1. Introduction
An unsettled debate in the economics literature is about the role of divorce laws on the probability of marital dissolution, focusing in particular on the big shift in divorce behavior in the United States (US) in the last five decades. Between 1965 and 1980, the divorce rate in the US more than doubled, reaching a rate of around 8 divorces per 1000 adults, before starting to steadily decline alongside the marriage rate. As a reason for this profound change in the divorce rate, a number of empirical works cite that the majority of American states adopted, in the 1970s, looser divorce laws which allowed spouses to unilaterally file for divorce. While Peters found no impact of unilateral divorce laws on divorce rates between 1975 and 1978 [
1], Allen showed, using the same data set, significant and permanent effects when he monitored for geographical differences in divorce propensities [
2]. Using US state-level panel data from 1968 to 1988 to control state and year-fixed effects, as well as state-specific time trends, Friedberg demonstrated that unilateral divorce laws had led to a 6% higher divorce rate, thereby explaining 17% of the increase in divorces [
3]. Later, Gruber found, using the US census data from 1960, 1970, 1980, and 1990, a similar positive effect of the unilateral divorce laws on the stock of divorced women and men [
4]. More recently, using longitudinal data on divorce rates in large samples of European countries, González and Viitanen [
5] and Kneip and Bauer [
6] showed that the results in the literature with significant positive effects of unilateral divorce laws are not pertinent to the US. However, using an extended data set from 1956 to 1998, and adding some variables into the econometric analysis of Friedberg in order to model the dynamic response of divorce explicitly [
3], Wolfers showed that the adoption of unilateral divorce laws increased US divorce rates sharply in the first two years following the adoption, but the effects of this legal change decayed within a decade [
7,
8]. A theoretical explanation (which we will further address in this section) as to why short-term and long-term effects of a policy switch from a mutual consent regime to a unilateral divorce regime may differ was proposed by Rasul [
9].
Given the contradictory results in the empirical literature on the effects of unilateral divorce laws on actual divorce rates, we aim to show in this paper whether the stable matching theory, pioneered by Gale and Shapley [
10], can be used to offer, on the described empirical irregularity, some insights that the other models could be missing. In our model, individuals are heterogeneous due to the nature of the one-to-one matching framework and they have incomplete information about the nontransferable utility of marriage with each of their potential mates.
1 At the beginning of the first period, each individual decides whether to marry or to remain single. Those who married in the first period learn the utility of their marriage at the beginning of the second period and then decide whether to stay married or to divorce for the rest of their lives. We show that divorce costs affect not only individuals’ decision to divorce in the second period but also their first-period decisions to marry, as well as whom to marry. Interestingly, the average probability of marital dissolution in the society is affected by all these three decision channels, which we simply refer to as ”the divorce channel,” ”the marital status channel,” and ”the marital composition channel,” respectively.
We can separate the effect of divorce costs on marital dissolution through the divorce channel, which we call ”the incentive effect,” since the lower the divorce costs, the higher the incentive for married couples to divorce in the second period. In addition, we can also identify in our model a composite effect of divorce costs operating through the other two channels, which we call ”the allocation effect.”. While it is certain that with lower divorce costs more individuals may decide to change their marital status from single to married in the first period, the extent to which any cost effects will be transmitted through the described marital status channel to the average probability of marital dissolution entirely depends on the divorce likelihoods of the new couples relative to those of the existing couples. The same uncertainty is true about the operation of the marital composition channel, which is novel to our study. To isolate the effect of this new channel, we will restrict ourselves to environments where the controlled change in divorce costs induces no impact on the marital status of individuals.
Our results show that the allocative effect of the marital composition channel is indeterminate: even small variations in divorce costs can yield unpredictable, yet significant, changes in the ordinal preferences of individuals over potential mates, consequently changing the identities of the spouses in equilibrium. Not surprisingly, the ambiguity of the allocation effect leads to the ambiguity of the aggregate effect of divorce costs. Thus, it is not true that the average probability of marital dissolution can always be reduced by tighter divorce laws that propose higher divorce costs. Conversely, it is also not true that divorce rates will be higher under looser divorce laws. Indeed, as the main result of our paper shows, we can find, for any society, matching environments and stable matching rules at which the allocation effect of divorce costs outweighs the incentive effect and thus the average probability of marital dissolution is nondecreasing in divorce costs.
