Next Article in Journal
Tacit Collusion under Fairness and Reciprocity
Previous Article in Journal
An Equilibrium Analysis of Knaster’s Fair Division Procedure
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Nash Implementation in an Allocation Problem with Single-Dipped Preferences

1
National Institute of Statistics and Applied Economics, Madinat Al Irfane, Rabat Institutes, 10100 Rabat, Morocco
2
University of Caen, Center for Research in Economics and Management(UMR CNRS 6211), 19 Rue Claude Bloch 14032 Caen, Cedex, France
Games 2013, 4(1), 38-49; https://doi.org/10.3390/g4010038
Submission received: 25 November 2012 / Revised: 10 January 2013 / Accepted: 15 January 2013 / Published: 30 January 2013

Abstract

:
In this paper, we study the Nash implementation in an allocation problem with single-dipped preferences. We show that, with at least three agents, Maskin monotonicity is necessary and sufficient for implementation. We examine the implementability of various social choice correspondences (SCCs) in this environment, and prove that some well-known SCCs are Maskin monotonic ( but they do not satisfy no-veto power) and hence Nash implementable.

1. Introduction

The objective of implementation theory is to study, in a rigorous manner, the relationship between outcomes in a society and the institutions under which those outcomes arise. The outcomes represent the production and allocation of public and private goods and services in a society where each agent has preferences over these outcomes. The institutions are the set of rules under which the allocation is decided and applied (property rights, voting laws and voting rules, constitutions, contract law, etc.). The relationship between institutions and outcomes can be viewed from a perspective of design, and, in this form, is called the theory of mechanism design. The “planner” or the mechanism designer (representative of state, a local collectivity, a region, manager of a firm, etc.) has a goal in mind—to maximize an objective function called social choice correspondence (or rule). This correspondence represents the social objectives that the society or its representatives want to achieve. A difficulty arises in the asymmetry of information between planner and agents. This asymmetric information results because the planner does not know the exact preferences of agents. If, for example, the “options” or outcomes are public goods, the agents will state false preferences in order to participate with lower costs, and once the public property is constructed, they can use it like everyone. In order for the agents to reveal their true preferences, the planner will implement a mechanism (non-cooperative game). It is a way of collecting messages and making a decision; it represents the communication and decision aspects of the organization. This mechanism is a list of messages or “strategy” spaces, and an outcome function mapping messages into allocations, where the strategies of players depend essentially on the preference profiles and the options (or alternatives) set. A social choice correspondence (SCC) is implementable in a given solution concept if the payment with this solution of the game corresponds to the socially desired alternative and vice versa. The planner, thus, hopes to, via this game, get the agents to reveal their sincere preferences.
To characterize the class of the SCCs which are implementable, some conditions on these correspondences should be imposed. Thus, Maskin [1], as the first to identify an important relationship between implementability and a condition known now as Maskin monotonicity, demonstrated that any implementable SCC in Nash equilibria must satisfy this condition. However, this condition alone is not sufficient, and so Maskin [1] gave an additional condition called no-veto power, thus proving that in a society where at least three agents exist, an SCC is implementable if the conditions of monotonicity and no-veto power hold.
Nevertheless, the problem of implementation theory is that there are important correspondences in economic, social, and political sciences which do not satisfy no-veto power1. Thus, many authors like Moore and Repullo [10], Dutta and Sen [11], Sjöström [12], Danilov [13], Yamato [14], and Ziad [15,16], tried to address this problem by providing alternative conditions.
