1. Introduction and Preliminaries
Metric fixed point theory is a vital and wide part of nonlinear functional analysis. In fact, metric fixed point theory provides various applications in different fields which include ordinary differential equations, partial differential equations, integral equations, functional equations, matrix equations, random differential equations, variational inequalities, eigen value problems, operator equations, optimization theory, approximation theory, fractal theory, control theory, probability theory, potential theory, electrical heating in the Joule–Thomson effect, fluid flow, chemical equations, steady state temperature distribution, neutron transport theory, Nash equilibria, econometrics, economic theory, epidemics, global analysis, physics, statistics, engineering, computer science, biology, chemistry, and several others. There is an extensive literature on this topic, which includes pure as well as applied aspects. Indeed, the area of metric fixed point theory originated in 1922 with the appearance of the Banach Contraction Principle [
1] (abbreviated as: BCP). This core result guarantees the existence and uniqueness of a fixed point under the hypothesis that the ambient space remains a complete metric space, whereas the underlying mapping should be a contraction mapping. Moreover, BCP offers a constructive procedure for approximation of the fixed point. Many authors have extended BCP employing relatively more general contractive conditions. One of the remarkable generalizations is due to Berinde [
2], which was first referred to as weak contraction and then almost contraction [
3].
Definition 1 ([2]). A function (from a metric space into itself) is said to be almost contraction if for some , for some , and for all , we have The symmetry of the metric
concludes that the almost contraction condition is equivalent to the following dual one (c.f. [
2]):
Theorem 1 ([2]). Suppose that remains a complete metric space while is an almost contraction self-mapping on . Then, admits a fixed point.
Theorem 1 subsumes the earlier classical fixed point theorems due to Banach [
1], Kannan [
4], Chatterjea [
5], and Zamfirescu [
6]. The class of almost contractions also covers a certain class of quasi-contractions due to Ćirić [
7]. Here, it can be highlighted that the a almost contraction mapping need not admit a unique fixed point. However, the fixed points of any almost contraction mapping can be computed by the convergence of the sequence of Picard iteration. By slightly modifying the almost contraction condition, Berinde [
2] obtained the following uniqueness result:
Theorem 2 ([2]). Suppose that remains a complete metric space while is self-mapping on . If for some , for some , and for all , we havethen admits a unique fixed point. For further study on almost contractions, we refer to [
8,
9,
10,
11,
12,
13,
14,
15]. On the other hand, fixed point theorems in ordered metric space have occupied a significant chapter in metric fixed point theory, especially due to the works of Ran and Reurings [
16] and Nieto and Rodríguez-López [
17]. The results in ordered metric spaces mainly weaken the contractive condition by employing the fact that the condition needs to hold only for those elements of the space that are related by the underlying partial order. In 2015, Alam and Imdad [
18] established yet another novel variant of BCP employing an amorphous (arbitrary) binary relation. In recent years, the fixed point results of Alam and Imdad [
18] were further generalized and extended by many authors (e.g., [
19,
20,
21,
22,
23,
24,
25,
26]).
The aim of this paper is to prove the fixed point theorems in the context of metric space equipped with a binary relation employing a relation-preserving almost contractivity condition. These results are indeed relation-theoretic versions of Theorem 1 and Theorem 2. Several examples are furnished in support of the newly proved results, which clearly show the important improvements of the existing results in the literature.
2. Relation-Theoretic Notions
This section is comprised of some definitions which are needed in the subsequent discussion. As usual, will stand for the set of real numbers, for the set of natural numbers, and for the set of whole numbers. Recall that a binary relation (often called a relation) on a set remains a subset of . For simplicity, we sometimes write instead of , e.g., in the case of the relations of “less than or equal to” () and “greater than or equal to” () on is expressed respectively as: and .
Definition 2 ([27]). Given a relation on a set , the setremains again a relation on , which is termed as an inverse relation
of . Moreover, the setforms again a relation on , which is called the symmetric closure
of . Clearly, remains the least symmetric relation on among those binary relations that contain . Definition 3 ([18]). Any two elements r and t of a set are called -comparative, whereas remains a relation on if either or . Usually, means that “r and t are -comparative”.
Proposition 1 ([18]). If remains a relation on , then Definition 4 ([27]). If remains a relation on a set , then is said to be complete if each pair of elements of is -comparative, , Definition 5 ([27]). If and remains a relation on , then the setinduces a relation on , which is termed as the restriction of on . Definition 6 ([18]). By an -preserving sequence, where remains a relation on a set , we mean the sequence , which satisfies Definition 7 ([18]). Given any set and a mapping , we say that a relation on is -closed if for any , Proposition 2 ([19]). Suppose that is a set so that remains a relation on while is a function from into itself. Then, the -closedness of implies the -closedness of .
