | Felapton |
• | No P is a M, Every M is a S ∴ Some S is not a P | Fesapo |
2.3. A Contemporary Approach to the Logic of Names
- Can the meaning of categorical sentences be changed to preserve the validity of argument forms of traditional logic, even when substituting empty names is allowed?
- When terms are limited to non-empty terms, it coincides with natural usage.
- A universal affirmative sentence (in the strong interpretation) is true if and only if it has a non-empty name in the subject, the extension of which is included in the extension of the name from the predicate.
- ‘Some S is not a P’ is not a contradiction of ‘Every S is a P’ and vice versa.
- ‘Some S is not a P’ is a contradiction of ‘All S is a P’ and vice versa.
- A universal denial sentence (in the strong interpretation) is true if and only if it has a non-empty name in the subject whose extension is disjoint with the extension of the name of the predicate.
- A universal denial sentence (in the super-strong interpretation) is true if and only if it has non-empty names in both the subject and the predicate, the extensions of which are disjoint.
3. Calculus of Names as an Extension of Traditional Logic
3.1. The Genesis of the Calculus of Names
5. A fundamental difference exists between a logical thesis and a rule of inference.
A logical thesis is a sentence in which, apart from logical constants, there are only sentence or name variables, which is true for all values of the variables that occur in it. An inference rule is a prescription that authorises a person which make inferences to derive new theses based on recognised theses. For example, […] the principles of identity [such as “If p, then p” and “Every a is an a”] are logical theses, but the rule of inference is the following «rule of detachment»:
Whoever accepts as true the implication “If , then ” and the antecedent of this implication “” has the right to accept as true also the consequent of this implication “”.
- If, with a given admissible substitution for variables (schematic letters), the schemes ‘If , then ’ and give true sentences, then, with this substitution, we also have a true sentence obtained from the schema .
- If the formulas ‘If , then ’ and are logically valid (i.e., they give true sentences under any admissible substitution for variables), then is also logically valid.
6. The original Aristotelian syllogism is a logical thesis, the traditional syllogism has the meaning of a rule of inference.
The Barbara mode given [below], […], is an implication of the type “If and , then ”, […]. As an implication, an Aristotelian syllogism is a proposition that Aristotle holds to be true, namely that the proposition is true for all values of the variables “a”, “b” and “c” that occur in it. Therefore, we get true sentences if we substitute some constant values for these variables. Since in the considered mode, apart from variables, there are only logical constants, namely “if-then”, “and” and “every-is”, the Aristotelian syllogism is a logical thesis.
The traditional syllogism:is not an implication. It consists of three sentence forms, listed one under the other, which do not form a single sentence. Since a traditional syllogism is not a proposition, it cannot be true or false either since, according to the generally accepted view, truth and falsity belong only to propositions. A traditional syllogism is, therefore, not a thesis. If we substitute some constant values for the variables in this syllogism, we do not get a proposition but an argument form. So a traditional syllogism is an argument schema and has the meaning of a rule of inference, which can be more precisely expressed as follows:
Whoever accepts as true premises of the form “Every b is an a” and “Every c is a b” has the right to accept as true a conclusion of the form “Every c is an a”. (Footnote 11 added: “How imprecise the historical studies of logic to date are is evidenced by this very characteristic detail: all the authors I know who have written about Aristotelian logic, […], present Aristotelian syllogisms in the traditional form, without even realising the fundamental difference between these forms.”)
7. Thanks to the distinction between logical theses and rules of inference, it became possible for logical sciences to construct axiomatically in the form of deductive systems.
3.2. Łukasiewicz’s Calculus of Names
8. The theory of the Aristotelian syllogism, which Aristotle has already tried to axiomatise, but which has not yet been presented in an axiomatic form, is based on two fundamental concepts: “Every a is a b”, in the signs “”, and “Some a is a b”, in the signs “” and on the following axioms:
Every a is an a. Some a jest an a. If every b is an a and every c is a b, then every c is an a. If every b is an a and some b is a c, then some c is an a.
In the signs (the functors “U” and “I” come before the arguments, and such same the conjunction sign “K” = “and”):
. . (Barbara). (Datisi).