Thomson [17,18] applied a certain number of conditions for these previous theoretical results to implement solutions of the problem of fair allocation with single-peaked preferences. He showed that Maskin’s theorem is silent about the implementability of many solutions which can be implemented by the Yamato’s condition of strong monotonicity. However, he found that this latter condition is not stable under intersection and so he appealed to the algorithm of Sjöm [12]. More recently, Doghmi and Ziad [19,20] provided new sufficient conditions and showed that many solutions can be implemented on the single-peaked preferences domain in an easier way compared to that of the previous conditions in the literature.
This domain of single-peaked preferences has been explored in social choice theory since the work of Black [21]. In parallel, an inverse configuration to this domain, calledsingle-dipped preferences, has also been explored in this theory and in many economic applications, but it has never been explored in relation to the problem of implementation theory.
Thus, in this paper, we examine the implementability of solution to the fair division problems when agents have single-dipped preferences. This type of preference requires that each agent has a unique bad alternative. Assuming that there is an amount Ω ∈ ℝ++ of a certain infinitely divisible good that is to be allocated among a set of n agents. The preference of each agent i is represented by a continuous and single-dipped preference relation Ri over [0, Ω] as illustrated in Figure 1.
Figure 1. Single-dipped preferences.
Figure 1. Single-dipped preferences.
Games 04 00038 g001
This type of preference has been introduced by Inada [22] to study public good situations. It is also explored for private goods areas by Klaus et al. [23] to characterize two classes of division rules that satisfy Pareto optimality, strategy-proofness, and replacement-domination proprieties. Klaus [24,25] provided two allocation models with single-dipped preferences. In the first model, she considered the problem of allocating an infinitely divisible commodity among agents. She characterized the class of rules that satisfy a whole selection of proprieties. In the second model, she studied the allocation of an indivisible object to a group of agents. Similar to the first model, she characterized the class of rules that satisfy some conditions. Ehlers [26] studied the problem of allocating an infinitely divisible endowment among a group of agents; he characterized a class of Pareto optimal and coalitionally strategy-proof allocation rules and studied some proprieties of fairness. Manjunath [27] explored the problem of locating a single public good when preferences of agents are single-dipped, thus providing a characterization of all rules satisfying unanimity and strategy-proofness properties. More recently, Barberà et al. [28] were interested in the characterization of the family of all individual and group strategy-proof rules on the domain of single-dipped preferences. They examined the implications of these strategy-proofness requirements on the maximum size of the rules’ range.
In this paper, we study the Nash implementation in an allocation problem with single-dipped preferences. We prove that, with at least three agents, any solution of the problem of fair division can be implemented in Nash equilibria if—and only if—it satisfies Maskin monotonicity. Thus, via this result, the no-veto power condition is dispensed of in this area, and so we implement some well-known correspondences which satisfy Maskin monotonicity but violate the condition of no-veto power.
The rest of this paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we introduce notations and definitions. In Section 3, we state and prove our main result in a domain of the allocation problem with single-dipped preferences, and we justify this result providing some well-known correspondences which satisfy Maskin monotonicity and violate the no-veto power condition. Section 4 provides our concluding remarks.