The works that most resemble our study by examining the effects of divorce costs on marital dissolution are Bougheas and Georgellis [
12]and Rasul [
9], which both consider a multi-period search theoretic model. While Bougheas and Georgellis allow the individuals to divorce unilaterally [
12], Rasul examines the mutual consent regime, as well, in order to identify the effect of a policy switch to a unilateral divorce regime [
9]. In both studies, the divorce channel and the induced incentive effect (which is called the ”pipeline effect” in [
9]) work in the same unambiguous way as in our model: the lower the divorce costs, the higher the divorce rate of existing couples in the short term.
The marital status channel operates in [
9] by the effect of divorce costs on the reservation signal of individuals, for any signal below which they choose to remain single and draw a new potential match in the next period from the pool of available mates. When divorce costs decrease, the reservation signal of individuals increases, implying better matches among those who choose to marry and, consequently, a fall in the divorce rate. Rasul illustrates how much influence this ’‘selection effect” has on the divorce rate of the newly formed marriages and how it may dominate, in the long run, the pipeline effect of lower divorce costs, thus leading to higher divorce rates among existing married couples [
9].
2 As remarked by Rasul [
9], the tension between the pipeline and the selection effect explains the earlier empirical result of Wolfers [
8]. On the other hand, the marital composition channel is missing in the search theoretic matching models of Bougheas and Georgellis [
12]and Rasul (2006) [
9], since all individuals of the same gender are
ex ante identical and the potential partner of each individual is randomly matched in the pre-marriage stage; thus all possible couples are
ex ante subject to the same likelihood of divorce.
We should finally note that the use of the stable matching theory on the problem of marriage formation and marital dissolution was earlier considered by Mumcu and Saglam [
13]. Their work showed that even small changes in divorce costs that yield insignificant effects on the post-divorce distribution of welfare may lead to wide fluctuations in the marital status of individuals with heterogeneous endowments. Our paper differs from theirs in that utilities in our case are not transferable among individuals. Our work is, to the best of our knowledge, the first attempt to deal with the problem of marital dissolution in a one-to-one matching framework with ”nontransferable” utilities. This framework allows us to study the effect of divorce costs in a society with heterogeneous individuals; in fact, it is solely this heterogeneity that activates the part of the allocation effect of divorce costs operating through the marital composition channel, which is currently missing from the existing search theoretic matching literature.
The organization of the paper is as follows:
Section 2 introduces the model,
Section 3 presents our results, and
Section 4 summarizes the findings.
2. The Model
There are two nonempty, finite and disjoint sets of individuals: a set of men, M and a set of women, W. We assume . The society is denoted by .
Each individual has two periods to live. The beginning of the first period involves a ‘’matching” stage, where individuals enter a marriage market where all matchings between men and women take place. In this stage, the individuals derive their preferences over the potential mates by calculating, the expected utilities of the potential marriages, and according to these preferences, they decide whether to marry or to remain single under a given matching rule. The outcome of this matching rule is a stable matching at which there exists no matched individual who prefers being single to his/her mate and no pair of individuals who are not matched to each other but prefer that they are.
At the beginning of the second period, each married individual enters a ‘’perfect learning” stage where the information about the quality of the marriage is acquired and the individual has to decide, as an optimal response to this new information, whether to stay married or to divorce. We assume that the society has a unilateral divorce regime in which either spouse in a couple has the right to unilaterally end the marriage. For simplicity, we assume that a marriage market does not open in the second period; therefore, individuals that choose to become single in the matching stage will remain single in both periods, whereas married individuals that decide on divorce in the perfect learning stage will become single in the second period. Here, we let
to denote the common discount factor of all individuals for the second period.
3 Before deriving the equilibrium in this two-period matching model, we will describe a matching environment.
2.1. Matching Environment
A matching is a one-to-one function, such that for each , if and only if ; implies and similarly implies . If , then m and w are matched to one another. For any , i is single if . Let denote the set of all matchings for the society N.
For any , we denote by the set of admissible mates in N; i.e., the set of individuals of the opposite gender. Then, for all and for all .