The expressions “Some a is not a b”, in the signs “”, and “No a is a b”, in the signs “”, can be defined as follows (Łukasiewicz used his bracketless notation here. In [4] ‘U’ and ‘Y’ were replaced by ‘A’ and ‘E’, respectively):
Df1. .
Df2. .
By both rules of substitution and detachment (propositional variables may be substituted with propositional forms of Aristotelian logic, for name variables only other name variables), and with the help of theses of propositional logic, from these axioms and definitions, we can derive all 24 (not 14 nor 19!) the correct modes of Aristotelian syllogistic. (Footnote 14 added: “The axiomatisation of Aristotelian syllogistic presented here, as well as the deduction of all modes, can be found in the script from my lectures, delivered in the autumn trimester of 1928/29 at the University of Warsaw, entitled: Elementy logiki matematycznej […]” [1]).
—for ‘Every S is a P’ |
—for ‘Some S is a P’ |
—for ‘No S is a P’ |
—for ‘Some S is not a P’ |
- all atomic formulas belong to X,
- if and , then and .
conversion, by (I) and (Datisi) | ||
conversion, by (C) and (df ) | ||
subalternation, by (I) and (Datisi) | ||
conversion per accidens, by (S) and (C) | ||
subalternation, by (S), (df ) and (df o) | ||
conversion per accidens, by (S) and (C) | ||
contrariety, by (S) and (df ) | ||
subcontrariety, by (S) and (df o) | ||
(Barbari) | by (Barbara) and (S) | |
(Darapti) | by (Datisi) and (S) | |
(Bamalip) | by (Barbara), (S) and (C) | |
(Camestros) | by (Barbari), (df ) and (df o) | |
(Calemos) | by (Camestros) and (C) | |
Felapton) | by (Barbari), (df ) and (df o) | |
(Fesapo) | by (Felapton) and (C) | |
(Celaront) | by (Darapti), (df ) and (df o) | |
(Cesaro) | by (Celaront) and (C) |
3.3. Set-Theoretic Semantics for Łukasiewicz’s Calculus
- Traditional models. In the semantic study of Ł, from a formal point of view, instead of speaking of substitutions of general names for name letters, for ForŁ, it is better to use set-theoretic semantics, which use traditional models of the form , where
- is a non-empty set (universe),
- is a function of denotation, which assigns to any name letter a non-empty subset of . (Like Corcoran [6] (p. 103), we could assume that the model (interpretation) is just the mapping itself, which assigns to any name letter a non-empty set.)
- is true in iff the set is included in the set ;
- is true in iff the sets and have a common element;
- is true in iff the sets and have no elements in common;
- is true in iff has an element which is not an element of .
- Set-theoretic tautologies vs. lexical tautologies. Since, to each general name, we can assign a set that is its extension, every set-theoretic tautology is also a lexical tautology. On the other hand, if every set was an extension of some name, then without any additional conditions, it could be proved that the opposite holds, i.e., that every lexical tautology is a set-theoretic tautology.
- For every set of natural numbers described above, there is a general name whose extension is this set.
- Polyreferential set-theoretic semantics for Łukasiewicz’s calculus. A general name that has at least two referents (or exactly one referent) we will call polyreferential (or monoreferential). These names correspond to polyreferential models having the form , where is a set that has at least two elements and is a function of denotation, which assigns to any name letter a subset of that has at least two elements.
4. Other Possible Formal Approaches to Syllogistics
Given that Aristotle is concerned with deductions, i.e., with how conclusions may be derived, we should expect him to be equally concerned with deducibility, i.e., with what conclusions are derivable. We should also bear in mind that deducibility can be discussed either by means of verbs such ‘as … implies …’ or ‘… follows from …’, or by means of conditionals such as ‘if … then necessarily …’ or plain ‘if … then …’; the difference between the verbal form and the conditional form being merely the difference between mention and use. In this way think we can explain Aristotle’s frequent use of conditionals in his discussions of syllogistic without needing to identify, as Łukasiewicz does, the conditionals with the syllogisms themselves.
- If , then .