2. General Notations and Definitions

Before defining our domain of applications in Section 3, we provide in this section general notations and definitions in order to present the key concepts of implementation theory. Let A be a setof alternatives, and let N = {1, ..., n} be a set of individuals, with generic element i. Each individual i is characterized by a preference relation Ri defined over A, which is a complete, transitive, and reflexive relation in some class i of admissible preference relations. Let = 1 × ... ×n. An element R = (R1, ..., Rn) ∈ ℜ is a preference profile. The relation Ri indicates the individual’s i preference. For a, bA, the notation aRib means that the individual i weakly prefers a to b. The asymmetrical and symmetrical parts of Ri are noted respectively by Pi and ∼i.
A social choice correspondence (SCC) F is a mapping from into 2A \{∅}, that associates with every R a non-empty subset of A. For all iRi and all a ∈ A, the lower contour set for agent i at alternative a is noted by: L(a, Ri) = {bA | aRib}. The strict lower contour set and the indifference lower contour set are noted respectively by LS(a, Ri) = {bA | aPib} and LI(a, Ri) = {bA | ai b}.
A mechanism (or form game) is given by Γ = (S, g) where S = ΠiN Si; Si denotes the strategy set of the agent i and g is a function from S to A. The elements of S are denoted by s = (s1,s2, ..., sn) = (si, s−i), where s−i = (s1, ..., si−1, si+1, ..., sn). When sS and biSi, (bi, si) = (s1, ..., si−i,bi, si+1, ..., sn) is obtained after replacing si by bi, and g(Si, si) is the set of results which agent i can obtain when the other agents choose s−i from S−i = ΠjN, j ≠ iSj.
A Nash equilibrium of the game (Γ,R) is a vector of strategies sS such that for any i, g(s)Rig(bi, si) for all biSi, i.e. when the other players choose si, the player i cannot deviate from si. Given N(g, R, S) the set of Nash equilibria of the game (Γ,R), a mechanism Γ = (S, g) implements an SCC F in Nash equilibria if for all R ∈ ℜ,F (R) = g(N(g, R, S)).
We say that an SCC F is implementable in Nash equilibria if there is a mechanism which implements it in these equilibria.
A SCC F satisfies unanimity if for any a ∈ A and any R ∈ ℜ, if for any iN, L(a, Ri) = A, then a ∈ F (R).
Maskin [1] introduced the following conditions on F to characterize the SCCs that are implementable in Nash equilibria.
Monotonicity: This condition stipulates that if an alternative a is socially chosen in a profile R, and if the alternatives ranked below a for all agents remain ranked below it (in the large sense) in a new profile R′, then the alternative a must be socially chosen in R′.
A SCC F satisfies monotonicity if for all R, R′ ∈ ℜ, for any aF (R), if for any iN, L(a, Ri) ⊆ L(a, R′i), then aF (R′).
Maskin [1] proved that any Nash implementable correspondence must satisfy Maskin monotonicity. However, this condition alone is not sufficient. For this, Maskin [1] gave the following additional condition.
No-veto power: This condition requires that if an alternative is ranked at the top for all agents except one, then this alternative must be socially chosen.
A SCC F satisfies no-veto power if for i, R ∈ ℜ, and aA, if L(a, Rj) = A for all jN\{i}, then aF (R).
Maskin [1] showed that, with at least three players, any social choice correspondence satisfies Maskin monotonicity, and the no-veto power is thus Nash implementable.
Doghmi and Ziad [19] reexamined this result by introducing the following new sufficient conditions.
Strict monotonicity: It is a strong version of Maskin monotonicity. A SCC F satisfies strict monotonicity if for all R, R′ ∈ ℜ, for any a ∈ F (R), if for any iN, LS(a, Ri) ∪{a}⊆ L(a, Ri’), then aF (R’).
Strict weak no-veto power. It is a weak version of no-veto power. It lies between no-veto power and unanimity. A SCC F satisfies strict weak no-veto power if for i, R ∈ ℜ, and aF (R), if for R′ ∈ ℜ, bLS(a, Ri) ⊆ L(b, Ri) and L(b, Rj) = A for all jN\{i}, then bF (R′).
Doghmi and Ziad [19] showed that, in addition to unanimity, strict monotonicity and strict weak no-veto power are sufficient for an SCC F to be implementable.