We assume that no individual completely knows in the first period the quality (hence the utility) of any potential marriage. Let denote a random variable representing the perception of individual of the quality of a marriage with individual . For all and , we restrict the support of to the interval and we assume that all individuals know these supports. We let denote the probability density function representing the beliefs of about the quality parameter corresponding to a marriage with . We assume that the densities are all independent. For each , we denote by the corresponding distribution function. We assume that for each and , the beliefs are mutually known to both i and j.
For each individual, a function U maps the type space to reals, with representing the instantaneous utility the individual derives from a marriage with the perceived quality θ. We set the lowest utility individuals may get from marriage to zero, i.e., . Moreover, we assume that is strictly increasing (hence the inverse function is defined and strictly increasing, too).
For each individual, we denote by
the instantaneous utility of being single and by
c the instantaneous divorce costs, which are the same for both men and women.
4 For convenience, we assume
;
i.e., the instantaneous net utility any individual obtains after getting divorced is positive and below his/her instantaneous utility from a marriage with the highest quality. Here, we also assume that each individual knows the list
and that this list is common for all individuals.
For a given society N, a utility-belief structure is described by the list , and a matching environment by the list . Define also the notations and .
2.2. Equilibrium
Below, we will describe the equilibrium in our two-period matching problem, going backwards from the perfect learning stage in the second period to the matching stage in the first period.
Perfect Learning Stage: Individual
who was matched to
in the first period learns the private quality parameter
associated with his or her marriage and decides whether to stay married or to divorce. The net utility in the second period becomes
if individual
i stays married or
if individual
i divorces. So, individual
i decides to stay married to individual
j if and only if
is not below a calculated threshold
, where
We can immediately note that the quality threshold,
, is nonincreasing in divorce costs,
c, and nondecreasing in the instantaneous utility of being single,
.
While we have considered above the decision of individual
i only, a similar decision is also made by individual
j. Therefore, individuals
i and
j remain married in the second period if and only if
. Let
denote the actual utility of individual
i in the second period conditional upon the individuals
i and
j being married in the first period. Clearly,
Matching Stage: Each individual
calculates the two-period expected utility,
, derived from a potential match with individual
. (Note that
is the expectation operator.) In the first period , individual
i does not know the actual value of
, the quality of a marriage with individual
j. Thus, the first period expected utility of individual
i is
. On the other hand, the (discounted) expected value of the second-period utility of individual
i, as calculated in the first period, is
After rearranging the terms in the last equation, we can add the (discounted) second-period expected utility of individual
i (from a marriage with individual
j) to his/her first-period expected utility to obtain
where
denotes the probability that individuals
i and
j will divorce in the second period.
5For notational convenience, we also define for all . Thus, we have defined the expected utility of each individual i derived from a marriage with . Apparently, the preferences represented by these expected utilities are complete and transitive. For any matching environment , we define the list as the preference (or expected utility) profile of N and we denote the associated marriage market by the triple .
We say that a mate is acceptable for at the preference profile if . (Obviously, individual i is acceptable for i.) Given a marriage market , a matching μ is individually rational if for all , the mate is acceptable for individual i. For a given matching μ, is a blocking pair if they are not matched to one another but prefer one another to their matches at μ; i.e., and . A matching is stable if it is individually rational and if there are no blocking pairs.
A well-known theorem by Gale and Shapley shows the existence of a stable matching for every marriage market [
10]. We will require that all matchings realized in the first stage of the first period are stable. This completes the description of the matching stage.
2.3. Gender-Optimal Equilibrium Matchings
As stable matchings in a matching environment are not necessarily unique, we will first restrict ourselves for most of our results to a special selection of equilibrium, namely gender-optimal stable matchings (and the rules that select them), which were first introduced and studied by Gale and Shapley [
10]. However, we will relax this restriction at the end of
Section 3 to show that our main results may hold true under other stable matching rules, as well.
We say that men strictly prefer μ to if all men like μ at least as well as , with at least one man strictly preferring μ to ; i.e., for all , with the inequality being strict for some . We also say that men weakly prefer μ to if either all men strictly prefer μ to or all men are indifferent between μ and , i.e. for all . Similarly, we define strict and weak preference relations for women.
For a given marriage market , a stable matching μ is said to be M-optimal if men weakly prefer μ to any other stable matching. Similarly, a stable matching ν is said to be W-optimal if women weakly prefer ν to any other stable matching. We denote the M-optimal and W-optimal stable matchings for the matching environment Φ by and , respectively. We also say that a stable matching is gender-optimal if it is M-optimal or W-optimal.