5. Calculi Allowing Empty Names
5.1. Shepherdson’s Approach
- Shepherdson’s -system. For the weak interpretation of the functor for universal affirmative sentences, we will leave the abbreviation ‘’ and—according to the proposal of Kotarbiński and Lejewski—we can read it as ‘all … is …’. The set of -formulas is built in the standard way from the atomic formulas, the Boolean propositional connectives, and brackets. For the set of the primitive functors ‘’ and ‘’, Shepherdson [9] proposed an axiomatisation of the -system. Of Łukasiewicz’s four axioms, he left (I), (Barbara), and (Datisi) but rejected the principle of identity (I) since it turns into a false sentence for all empty names. Instead, Shepherdson took two axioms weaker than (I):
- The Shepherdsonian -system. We can extend the set of -formulas to the set of -formulas as for Łukasiewicz’s calculus. To Shepherdson’s axioms, we add (df ) and (df o). Moreover, all substitutions of all CPL tautologies with -formulas are also accepted as axioms. By Sh, we denote the system that has Shephedson’s axioms, definitions (df ) and (df o), and two rules for deriving theses: detachment and substitution. We remember that using these means, from (I) and (Datisi), we get (C). Moreover, by (C) and (df ), we get (C). Of course, all theses of the Shepherdsonian -system are also theses of Ł.
- Definitional extensions of Sh. Let us define the unary functor ‘’ (“exists”) with which we state the non-emptiness of a given name:
- Set-theoretic semantics for Sh. In the semantic study of Sh, we can use set-theoretic semantics as for Ł. Now, however, we use models of the form , where the universe is an arbitrary set (may be empty), and the denotation function assigns to name letters arbitrary subsets of . With this only change, in the same way as in the first point of Section 3.3, we define the notions of a formula being true in a model and of being a tautology.
- is true in iff the set is non-empty;
- is true in iff the set is non-empty and is included in ;
- is true in iff ;
- is true in iff and the set is non-empty;
- is true in iff the set is non-empty and is disjoint with ;
- is true in iff the sets and are non-empty and they are disjoint.
- A formula is a tautology if and only if it is true in every model with a non-empty universe.
- Non-monoreferential set-theoretic semantics for a Shepherdsonian system. We remember that in using Łukasiewicz’s calculus, we can exclude monoreferential names (empty names are excluded out of necessity). In Section 7, we will show that Shepherdsonian systems can apply only for non-monoreferential (i.e., empty or polyreferential) names. These names corresponding to non-monoreferential models having the form , where
- is a set that has at least two elements;
- is a function of denotation that assigns to any name letter either the empty set or a subset of with at least two elements.
5.2. Słupecki’s Approach
- Słupecki’s system. Słupecki [10] proposed a calculus of names in which the functors of affirmative sentences were primary and adopted the strong interpretation for universal affirmative sentences. Therefore, we can abbreviate these functors as ‘ȧ’ and ‘’, respectively. The theses of Słupecki’s calculus can also be applied to empty names. This system includes all correct Aristotelian syllogisms, the laws of the logical square, and conversion laws.
[…] the sentence [corresponds to our ‘’] understand only as an abbreviation of the sentence [corresponds to our ‘’] and read: it is not the case that every a is a b (The author of this paper translates the Polish text from [10]).
- Complete axiomatisations ofȧi-tautologies. In [11,18,19], it was shown that the following four sets form full axiomatisations of all ȧ-tautologies:
- Słupecki’s axioms plus formula (†);
- (C), (Bȧrbȧrȧ), and (Dȧrii) plus formulas (†) and (‡);
- (ȧS) and (Bȧrbȧrȧ) plus (†) and the following formula:
- (Bȧrbȧrȧ), (Dȧtisi), (†), and (‡).
6. The Modern Syllogistic with Leśniewski’s Copula
6.1. On Leśniewski’s Copula and Related Functors
- Leśniewski’s singular sentences and sentences about the identity. The copula ‘is’ is the only primitive of Leśniewski’s Ontology. This theory can be classified as a quantifier calculus of names. In this work, however, we deal only with the quantifier-free calculus of names.
- ‘S is a P’ is true if and only if the name S has exactly one referent, which is a referent of the name P.
- ‘’ is true if and only if the name S has exactly one referent which is not a referent of the name P.