3. Applications to Allocation Problem with Single-Dipped Preferences

There is an amount Ω ∈ ℝ++ of a certain infinitely divisible good that is to be allocated among a set N = {1, ..., n} of n agents. The preference of each agent iN is represented by a continuous and single-dipped preference relation Ri over [0, Ω] (the asymmetrical part is written Pi and the symmetrical part ∼i). For all xi, yi ∈ [0, Ω],xiRiyi means that, for the agent i, to consume a share xi is as good as to consume the quantity yi. A feasible allocation for the economy (R, Ω) is a vector x ≡ (xi)iN ∈ ℝ+n such that ΣiN xi = Ω and X is the set of the feasible allocations. We note that the feasible allocations set is X = [0, Ω] × ... × [0, Ω]. Thus, L(x, Ri) = X is equivalent to L(xi, Ri) = [0, Ω]. For the set L(x, Ri) = X, xRiy for all yX implies that xiRiyi. Thus, the agents’ preferences are defined over individual consumption spaces, not over allocation space. Then the proprieties of implementation theory, presented in general setup in Section 2, become as follows: A SCC F satisfies monotonicity if for all R, R′ ∈ ℜ, for any xF (R), if for any iN, L(xi, Ri) ⊆ L(xi, R′i), then xF (R′). A SCC F satisfies strict monotonicity if for all R, R′ ∈ ℜ, for any xF (R), if for any iN, LS(xi, Ri) ∪{xi}⊆ L(xi, R′i), then xF (R′). A SCC F satisfies no-veto power if for i, R ∈ ℜ, and xX, if L(xj, Rj) = [0, Ω] for all jN\{i}, then xF (R). A SCC F satisfies strict weak no-veto power if for i, R ∈ ℜ, x, yX, and xF (R), if for R′ ∈ ℜ, yiLS(xi, Ri) ⊆ L(yi, R′i) and L(yj, R′) = [0, Ω] for all jN\{i}, then yF (R′). A SCC F satisfies unanimity if for any xX and any R ∈ ℜ, if for any iN, L(xi, Ri) = [0, Ω], then xF (R). We note that the free disposability of the good is not assumed.
A preference relation Ri is single-dipped if there is a number d(Ri) ∈ [0, Ω] such that for all xi, yi ∈ [0, Ω] if xi < yid(Ri) or d(Ri) ≤ yi < xi, then xiPiyi. We call d(Ri) the dip of Ri.
The class of all single-dipped preference relations is represented by ℜsd. For R ∈ ℜsd, let d(R) = (d(R1), ..., d(Rn)) be the profile of dips. A single-dipped preference relation Ri ∈ ℜsdi is described by the function ri : [0, Ω] → [0, Ω] which is defined as follows: ri(xi) is the consumption of the agent i on the other side of the dip which is indifferent to xi (if it exists); otherwise, it is 0 or Ω. Formally, if xid(Ri), then, ri(xi) ≥ d(Ri) and xii ri(xi) if such a number exists or ri(xi) = Ω otherwise; if xid(Ri), then, ri(xi) ≤ d(Ri) and xii ri(xi) if such a number exists or ri(xi) = 0 otherwise.
Let us introduce some well-known correspondences.
No-Envy correspondence, NE, (Foley [29]). This correspondence selects the feasible allocations for which each agent prefers his own share than the shares of the other agents. It is defined as follows: Let R ∈ ℜsd, NE(R) = {xX if xiRixj for each pair {i, j}⊆ N}.
Individually Rational Correspondence from Equal Division, Ied: This correspondence selects the feasible allocations for which each agent prefers his own share rather than the average one. It is defined as follows: Let R ∈ ℜsd, Ied(R) = {xX : xiRi(Ω/n) for all iN}.
Pareto correspondence, P : This solution selects the feasible allocations which are not weakly dominated by another allocation for all agents and not strictly dominated for at least one agent. It is defined as follows: Let R ∈ ℜsd, P (R) = {xX : ∄x′ ∈ X such that for all iN, x′iRixi, and for some iN, xiPixi}.