We know that in any matching environment Φ where men and women have strict preferences, the ‘’Deferred Acceptance Algorithm” by Gale and Shapley produces
if men propose to women and
if women propose to men [
10].
6Now, for any society we define a matching rule as a function from the set of all matching environments to the set of all matchings. For any matching rule and any matching environment Φ, we denote by the matching selected at the matching environment Φ. We say that a matching rule is the M-optimal matching rule if it selects the M-optimal stable matching at all matching environments; i.e., for all Φ. We also define the W-optimal matching rule, analogously. We denote by and the M-optimal and W-optimal matching rule, respectively.
It must be pointed out that the gender-optimal equilibrium matchings need not be perfectly (positive) assortative in the sense that the married partners have similar characteristics (or derive similar qualities from a marriage to each other). The reason is that under incomplete information, no equilibrium matching – whether it be gender-optimal or not – can be based on any observable characteristics of individuals. In fact, equilibrium matchings in our setup are only determined by the preference orderings of individuals over potential mates, while these orderings depend on the beliefs of individuals over the unobservable qualities of the potential marriages. It is well known from Knuth [
14] that for preference orderings under which gender-optimal equilibrium matchings differ, the
M-optimal stable matching is the least preferred stable matching for women, and oppositely, the
W-optimal stable matching is the least preferred stable matching for men. Thus, the mutual satisfaction of the two sides of the matching problem is not always possible without sacrificing the stability of matchings.
7Before giving our results in the next section, we finally define, using (3), the average probability of marital dissolution in the society
N for the matching environment
under the matching rule
as
where
is the set of women who were not single in the first period. Likewise, we define (abusing the above notation) the average probability of marital dissolution in the society
N for the matching environment
under the matching
μ as
where
.
3. Results
Below, we first observe that the probability of marital dissolution under any given matching is nonincreasing in divorce costs.
Proposition 1. For any society N, any matching environment , and any matching , we have if .
The above proposition follows from (1), (3) and (5) together with the facts that and that for all and . We call this effect, which also works in search theoretic models, the ‘’incentive effect” of divorce costs; since the higher the divorce costs, the higher the incentive for the marriages that were formed in the first period to continue into the second period as well. Indeed, divorcing becomes totally unattractive for the whole society when divorce costs are sufficiently high; i.e., for all N and we have .
The incentive effect is only a partial specification of the relation between divorce costs and marital dissolution, since given any non-constant matching rule
and any matching environment
, a change in divorce costs
c can also change equilibrium matchings
, which we have fixed in the above proposition.
8 This dependence is evident from equations (1) and (2), since a sufficiently large change in divorce costs can change the ‘’ordinal” preferences of the individuals over their potential mates because of the heterogeneity of the individuals’ beliefs and utilities. Naturally, impacts of divorce costs on the equilibrium matchings are also transmitted to the average probability of divorce. We refer to this second effect of divorce costs on the marital dissolution as the ”allocation effect.” Below, we will formally define these two effects.
Given any society
N and any matching environment
, the change in the average probability of marital dissolution under a matching rule
when the cost value is changed from
c to
is given by
where
is the change in the average probability of marital dissolution for the matching environment
due to a change in the matching from
to
, and
is the change in the average probability of marital dissolution under the matching
due to a change in the matching environment from
to
. We call the terms
and
, respectively the allocation and the incentive effect, due to the change in divorce costs from
c to
.
By Proposition 1, we know that the incentive effect is always negative,
i.e.,
if
. In fact, this is an already well-known result. (See, for example, Bougheas and Georgellis [
12] and Rasul [
9]). What we aim to accomplish in the rest of this paper is to find the effect of the marital composition channel on the probability of marital dissolution. To isolate the effect of this new channel, we will consider environments where the controlled change in divorce costs will not affect marital status of individuals in the society. Thus, the allocation effect of divorce costs will arise only through the marital composition channel. We will establish that, unlike the incentive effect, this new effect has an indeterminate sign, as will be evident from the comparison of the results in Examples 1 and 2. Below, we will first show that for any gender-optimal matching rule there exists a matching environment in which the allocation and incentive effect may work in opposite directions.