- ‘’ is true if and only if the names S and P have the same (one) referent.
- Set-theoretic semantics for Leśniewski’s functors. For any model , we extend the notion of being a true formula for Leśniewski’s use of functors. So, for all name letters and , we accept the following:
- is true in iff is a singleton whose only element belongs to .
- is true in iff is a singleton whose only element does not belong to .
- is true in iff and are identical singletons.
6.2. The Quantifier-Free Fragment of Ontology
6.3. The Fusion of Shepherdson’s System with the Quantifier-Free Ontology
- Set-theoretic semantics. In the semantic study of Sh, we can use set-theoretic semantics for Sh, additionally using the interpretation for ‘’. As can be easily seen, is sound regarding set-theoretic semantics. Indeed, all of its axioms are tautologies, and substitution and detachment preserve the validity of formulas. In Section 7, we show different ways of proving the completeness of Sh.
6.4. Systems for ȧi-Tautologies
- The completeness of axiomatisations ofȧi-tautologies. The presented axiomatisations of ȧ-systems are complete since they are definitionally equivalent to given complete -systems.
7. Methods for the Completeness of Calculi of Names with Respect to Set-Theoretic Semantics
7.1. Proofs of the Completeness of Calculi Using Shepherdson’s Approach
- For . Shepherdson [9] takes the following open first-order conditions, which correspond to the axioms (I), (Barbara), (Datisi), (⋆), and (⋆⋆):
- B1.
- B2.
- B3.
- B4.
- B5.
- (Th8)
- Every -algebra is epimorphic (briefly speaking, an epimorphism, in other words, quasi-isomorphism or onto-homeomorphism, is an isomorphism without injection; all epimorphic relational structures give the same true formulas) to a special -algebra.
- if and , then ;
- if , then .
- ($)
- If holds, then or is an I-set of and .
- ($$)
- holds iff is an I-set of iff .
- holds iff ,
- holds iff .
- A formula is a theorem of if and only if it is true in all -algebras.
- (Th10)
- A formula is a theorem of if and only if it is true in all special -algebras.
- D1.
- D2.
- (Th10′)
- A formula is a theorem of if and only if it is true in all special -algebras.
- is a thesis of Sh iff is a theorem of .
- is a tautology iff is true in all special -algebras.
- is a thesis of Sh iff is a tautology.
- B4′.
- For B3, Shepherdson created special B3-algebras that differ from special B1-algebras only in that their universes consist of non-empty sets since they have to meet (B4′). He obtains the following theorem:
- (Th11)
- Every -algebra is epimorphic to a special -algebra. A formula of is a theorem if and only if it is true in all special .
- is a thesis of Ł iff is a traditional tautology.
- C0.
- C1.
- C2.
- C3.
- (Th1ε)
- Every -algebra is epimorphic to a special -algebra.
- if not , then ;
- if not and , then ;
- if , then .
- holds iff ,
- holds iff .
- holds iff is a singleton and .
- (Th2ε)
- A formula is a theorem of if and only if it is true in all special -algebras.
- (Co)
- a formula is a theorem of if and only if it is open and derivable from all open axioms of C by detachment and substitution.
- (Th3ε)
- For any open formula, it is a theorem of if and only if it is theorem of C.
- (Th4ε)
- For any open formula, it is a theorem of if and only if it is true in all special -algebras.
- (Th4′ε)
- For any open formula, it is a theorem of if and only if it is true in all special -algebras.
- is a thesis of Sh iff is a theorem of .
- is a tautology iff is true in all special -algebras.
- is a thesis of Sh iff is a tautology.
7.2. Proofs of the Completeness of Calculi with the Direct Use of Henkin’s Method
7.2.1. With Using Filters Designated by Maximal Consistent Sets in a Given Calculus
- if and , then ;
- if , then .
- (f1)
- if , then or is a filter;
- (f2)
- if , then is a filter.
- For Sh. For any maximal consistent set in , we use , where
- consists of all filters designated by ( may be empty),
- .
- (a)
- iff iff .
- (CSh)
- is true in iff .
- is true in iff .
- A formula is a thesis of Sh if and only if it is an -tautology.