3.1. The Main Result: Robustness of Maskin Monotonicity

As mentioned in Section 2, Maskin monotonicity is a necessary condition that an SCC must satisfy in order to be Nash implementable. However, Maskin monotonicity alone is not sufficient for implementation. In this subsection, we show that, in the domain of the allocation problem with single-dipped preferences, Maskin monotonicity becomes necessary and sufficient for implementation, and so the no-veto power condition is no longer required. To prove this result, we begin by introducing the following Lemmas.
Lemma 1 Let R, R′ ∈ ℜsd and x, yX. If the preferences are single-dipped, yiLS(xi, Ri), and LS(xi, Ri) ⊆ L(yi, R′i), then L(yi, R′i) = [0, Ω].
Proof. Let R, R′ ∈ ℜsd and x, yX. Since we have yiLS(xi, Ri), and LS(xi, Ri) ⊆ L(yi, R′i), it is clear from the single-dippedness and the continuity of the preferences that L(yi, R′i) = [0, Ω]. Q.E.D.
Lemma 2 On a single-dipped domain, any non-constant strict monotonic SCC satisfies unanimity.
Proof. We show that any non-constant strict monotonic SCC F satisfies unanimity. Suppose not; i.e., for all R, R′ ∈ ℜsd, for any xF (R), if for any iN, LS(xi, Ri) ∪{xi}⊆ L(xi, R′i), then xF (R′). But, for any xX and any Games 04 00038 i001 ∈ ℜ, for any iN, [0, Ω] = L(xi, Games 04 00038 i001), and xF ( Games 04 00038 i001). We have for all iN, LS(xi, Ri) ∪{xi}⊆ [0, Ω] = L(xi, Games 04 00038 i001). By strict monotonicity, xF ( Games 04 00038 i001),a contradiction. Q.E.D.
According to Lemmas 1 and 2, we have the following corollary:
Corollary 1 On a single-dipped domain, any non-constant strict monotonic SCC satisfies strict weak no-veto power.
In the following, we show that strict monotonicity, alone, is sufficient for Nash implementation when preferences are single-dipped.
Proposition 1 Let n 3. In the allocation problem with single-dipped preferences, any SCC satisfying strict monotonicity can be implemented in Nash equilibria.
Proof. By Lemma 2, Corollary 1 and Theorem 1 of Doghmi and Ziad [19], the proof is completed as required. Q.E.D.
Now, we show that strict monotonicity is not only sufficient, but is also necessary, as long as it becomes equivalent to Maskin monotonicity.
Proposition 2 In the allocation problem with single-dipped preferences, the strict monotonicity condition becomes equivalent to Maskin monotonicity.
Proof. Let R, R′ ∈ ℜsd and x, yX. Suppose xid(Ri) (similar statements can be proved for xid(Ri)). i) ⇒, it is clear that LS(xi, Ri) ∪{xi}⊆ L(xi, Ri). Therefore, strict monotonicity implies Maskin monotonicity. ii) ⇐, in this case, suppose that LS(xi, Ri) ∪{xi}⊆ L(xi, R′) (1). It is clear that L(xi, Ri) = LS(xi, Ri) ∪{xi}∪{ri(xi)} if ri(xi) exists (2). From (1) and the continuity of preferences, it is necessary to have ri(xi) ≤ ri′ (xi) (3). Then, (1), (2) and (3) give L(xi, Ri) ⊆ L(xi, R′i) ∀i. Thus, we have the inclusion of Maskin monotonicity. Q.E.D.
Through propositions 1 and 2, we complete the proof of the following theorem which is the main result of the paper.
Theorem 1 : Let n 3. A SCC in the allocation problem with single-dipped preferences is Nash implementable if and only if it satisfies Maskin monotonicity.
To justify this result, we provide in the next subsection a list of solutions which satisfy Maskin monotonicity, and violate the condition of no-veto power.

3.2. Examples of SCCs satisfying/not satisfying Maskin’s proprieties

In this subsection, we check whether the no-envy correspondence, the individually rational correspondence from equal division, (NEIed) correspondence, (NEP) correspondence, and (IedP) correspondence satisfy Maskin’s conditions of monotonicity and no-veto power or not.