Example 1. Consider first the
M-optimal matching rule
. Consider a society
N involving
and
with
given by
,
,
, and
where
and
Let
. We compute
. Then, the expected utility profile
is calculated as follows:
| | | | |
| 0.299216 | — | 0.299313 | 0.299314 |
| — | 0.299216 | 0.299314 | 0.299313 |
| 0.299313 | 0.299306 | 0.299216 | — |
| 0.299306 | 0.299313 | — | 0.299216 |
From the above table, it follows that
i.e.,
and
are matched to
and
, respectively. We then compute
. It is interesting to note that the equilibrium matching
does not exhibit positive assortative mating in terms of the individuals’ preferences over stable matchings, since the
W-optimal stable matching swaps the mates of the two men under
;
i.e.,
Now, consider the matching environment
with
. We compute
. Then, the expected utility profile
is calculated as follows:
| | | | |
| 0.299216 | — | 0.299296 | 0.299293 |
| — | 0.299216 | 0.299293 | 0.299296 |
| 0.299296 | 0.299290 | 0.299216 | — |
| 0.299290 | 0.299296 | — | 0.299216 |
It follows that
Here, we should immediately note that
, that is the increase in divorce costs from
c to
leads to a new stable matching that exhibits positive assortative mating in terms of preferences over stable matchings. Now, we calculate
, which is higher than
. We also compute
and
.
Finally, by interchanging the names of men and women in the above society, we can simply get the same result for the W-optimal matching rule , as well. ☐
The allocation effect (obtained exclusively through the marital composition channel) for the above example is positive and it dominates the incentive effect. We thus get the increase in the average probability of divorce. It may seem surprising that even though the rise in divorce costs in the above example changes an initial
M-optimal stable matching – which is the least preferred by women among all stable matchings – to a new
M-optimal stable matching – which is the most preferred stable matching by women – it leads to an increase in the probability of marital dissolution. The underlying reason for this result is that equilibrium matchings in our setup are formed according to the preferences of individuals over prospective mates, represented by the expected utilities of individuals derived from the corresponding marriages. These expected utilities, which are calculated using the beliefs of individuals (represented by some probability density functions) about the unobservable qualities of the potential marriages, depend on all possible moments of the associated probability distributions, while the probability of divorce between couples only depends on a single aspect of these beliefs, namely the size of the lower tail of the couples’ probability distributions at the common quality threshold. Since this particular aspect of the individuals’ beliefs does not summarize all the relevant information in a probability distribution, we inevitably observe an ambiguous relation between individuals’ preferences over equilibrium matchings and the probabilities of divorce at these matchings. These points should be more apparent after examining
Table 1, which reports divorce probabilities in Example 1.
Table 1.
Divorce Probabilities in Example 1 (Probabilities for Matched Pairs in Boldface).
Table 1.
Divorce Probabilities in Example 1 (Probabilities for Matched Pairs in Boldface).
| | |
| | | | |
| 0.396980 | 0.396624 | 0.396656 | 0.396376 |
| 0.396624 | 0.397013 | 0.396376 | 0.396656 |
The above table shows that although the divorce probability decreased for all potential couples in the society in response to an increase in divorce costs from to , the change of matchings from to caused the divorce probabilities of the matched couples to rise. Please note that if the couples and , which are married when the cost of divorce is c, remained married when the cost of divorce is , the divorce probability of each couple would fall from to (the incentive effect). However, the matchings did not remain the same when divorce costs were increased. The reason is that the preference orderings of both men changed completely, despite the rise in the divorce cost being extremely small. At the higher cost level , the married couples turn out to be and , each of which faces a divorce probability of instead of (the allocation effect). As the allocation effect dominates the incentive effect, the average probability of divorce becomes higher under the increased divorce costs. Examining the setup in Example 1, we may further note that the increase in divorce costs slightly changes the quality threshold (the sole determinant of divorce probabilities), thereby reducing it from the level to only. At both matching environments and , the beliefs of the individuals about the quality of potential marriages are such that the cumulative probabilities between the two quality thresholds are almost zero, i.e., and ; therefore, for each potential couple, the probability of divorce, as defined in equation (3), falls only insignificantly in response to a small decrease in the quality thresholds (the incentive effect). Consequently, the incentive effect that is always negative becomes inadequate in size to outweigh the allocation effect that turns out to be positive for this example.
Our next proposition below generalizes Example 1 to state that for any gender-optimal matching rule and for any society there exists a matching environment where increases in divorce costs may raise the average probability of marital dissolution.
Proposition 2. For any society N and a given gender-optimal matching rule where , there exists a matching environment and divorce costs such that we have .
Proof. Consider first the
M-optimal matching rule
. Consider the society
N with the list
in Example 1. Let
be any larger society such that
and
with at least one of the inclusions being strict. Consider the two cost values
and
. Consider the list
such that
,
, and
. (Thus, we have extended all utility specifications for
N in Example 1 to
.) By this construction, we have
and
. Now, let
if
and
. Moreover, for all
such that
, let
, where
Then, we have
and
for all
such that
. Since we also have
for all
, it follows that under both
c and
, all individuals in
will decide to remain single in both periods. Thus, we have
and
for all
(with
and
defined in Example 1), and
for all
. It then follows that
and
. Finally, by interchanging the names of all men and women above, we can simply get the desired result for the
W-optimal matching rule
, as well. ☐
The above proposition shows that there are environments in which a policy change that decreases divorce costs, which are clearly a pure deadweight loss, is Pareto improving. However, the following example shows that there are also matching environments in which the opposite conclusion is true; i.e., an increase in divorce costs reduces the average probability of marital dissolution. We show that in such environments the allocation effect (through the marital composition channel) turns out to be negative under gender-optimal matching rules.
Example 2. Consider first the
M-optimal matching rule
. Consider a society
N involving
and
with
given by
,
,
, and
where
and
Let
. We compute
. Then, the expected utility profile
is calculated as follows:
| | | | |
| 0.299216 | — | 0.307935 | 0.307887 |
| — | 0.299216 | 0.308197 | 0.308259 |
| 0.307935 | 0.308197 | 0.299216 | — |
| 0.308259 | 0.307887 | — | 0.299216 |
From the above table, it follows that
We then compute
.
Note that the equilibrium matching
) does not exhibit positive assortative mating, since the optimal stable matching from the viewpoint of women is
Now, consider the matching environment
such that
. We compute
. Then, the expected utility profile
is calculated as follows:
| | | | |
| 0.299216 | — | 0.302274 | 0.303467 |
| — | 0.299216 | 0.303424 | 0.302192 |
| 0.302274 | 0.303424 | 0.299216 | — |
| 0.302192 | 0.303467 | — | 0.299216 |
It follows that
Here, we have
, that is the increase in divorce costs from
c to
leads the society to an equilibrium that exhibits positive assortative mating. We can now calculate
,
and
.
Finally, by interchanging the names of men and women in the above society, we can simply get the same result for the W-optimal matching rule , as well. ☐
Interestingly, the rise in divorce costs changes in Example 2, like in the previous example, a non-positive assortative mating to a positive assortative mating in terms of preferences over stable matchings. Despite this striking similarity, the sign of the allocation effect is different in the two examples, because of the nontrivial differences in the heterogeneous beliefs of the individuals.
Table 2.
Divorce Probabilities in Example 2 (Probabilities for Matched Pairs in Boldface).
Table 2.
Divorce Probabilities in Example 2 (Probabilities for Matched Pairs in Boldface).
| | |
| | | | |
| 0.644968 | 0.660223 | 0.607185 | 0.597440 |
| 0,674823 | 0.660223 | 0.587452 | 0.597440 |
Table 2 above shows that the probability of divorce decreased for all potential couples in the society in response to a rise of the cost of divorce from
to
. If the couples
and
, which are married when the cost of divorce is
c, remained to be married when the cost of divorce is
, the divorce probability would fall from
to
for the first couple, from
to
for the second couple, and from
to
for the society as a whole (the incentive effect). However, at the cost level
, the married couples change to
and
, which face the divorce probabilities
and
, respectively. Thus, at higher divorce costs, the society is facing an average divorce probability of
instead of
(the allocation effect). Since the allocation effect for this example is negative like the incentive effect, the average probability of divorce becomes lower under the increased divorce costs. We should also note that, unlike in Example 1, the increase in divorce costs changes the quality threshold significantly, thereby reducing it from the level
to
. Moreover, at both matching environments
and
, the beliefs of the individuals about the quality of potential marriages are such that the change in the cumulative probabilities between the two quality thresholds is not negligible (
i.e.,
and
), therefore for each potential couple, the probability of divorce, as defined in equation (3), falls significantly (the incentive effect). Apparently, the observed negative sign of the allocation effect in Example 2 has sufficed for the decrease in the average probability of divorce. However, such a result does not necessarily hinge upon the sign of the allocation effect. In fact, what is failing in the case of Example 1 as to the surprising effect of divorce costs on the average probability of divorce is not that the sign of the allocation effect is positive, but rather that the reduction in divorce costs is not sufficiently high to ensure that the induced incentive effect will be adequately large to outweigh a positive allocation effect.
We will finally discuss whether our main results in Example 1 and Proposition 2 may still hold when the matchings in the society are determined by a stable matching rule that is not gender optimal. Since such rules have not been explicitly studied in the one-to-one matching literature, we need to construct one that will suffice for our purpose. Nevertheless, we will first give some helpful structures, adapted from Roth and Sotomayor [
15].
For each matching environment
and each pair of matchings
μ and
in
, we define the join,
, as the function that assigns each man to his mate at the most preferred of these matchings, and the meet,
as the function that assigns each man to his mate at the least preferred of the two matchings;
i.e.,
and
Now, consider any society involving
and
with
, and any matching environment Φ. For any pair of matchings
and
, define a number
such that
if there exists no integer
such that
for all
, and
, otherwise. Clearly, for any pair of matchings
and
, we have
if
. Now, consider the matching rule, denoted by
: If there exists a unique pair of stable matchings
and
such that
,
and
, then let
and otherwise let
. Below, we will show that the result in Example 1 is valid under the matching rule
, as well.
Example 3. Consider a society
N involving
and
with
given by
,
,
, and
where
and
Let
. We compute
. Then, the expected utility profile
is calculated as follows:
| | | | | | | | |
| 0.299216 | — | — | — | 0.299313 | 0.299314 | 0.299199 | 0.299199 |
| — | 0.299216 | — | — | 0.299314 | 0.299313 | 0.299199 | 0.299199 |
| — | — | 0.299216 | — | 0.299199 | 0.299199 | 0.299313 | 0.299314 |
| — | — | — | 0.299216 | 0.299199 | 0.299199 | 0.299314 | 0.299313 |
| 0.299313 | 0.299306 | 0.299199 | 0.299199 | 0.299216 | — | — | — |
| 0.299306 | 0.299313 | 0.299199 | 0.299199 | — | 0.299216 | — | — |
| 0.299199 | 0.299199 | 0.299313 | 0.299306 | — | — | 0.299216 | — |
| 0.299199 | 0.299199 | 0.299306 | 0.299313 | — | — | — | 0.299216 |
For the above environment, there are only four stable matchings given by
It is easy to check that
and
. Moreover,
. Therefore,
. We then compute
.
Now, consider the matching environment
with
. We compute
. Then, the expected utility profile
is calculated as follows:
| | | | | | | | |
| 0.299216 | — | — | — | 0.299296 | 0.299293 | 0.299199 | 0.299199 |
| — | 0.299216 | — | — | 0.299293 | 0.299296 | 0.299199 | 0.299199 |
| — | — | 0.299216 | — | 0.299199 | 0.299199 | 0.299296 | 0.299293 |
| — | — | — | 0.299216 | 0.299199 | 0.299199 | 0.299293 | 0.299296 |
| 0.299296 | 0.299290 | 0.299199 | 0.299199 | 0.299216 | — | — | — |
| 0.299290 | 0.299296 | 0.299199 | 0.299199 | — | 0.299216 | — | — |
| 0.299199 | 0.299199 | 0.299296 | 0.299290 | — | — | 0.299216 | — |
| 0.299199 | 0.299199 | 0.299290 | 0.299296 | — | — | — | 0.299216 |
It is easy to check that the only stable matching at this preference profile is
By the definition of
, we have
. Now, we can calculate
, which is higher than
. Finally, we compute
and
. ☐
As should be obvious from the proof of Proposition 2, one can generalize Example 3 such that given the described matching rule and an arbitrary society involving at least four men and four women, there always exists a matching environment where increases in divorce costs would raise the average probability of marital dissolution.