- For Ł. For any maximal consistent set in Ł, we use as for . Now, by (I) and (a), is a traditional model since for each , we have that is a filter belonging to . The rest of the proof is similar to that for Sh. Therefore, we get the following:
- A formula is a thesis of Ł if and only if it is a traditional -tautology.
- For . For any maximal consistent set in , we use , where
- consists of all filters designated by and all name letters such that ,
- (a)
- If , then and .
- (b)
- iff iff .
- (c)
- if and , then ;
- (d)
- iff iff is a singleton.
- (CShε)
- is true in iff .
- is true in iff .
- A formula is a thesis of Sh if and only if it is an -tautology.
7.2.2. Without Using Filters
For Sh
- consists of all pairs of name letters such that ( may be empty),
- consists of all those and only those for which .
- (o)
- iff iff .
- (CSh)
- is true in iff .
- is true in iff .
- A formula is a thesis of Sh if and only if it is an -tautology.
- A formula is a thesis of Sh if and only if it is true in every model with a non-empty universe.
- consists of all pairs of name letters,
- consists of all those and only those for which both and .
For Ł
- A formula is a thesis of Ł if and only if it is a traditional -tautology.
For
- iff ,
- is an equivalence relation that is a congruence with respect to all functors.
- if , , and , then .
- consists of all pairs of name letters such that and all equivalent classes and name letters such that ( may be empty),
- (i)
- if and , then ;
- (ii)
- iff iff .
- (iii)
- iff iff is a singleton.
- (CShε)
- is true in iff .
- is true in iff .
- A formula is a thesis of Sh if and only if it is an -tautology.
- consists of all pairs of name letters, all equivalent classes of name letters, and all name letters,
8. Further Extensions of Calculi of Names
8.1. Calculi of Names Plus Traditional Singular Sentences and Identities
- is true in iff ;
- is true in iff ;
- is true in iff .
8.2. Calculi of Names Plus Czeżowski’s Singular Sentences and Identities
- is true in iff ;
- is true in iff ;
- is true in iff .
- What happens if we reject Czeżowski’s assumption that the object chosen as S is an S?
- Are ‘This S is a P’ and ‘This S is not a P’ without truth values or only false?
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Łukasiewicz, J. Elementy Logiki Matematycznej; Presburger, M., Ed.; Publications of Students of Mathematics and Physics in Warsaw Univesity: Warsaw, Poland, 1929; Volume 18, 2nd ed., Polish Scientific Publ.: Warsaw, Poland, 1958; English Translated by Wojtasiewicz, O., Elements of Mathematical Logic, The Macmillan Co.: New York, NY, USA, 1963. [Google Scholar]
- Łukasiewicz, J. ‘Znaczenie analizy logicznej dla poznania’ (The importance of logical analysis for cognition). PrzegląD Filoz. 1934, 37, 369–377. [Google Scholar]
- Łukasiewicz, J. ‘O sylogistyce Arystotelesa’ (On Aristotle’s syllogistic). Spraw. PAU 1939, 44, 220–227. [Google Scholar]
- Łukasiewicz, J. Aristotle’s Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic; 2nd ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1957. [Google Scholar]
- Corcoran, J. Aristotle’s natural deduction system. J. Symb. Log. 1972, 37, 437. [Google Scholar]
- Corcoran, J. Aristotle’s natural deduction system. In Ancient Logic and Its Modern Interpretations; Corcoran, J., Ed.; Synthese Historical Library: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1974; pp. 85–131. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Smiley, T.J. What is a syllogism? J. Philos. Log. 1973, 2, 136–154. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Smith, R. Introduction. In Prior Analytics; Translated, with introduction, notes, and commentary, by Smith, R.; Hackett Publishing Company: Indianapolis, IN, USA; Cambridge, UK, 1989; pp. XIII–XXXI. [Google Scholar]
- Shepherdson, J.C. On the interpretation of Aristotelian syllogistic. J. Symb. Log. 1956, 21, 137–147. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Słupecki, J. Uwagi o sylogistyce Arystotelesa, Notes on Aristotle’s syllogistic. Ann. UMCS 1946, 1, 187–191. [Google Scholar]