3.2.1. Maskin Monotonicity

In the considered examples of SCCs, we begin by examining the implementability of the no-envy correspondence. We provide the following proposition.
Proposition 3 The no-envy correspondence satisfies Maskin monotonicity.
As the no-envy correspondence, the individually rational correspondence from the equal division also satisfies Maskin monotonicity.
Proposition 4 The individually rational correspondence from equal division satisfies Maskin monotonicity.
The proofs of Propositions 3 and 4 are omitted. This is because the no-envy correspondence and the individually rational correspondence from equal division satisfy Maskin monotonicity in the general environment and so it is obvious that this condition is checked for the restricted domain of an allocation problem with single-dipped preferences.
By stability under the intersection of Maskin monotonicity, we give the next proposition.
Proposition 5 The intersection of the no-envy correspondence with the individually rational correspondence from equal division satisfies Maskin monotonicity.
According to Doghmi and Ziad [5], the Pareto correspondence does not satisfy Maskin monotonicity in the domain of the allocation problem with single-dipped preferences, and is hence not Nash implementable2. In the following, we examine whether or not some correspondences which intercept the Pareto correspondence satisfy Maskin monotonicity. We begin by studying the intersection of the Pareto correspondence with the no-envy correspondence. We give the following lemma.
Lemma 3 On a single-dipped domain, the intersection of the Pareto correspondence with the no-envy correspondence is not empty.
Proof. We show that for all R ∈ ℜsd, (PNE)(R) ≠ ∅; i.e., there exists xX such that xP (R) and xNE(R). Suppose not; there exists R ∈ ℜsd, for all xX, xP (R) or xNE(R). Suppose that xP (R) but xNE(R). This means that (a) ∄yX such that for all iN, yiRixi, and for some iN, yiPixi, but (b) there exists a pair {i, j}⊆ N such that xiPixi. Assume that for all iN, xid(Ri) and yid(Ri). For affirmation (a), assume that for some i, xiPiyi, for some j, xjPjyj, and for all kN \{i, j}, ykPkxk. Now, since we have by (b), xiPixi, we consider an allocation zX such that zi = xj, zj = rj(xj), and zk = yk. Thus we have ziPixi, zjj xj, and zkPkxk, and so xP (R), a contradiction. Q.E.D.
Through Proposition 3 and Lemma 3, we complete the proof of the following proposition.
Proposition 6 The intersection of the Pareto correspondence with the no-envy correspondence satisfies Maskin monotonicity.
Now, we examine the intersection of the Pareto correspondence with the individually rational correspondence from equal division. We provide the following lemma.
Lemma 4 On a single-dipped domain, the intersection of the Pareto correspondence with the individually rational correspondence from equal division is not empty.
Proof. By the same reasoning in the proof of Lemma 3, we show that for all R ∈ ℜsd, (PIed)(R) = ∅; i.e., there exists xX such that xP (R) and xIed(R). Suppose not; there exists R ∈ ℜsd, for all xX, xP (R) but xIed(R). This means that (a) ∄yX such that for all iN, yiRixi, and for some iN, yiPixi, but (b) there exists an agent i such that Games 04 00038 i002Pixi. Assume that for all iN, xid(Ri) and yid(Ri), and for some i, j, and for all kN \{i, j}, yk < xj < xi < Games 04 00038 i002 < yi < yjd(Rj) < xkdi(Ri) ≤ d(Rk) (c). Thus, for affirmation (a), we have for some i, xiPiyi, for some j, xjPjyj, and for all kN \{i, j}, ykPkxk. Now, since we have by (b), Games 04 00038 i002Pixi, we consider an allocation zX such that zi = Games 04 00038 i002, zj = xj, and zk = yj. Thus we have ziPixi, zjj xj, and by (c), zk = yj < xkd(Rk), and so zkPkxk, and therefore xP (R), a contradiction. Q.E.D.
Through Proposition 4 and Lemma 4, we complete the proof of the following proposition.
Proposition 7 The intersection of the Pareto correspondence with the individually rational correspondence from equal division satisfies Maskin monotonicity.