Proposition 3 ([20]). Suppose that is a set so that remains a relation on while is a function from into itself. Then, the -closedness of implies the -closedness of , where .
Definition 8 ([19]). A metric space is termed as -complete (whereas remains a relation on ) if each Cauchy -preserving sequence in converges.
Obviously, for any metric space completeness implies -completeness whatever the relation . In particular, if remains the universal relation, then the concepts of -completeness and usual completeness are equivalent.
Definition 9 ([19]). A function (from a metric space into itself) is termed as -continuous (whereas remains a relation on ) at a point iffor any sequence which is -preserving and converges to r. Naturally, -continuity of means -continuity of at every point of . Obviously, for any mapping on a metric space endowed with the relation , continuity implies -continuity. In particular, if remains the universal relation, then the concepts of -continuity and usual continuity are equivalent.
Definition 10 ([18]). On a metric space , an underlying relation is termed as ϱ-self-closed if each sequence (which is -preserving and convergent such that ) has a subsequence whose terms are -comparative with r, , In the sequel, for a metric space , a relation and a function , the following notations will be adopted.
- (i)
:= the collection of the fixed points of ,
- (ii)
.
3. Main Results
In the following lines, a fixed point theorem for almost contraction employing a binary relation is presented.
Theorem 3. Let be a metric space equipped with a binary relation . Let be a self-mapping on . Moreover, assume that
- (i)
is -complete,
- (ii)
is -closed,
- (iii)
is -continuous or is ϱ-self-closed,
- (iv)
,
- (v)
for some and and for all with , we have
Then, admits a fixed point.
Proof. In view of assumption (iv), we can choose
. We define a sequence
of Picard iteration based at the initial point
, so that
As
, the
-closedness of
together with Proposition 3 yields that
so that
It follows that the sequence
is
-preserving.
We denote
. Applying the contractivity condition (v) and using (
1) and (
2), we obtain for all
that
which in view of (
1) reduces to
By induction, (
3) reduces to
so that
For
, using (
4), we obtain
It follows that
is a Cauchy sequence. Hence,
is an
-preserving Cauchy sequence. Due to the
-completeness of
, one can find
satisfying
Now, we use assumption (iii) to show that
r is a fixed point of
. Suppose that
is
-continuous. Since
is
-preserving with
, therefore, the
-continuity of
asserts that
. Using the uniqueness of the limit, we obtain
so that
r is a fixed point of
. Alternately, assume that
is
-self-closed. Since
is an
-preserving sequence such that
, therefore, by the
-self-closedness of
, one can find a subsequence
of
with
for all
. Obviously, we have
On using
, symmetry of
, assumption
, and (
5), we have
so that
. By the uniqueness of limit, we obtain
. Thus,
r remains a fixed point of
. □
Now, a result on uniqueness of fixed points is proved by making a slight modification in almost contractivity conditions in addition to using an additional hypothesis.
Theorem 4. Under the hypotheses (i)–(iv) of Theorem 3, if the following assumptions hold:
- (vi)
for some and and for all with , we have - (vii)
is complete,
then, has a unique fixed point.
Proof. Proceeding along the lines similar to the proof of Theorem 3, we can find that
. We take
so that
Clearly,
. Hence, by assumption (vii), we obtain
Making use of (
6), (
7), and the contractivity condition (vi), we obtain
Using (
6) again, we obtain
Therefore, Equation (
8) reduces to
so that
However, due to
, the above inequality yields
, i.e.,
. This concludes that the fixed point of
is unique. □
Remark 1. Under the restriction , Theorem 4 reduces to the classical relation-theoretic contraction principle [18]. Therefore, our main results (, Theorems 3 and 4) extend and improve the results of Alam and Imdad [18]. 4. Examples
In this section, we furnish examples, which demonstrate the importance of Theorem 3.
Example 1. Take with usual metric . Define a binary relation . Then, is an -complete metric space. Let be the identity mapping on . Then, is -continuous and is -closed. Now, for any arbitrary , and for all satisfying , we have satisfies assumption of Theorem 3. Thus, all the conditions of Theorem 3 are satisfied. Consequently, has a fixed point in . Indeed, here, . Example 2. Take with usual metric . Define a binary relation (natural ordering). Then, is an -complete metric space. Let be a mapping on defined by Then, is -continuous and is -closed. Now, for any , and for all satisfying , we have satisfies assumption of Theorem 3. Thus, all the conditions of Theorem 3 are satisfied. Consequently, has a fixed point in . Indeed, here, has a fixed point, namely: .