- Pietruszczak, A. ‘O logice tradycyjnej i rachunku nazw dopuszczającym podstawienia nazw pustych’ (On traditional logic and calculus of names allowing substitutions of empty names). Ruch Filoz. 1987, 44, 158–166. [Google Scholar]
- Ishimoto, A. A propositional fragment of Leśniewski’s elementary ontology. Stud. Log. 1977, 36, 285–299. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Quine, W.V. Methods of Logic; Henry Holt and Co.: New York, NY, USA, 1950. [Google Scholar]
- Morawiec, A. Podstawy logiki nazw. Stud. Log. 1961, 12, 145–161. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pratt-Hartmann, I.; Moss, L.S. Logics for the relational syllogistic. Rev. Symb. Log. 2009, 2, 647–683. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kotarbiński, T. Elementy Teorii Poznania, Logiki Formalnej i Metodologii Nauk; Pergamon Press and Ossolineum: Oxford, UK; Wrocław, Poland, 1966. [Google Scholar]
- Lejewski, C. On Leśniewski’s ontology. Ratio 1958, 1, 150–176, Reprint in: Srzednicki, J.T.J.; Rickey, V.F. (Eds.) Leśniewski’s Systems. Ontology and Mereology; Martinus Nijhoff Publishers (Kluwer) and Ossolineum: Hague, The Netherlands; Wrocław, Poland, 1984; pp. 1148–1230. [Google Scholar]
- Pietruszczak, A. ‘O pewnym ujęciu logiki tradycyjnej’ (On a certain approach to traditional logic). Acta Univ. Nicolai Copernic. Log. 1991, I, 31–41. [Google Scholar]
- Pietruszczak, A. Bezkwantyfikatorowy Rachunek Nazw. Systemy i ich Metateoria. Doctoral Dissertation, Nicolaus Copernicus University in Toruń, Toruń, Poland, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Quine, W.V. Logic and reification of universals. In From a Logical Point of View; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1953; pp. 102–129. [Google Scholar]
- Pietruszczak, A. ‘Standardowe rachunki nazw z funktorem Leśniewskiego’ (Standard calculi of names with Leśniewski’s functor). Acta Univ. Nicolai Copernic. Log. 1991, I, 5–29. [Google Scholar]
- Pietruszczak, A. ‘Stała Leśniewskiego w teoriach sylogistycznych. Semantyczne badania pewnych kwantyfikatorowych rachunków nazw’ (Leśniewski’s copula in syllogistic theories. Semantic studies of certain quantifier calculus of names). Acta Univ. Nicolai Copernic. Log. 1992, III, 45–76. [Google Scholar]
- Corcoran, J. Completeness of an ancient logic. J. Symb. Log. 1972, 37, 696–702. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Clark, M. The Place of Syllogistic in Logical Theory; Nottingham University Press: Nottingham, UK, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Moss, L.S. Completeness theorems for syllogistic fragments. In Logics for Linguistic Structures; Hamm, F., Kepser, S., Eds.; Series “Trends in Linguistics”; Mouton de Gruyter: Berlin, Germany; New York, NY, USA, 2008; pp. 143–173. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Czeżowski, T. On certain peculiarities of singular propositions. Mind 1955, LXIV, 392–395. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Takano, M. A semantical investigation into Leśniewski’s axiom of his ontology. Stud. Log. 1985, 44, 71–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rasiowa, H.; Sikorski, R. The Mathematics of Metamatematics, 2nd ed.; PWN: Warszawa, Poland, 1968. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Pietruszczak, A. The Calculus of Names—The Legacy of Jan Łukasiewicz. Axioms 2025, 14, 160. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms14030160
Pietruszczak A. The Calculus of Names—The Legacy of Jan Łukasiewicz. Axioms. 2025; 14(3):160. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms14030160
Chicago/Turabian StylePietruszczak, Andrzej. 2025. "The Calculus of Names—The Legacy of Jan Łukasiewicz" Axioms 14, no. 3: 160. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms14030160
APA StylePietruszczak, A. (2025). The Calculus of Names—The Legacy of Jan Łukasiewicz. Axioms, 14(3), 160. https://doi.org/10.3390/axioms14030160