3.2.2. No-Veto Power

We check whether the monotonic correspondences satisfy this additional condition for sufficiency or not. We provide the following proposition.
Proposition 8 The no-envy solution, the individually rational correspondence from equal division, (NEIed) correspondence, as well as the intersections of these solutions with the Pareto correspondence all fail to satisfy no-veto power.
Proof. Let R ∈ ℜsd, Ω = 12, x = (0, 0, 12) ∈ X. Let R1 = R2, for these profile, L(xi = 1,2,Ri = 1,2 = [0, Ω]. Figure 2 illustrates such representations. Also, we have xi = 1,2P3x3, hence xNE(R).
For the individually rational correspondence from equal division, we have from Figure 2, L(xi = 1,2,Ri = 1,2 = [0, Ω], but Games 04 00038 i003 P3x3. Hence xIed(R). Thus x ∉ (NEIed)(R). From Proposition 6 in Doghmi and Ziad [5], the Pareto correspondence violates no-veto power and hence the intersections of these solutions with the Pareto correspondence all fail to satisfy no-veto power. Q.E.D.
We conclude that, in the domain of the allocation problem with single-dipped preferences, Maskin’s theorem is silent about the implementability of the monotonic correspondences under consideration. By Theorem 1, all these monotonic correspondences are Nash implementable.

4. Conclusion

We have examined the Nash implementation in an allocation problem with single-dipped preferences. We have shown that, with at least three agents, an SCC is implementable in Nash equilibrium if, and only if, it is Maskin monotonic. We have showed that in this area, some well-known SCCs satisfy Maskin monotonicity, but they violate no-veto power, and so Maskin’s theorem is silent about its implementability. Through our result, the no-veto power condition is no longer required and hence these correspondences are Nash implementable.
Figure 2. The NE correspondence, the Ied correspondence and the (NEIed) correspondence fail to satisfy no-veto power.
Figure 2. The NE correspondence, the Ied correspondence and the (NEIed) correspondence fail to satisfy no-veto power.
Games 04 00038 g002
For future research, the Nash implementation can be examined in an extended class of preferences called single-troughed preferences. This domain of individual preferences is a natural enlargement of the domain of single-dipped preferences. It requires that each agent is indifferent among several bad alternatives. It has been used recently by Manjunath [27] to characterize all rules satisfying unanimity and strategy-proofness properties.

Acknowledgements

I am indebted to two anonymous referees of the journal for remarkably insightful and detailed comments that greatly improved this paper.
  • 1 Also there are well-known correspondences that satisfy neither Maskin monotonicity nor no-veto power. Thus, literature on implementation theory has recently emerged (Matsushima [2], Matsushima [3], Dutta and Sen [4], Doghmi and Ziad [5], Lombardi and Yoshihara [6], Lombardi and Yoshihara [7], Holden et al. [8], Korpela [9]) introducing the notion of partial honesty on the preferences of agents in order to implement this family of correspondences.
  • 2 The Pareto correspondence satisfies the unanimity condition in the domains of the allocation problem with single-dipped and single-plateaued preferences, and so it is Nash implementable with partially honest agents in these domains. For more details, see Doghmi and Ziad [5].

References

  1. Maskin, E. Nash equilibrium and welfare optimality. Working Paper; M.I.T., 1977. Rev. Econ. Stud. 1999, 66, 23–38. [Google Scholar]
  2. Matsushima, H. Role of honesty in full implementation. J. Econ. Theory 2008, 139, 353–359. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Matsushima, H. Behavioral aspects of implementation theory. Econ. Lett. 2008, 100, 161–164. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  4. Dutta, B.; Sen, A. Nash implementation with partially honest individuals. Games Econ. Behav. 2012, 74, 154–169. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  5. Doghmi, A.; Ziad, A. On partially honest Nash implementation in private good economies with restricted domains: A sufficient condition. BE. J. Theor. Econ. 2013. forthcoming. [Google Scholar]
  6. Lombardi, M.; Yoshihara, N. Partially-honest Nash implementation: Characterization results. Working Paper no. 561; Hitotsubashi University: Hitotsubashi, Japan, 2011. [Google Scholar]
  7. Lombardi, M.; Yoshihara, N. Natural implementation with partially honest agents. Working Paper; Hitotsubashi University: Hitotsubashi, Japan, 2012. [Google Scholar]
  8. Holden, R.; Kartik, N.; Tercieux, O. Simple mechanisms and preferences for honesty. Working paper no. 1213-06; Columbia University: New York, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
  9. Korpela, V. Bayesian implementation with partially honest individuals. Working paper; University of Turku: Turun yliopisto, Finland, 2012. [Google Scholar]
  10. Moore, J.; Repullo, R. Nash implementation: a full characterization. Econometrica 1990, 58, 1083–1100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Dutta, B.; Sen, A. A necessary and sufficient condition for two-person Nash implementation. Rev. Econ. Stud. 1991, 58, 121–128. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Sjstrm, T. On the necessary and sufficient conditions for Nash implementation. Soc. Choice Welfare 1991, 8, 333–340. [Google Scholar]
  13. Danilov, V. Implementation via Nash equilibrium. Econometrica 1992, 60, 43–56. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  14. Yamato, T. On Nash implementation of social choice correspondences. Games Econ. Behav. 1992, 4, 484–492. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  15. Ziad, A. On the necessary and sufficient conditions for Nash implementation. Econ. Lett. 1997, 56, 209–213. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  16. Ziad, A. A new necessary condition for Nash implementation. J. Math. Econ. 1998, 29, 381–387. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  17. Thomson, W. Manipulation and Implementation to solutions to the problem of fair allocations when preferences are single-peaked. Working paper, University of Rochester, 1990. [Google Scholar]
  18. Thomson, W. Implementation to solutions to the problem of fair allocations when preferences are single-peaked. Rev. Econ. Design 2010, 14, 1–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  19. Doghmi, A.; Ziad, A. Reexamination of Maskin’s theorem on Nash implementability. Econ. Lett. 2008, 100, 150–152. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Doghmi, A.; Ziad, A. Nash implementation in exchange economies with single-peaked preferences. Econ. Lett. 2008, 100, 157–160. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  21. Black, D. On the rationale of group decision making. J. Public Econ. 1948, 561, 23–34. [Google Scholar]
  22. Inada, K.I. A note on the simple majority decision rule. Econometrica 1964, 32, 525–531. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  23. Klaus, B.; Peters, H.; Storcken, T. Strategy-proof division of a private good when preferences are single-dipped. Econ. Lett. 1997, 55, 339–346. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  24. Klaus, B. Coalitional strategy-proofness in economies with single-dipped preferences and the assignment of an indivisible object. Games Econ. Behav. 2001, 34, 64–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  25. Klaus, B. Population-monotonicity and separability for economies with single-dipped preferences and the assignment of an indivisible object. Econ. Theor. 2001, 17, 675–692. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  26. Ehlers, L. Probabilistic allocation rules and single-dipped preferences. Soc. Choice Welfare 2002, 19, 325–348. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  27. Manjunath, V. Strategic and normative analysis of ressource allocation problems. PhD diss., University of Rechester, New York, 2011. [Google Scholar]
  28. Barberà, S.; Berga, D.; Moreno, B. Domains, ranges and strategy-proofness: the case of single-dipped preferences. Soc. Choice Welfare 2012 39, 335–352.
  29. Foley, D. Resource allocation and the public sector. Yale Econ. Essays 1967, 7, 45–98. [Google Scholar]

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Doghmi, A. Nash Implementation in an Allocation Problem with Single-Dipped Preferences. Games 2013, 4, 38-49. https://doi.org/10.3390/g4010038

AMA Style

Doghmi A. Nash Implementation in an Allocation Problem with Single-Dipped Preferences. Games. 2013; 4(1):38-49. https://doi.org/10.3390/g4010038

Chicago/Turabian Style

Doghmi, Ahmed. 2013. "Nash Implementation in an Allocation Problem with Single-Dipped Preferences" Games 4, no. 1: 38-49. https://doi.org/10.3390/g4010038

APA Style

Doghmi, A. (2013). Nash Implementation in an Allocation Problem with Single-Dipped Preferences. Games, 4(1), 38-49. https://doi.org/10.3390/g4010038

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop