The Intermediate Value Theorem and Decision-Making in Psychology and Economics: An Expositional Consolidation
Abstract
:Cauchy and Bolzano pioneered the transformation of the work of 18th-century analysts into 19th-century rigor. Their work is an example of simultaneous discovery: simultaneous announcement of their program for rigorizing analysis, their definitions of continuous functions and their common desire to prove the intermediate value theorem. Both accepted Lagrange’s goal of reducing the calculus to the “algebraic analysis of finite quantities”.Grabiner (1984)1
Mathematics is not about anything in particular; it is instead the logically connected study of abstract systems. There were revolutions in thought which changed mathematicians’ views about the nature of mathematical truth, and about what could or should be proved—one such revolution occurred between the 18th and 19th nineteenth centuries: a rejection of the mathematics of powerful techniques and novel results in favor of the mathematics of clear definitions and rigorous proofs.Grabiner (1974)2
1. Introduction
Grabiner [1] makes clear that Lagrange’s theorem was limited to polynomials, and that the intermediate value theorem (IVT) in its modern form was independently discovered and rigorously proved only later by [3,4]. We furnish a version given in [5], and typically taught to incoming undergraduates in mathematics.4If we have any equation, and if we know two numbers such that, if they are successfully substituted for the unknown in that equation, they give results of opposite signs, the equation will necessarily have at least one real root whose value will be between those two numbers.3
In short, this literature, along with the other economic one, can also be related to Rosenthal’s 1955 theorem and viewed as uplifting of insights and results for functions to binary relations, and to use this to connect the solvability postulate to the IVP, and thereby to effect a synthesis of sorts of unconnected results in mathematical economics and mathematical psychology.14 In a nutshell, in keeping with the theme of understanding the richness of a structure, the connections of the continuity postulate and the solvability to the IVP that we forge, provide a novel overview of the subject summarized in four portmanteau theorems.15 It is the lens through which the equivalence of these postulates for binary relations can now be viewed.Solvability is reminiscent of the intermediate value property of continuous real-valued functions. Without richness conditions such as solvability … axiomatizations become considerably more complex.(p. 5)
2. The IVT and Its Generalizations
2.1. The Classical Theorem
2.2. Beyond Continuous Functions
2.3. A Topological and Algebraic Conception
2.4. A Measure-Theoretic Conception
- (LT1)
- For each and there is a measurable subset A of S such that
- (LT2)
- For each there is a and a measurable subset A of S such that
- (LT3)
- For each there is a measurable subfamily such that whenever and for each
2.5. More on Finite-Dimensional Spaces
3. The IVP in Psychology and Economics
3.1. Binary Relations: Preliminaries
3.2. IVP for Binary Relations
3.3. A Restricted IVP in Measurement Theory
4. The Principal Results
4.1. Equivalence Theorems for Functions
- (a)
- continuity ⇒ linear continuity ⇒ IVP ⇒ restricted solvability,
- (b)
- linear continuity ⇒ separate continuity ⇒ restricted solvability,
- (c)
- continuity ⇒ strong IVP ⇒ IVP ⇒ weak IVP.
4.2. Equivalence Theorems for Binary Relations
- (a)
- Graph continuity ⇔ continuity ⇒ linear continuity ⇔ mixture continuity ⇒ Archimedean and separate continuity and weak Wold continuity and IVP
- (b)
- Continuity ⇒ Wold-continuity ⇔ strong IVP and order denseness ⇒ weak Wold-continuity ⇔ IVP and order denseness ⇒ Archimedean
- (c)
- Separate continuity or IVP ⇒ restricted solvability
5. Proofs of the Results
- (a)
- The statement that continuity implies linear continuity, and that IVP implies restricted solvability follow from their definitions. Next, we show that linear continuity implies IVP. Pick and such that . Since f is linearly continuous, it is continuous on the straight line segment connecting x and y. Consider the following sets: and . These sets are non-empty, disjoint and open in . If there is no such that , these two sets is an open covering of . Since is a connected set, this furnishes us a contradiction. Therefore, f satisfies the IVP.
- (b)
- The argument that linear continuity implies separate continuity follows from their definitions. Next, we show that separate continuity implies restricted solvability. Separate continuity implies that f is continuous in any line parallel to any coordinate axis, and restricted solvability is implied by the fact that IVP holds on any given index. Hence, Theorem 2 completes the proof.
- (c)
- The strong IVP implies the IVP, and the IVP implies the weak IVP follow from their definitions. It remains to prove that continuity implies the strong IVP. Pick , a curve connecting x and y and such that . Consider the following sets: and . These sets are non-empty, disjoint and open in . If there is no such that , these two sets are an open covering of . Since a curve is a connected set, this furnishes us a contradiction. Therefore, f satisfies the strong IVP.
6. Conclusions
- (i)
- if either (a) , (b) and there exists such that and or (c) and there exists such that and
- (ii)
- If neither nor then
The first open direction of work that we want to single out is whether, and how, the consolidated theory of equivalences between continuity, solvability and intermediate valuedness presented in this paper carries over to a semiorder.The concept of semiorder originally appeared in 1914–albeit under a different name–in the work of Fishburn and Monjardet (1992) and Wiener (1914). Nowadays, a semiorder is equivalently defined as either a reflexive and complete relation that is Ferrers and semitransitive (sometimes called a weak semiorder), or an asymmetric relation that is Ferrers and semitransitive (sometimes called a strict semiorder).48
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
Appendix A. An Abbreviated Listing
1 | See the concluding paragraph on page 120 in Grabiner [1]. The last sentence of the epigraph is taken from the third full paragraph on page 111 in the same reference. This is an important historical reference on the IVT that goes into the similarity and the dissimilarity of the investigations of Bolzano and Cauchy, after subscribing to Lagrange’s influence on both. |
2 | See Grabiner [2] (p. 355). She asks whether “mathematical truth is time-dependent [and highlights] how 19th-century mathematicians looked at 18th-century approximations as a construction of the solution, and therefore as a proof of its existence”. It explicitly mentions Cauchy’s proof of the IVT in this connection; see pages 361–362. |
3 | See Grabiner [1] (p. 114), and for the precise reference to Lagrange’s text, see her Footnote 54. Cauchy’s interventions in the discourse of mathematics bears an obvious parallel to the interventions of Gerard Debreu in the discourse of economic theory, a parallel surely worth further investigation. |
4 | As Barany [6] notes: “Today the intermediate value theorem [IVT] is one of the first theorems about functions that advanced undergraduates learn in courses on mathematical analysis. These courses in turn are often the first places such students are comprehensively taught the methods of rigorous proof at the heart of contemporary mathematics”. |
5 | See Barany [6] referring to Grabiner [7]. Barany [8] had already read Cauchy’s introduction to his Cours d’analyse as a “rich snapshot of a scholarly paradigm in transition, a prefatory drama that attempts to rework the ground of an entire discipline”: a drama in three acts and three paragraphs. The engine of this interesting reading is the double meaning and the evolution of the terms geometry and algebra as they play out in (i) curricular developments reflecting theory and practice, (ii) the role of algebra within mathematics, and (ii) the epistemological positioning of mathematics in systems of knowledge. |
6 | The phrasing of the result in the geometric register as the intersection of two lines as opposed to the existence and computation of the root of an equation in an algebraic one; see Footnote 16 in [8] and the text it footnotes. He writes, “The crucial distinction between geometry and algebra, for Cauchy, signified far more than the contrast between unguarded formalism and rigorous foundations. The difference comes from the double meaning, dating to the early Moderns, of the two terms”. Also see [7]. In addition to Cauchy’s two proofs, it has also been well-noted that he used infinitesimally small quantities in his definition of continuity, and thereby can be seen as one of the worthy precursors of Abraham Robinson’s nonstandard analysis; see [9] and Footnotes 12 and 4 in [6,8], respectively. Also see Note 7 below. |
7 | As emphasized to the authors by David Ross, one can prove results of the form “if f satisfies the IVP and some property then f is continuous”. for example, can be “ is closed for every x in a dense set” or “f is injective”. Ross adds that “These results allow pretty, natural, and practically trivial nonstandard proofs”. The first conditions was first discovered by [10]; on this see also [11,12]. We are grateful to David Ross for bringing these references to our attention. |
8 | |
9 | To wit, the “hiddenness” of completeness when non-degeneracy, transitivity and continuity is assumed; or that of full transitivity when non-degeneracy, partial transitivity and continuity is assumed, all in the setting of topological connectedness. It is this connection that is made transparent in [18]. In this connection, also see Preface and the opening sections of [19]. |
10 | |
11 | As detailed in [18,22] is a crucial complementary input to this point of view, and by now a comprehensive overview, pertaining not only to his original contribution, but also for bi-preferences and hybrid structures inspired by [23], is well-documented in the literature; see [18,24,25,26,27,28] and their references. |
12 | |
13 | The papers of [29,30] sighted above are surely relevant here. This viewpoint can also be discerned in the recent survey of Moscati (2016) on the one hand, and that expressed in the survey of Karni, Maccheroni, and Marinacci (2015) on the other. It goes quite a way back to Krantz-Luce-Suppes-Tversky [35] and their followers. |
14 | |
15 | |
16 | See [43], and a topological elaboration of some of Sen’s non-topological results in [18]. As to alternative phrasing and incorporation of the IVT where one would not always expect it, see [19,44]. Lax’s alternative formulation of the result is especially illuminating for the ideas pursued in this paper. |
17 | |
18 | This is already apparent to a careful reader if he or she compares the proof in [47,48], on the one hand, and that in [30] on the other. Nash sees his second proof as a “considerable improvement” over his first, something that can also be related to Cauchy’s proofs of the IVT as highlighted in [6,8], and also referred to in Note 6. |
19 | See Theorem 1 of Chapter 2 of [49]. The application highlighted the importance of what are now referred to as the Inada conditions, and also of the importance of the assumption that the marginal productivity of capital goes to zero as capital becomes arbitrarily large. |
20 | See Chapter 4 titled “The state of steady economic growth”. As such, Meade’s analysis has a resonance with the discussion of Bolzano and Cauchy in [1]; also see Note 6 on the quarrel between geometry and analysis. |
21 | See Chapter 2 in [50]. Whereas the Arrow-Hahn demonstration went against the grain of the self-congratulatory equivalence between the GND lemma and the Brouwer fixed point theorem, its primary importance lies in looking beyond the work of the fifties towards constructive proofs and speeds of convergence. The pioneering papers of [30,48,51,52] all applied tailor-made fixed-point theorems of Brouwer, Kakutani and Eilenberg-Montgomery to prove existence theorems in Walrasian competitive analysis and Cournot-Nash non-cooperative game theory. It was clearly understood by [53] that the Gale-Nikaido-Debreu lemma forms one possible underpinning of the very notion of a Walrasian equilibrium; see [54] and its references for a discussion of the Gale-Nikaido-Debreu lemma, as well as [55] for a reception of Uzawa’s result in Walrasian theory, and [56] for a narrative of the history of the problematic. Also see Note 54 below. |
22 | |
23 | In this connection we may point out that while the basic observation is already implicit in the raw and primitive Bolzano-Cauchy version of the IVP furnished above, the interval is not rich enough to provide a further and fuller elaboration. An execution of this observation for functions with a finite-dimensional Euclidean domain and one-dimensional range admitting of a veritable diversity of continuity assumptions is provided in Section 4.1. The execution of this observation for generalizations of Bolzano’s theorem to higher dimensional settings (finite or infinite) in the spirit of Poincaré-Miranda’s theorem is still an open problem. |
24 | See the importance, and the priority of Otto Holder in [40]. Also see some relevant references in Note 11. |
25 | The following convention is being maintained throughout the paper: none of the named theorems are new and all of the lettered theorems and numbered propositions are original. |
26 | |
27 | When X is Hausdorff, it follows from being compact and being Hausdorff that m is a homeomorphism between and Hence, these two spaces are homeomorphic; see for example Willard [68] (Theorem 17.14, p. 123). |
28 | It is clear that an equivalent definition can be provided by replacing with closed sets. |
29 | In deference to Herstein–Milnor [23], lower case Greek letters consistently denote real numbers in [0, 1]. |
30 | See Chapter (1; p. 51). |
31 | See [72] for the proof of Liapounoff’s theorem using signed measures. For an infinite-dimensional Banach space that is not necessarily separable nor has the Radon-Nikodym property, [73] identifies a saturated measure space which is necessary and sufficient for the conclusions of Liapounoff’s theorem. |
32 | The fact that Brouwer’s theorem follows from the Borsuk–Ulam theorem seems to be folklore; see for example [75,76,77]. Note also that the Poincaré–Miranda theorem is equivalent to Brouwer’s theorem is well-known; see for example [78]. See also [79] for an extended survey on the application of the Borsuk–Ulam theorem. |
33 | |
34 | For vectors x and y, “” means in every component; “” means and ; and “” means in every component. |
35 | |
36 | A straight line in X is the intersection of a one dimensional affine subspace of and X. |
37 | Ref. [88] use a version of the Archimedian assumption in their theory. There are many versions of the axiomatics of the expected utility theory. Nash and Marschak use weak Wold-continuity while [23] use mixture continuity; see [89] for a review of this literature and [31] for a history of axiomatics of the expected utility theory. |
38 | |
39 | See the use of IVP as a sufficient condition for continuity property in Note 7. |
40 | The examples are important benchmarks of a rich trajectory dating to Cauchy in the early part of the 18th-century. The fact that continuity is stronger than separate continuity was, even then in the time of Cauchy, standard material in textbooks on multivariate calculus, but an investigation of the relationship between continuity and more general restricted continuity properties of a function constituted a rich development to which many mathematicians, including Heine, Baire and Lebesgue, contributed; see for example [20] and the recent detailed survey of [92]. |
41 | |
42 | A polyhedron is a subset of that is an intersection of a finite number of closed half-spaces. |
43 | A function on a subset X of is weakly monotone if implies for all , where ≥ if the usual relation in ; see Note 34 for details. |
44 | The interiority assumption is essential to show separate continuity implies continuity. To see this, let and is defined as for and for . Note that X is convex and bounded by ≥, and f is weakly monotone. Since the restriction of f on any line parallel to a coordinate axis is a singleton, f is separately continuous. However, it is clear that f is discontinuous. |
45 | These two papers generalize and unify the existing partial equivalence results among the postulates on preferences. For the relationship between Wold-continuity and continuity under a monotonicity assumption, see for example [45,46,96]; for a partial relationship between Archimedean, mixture continuity and continuity postulates under convexity or cone-monotonicity assumptions, see for example [97,98,99,100]; and for the relationship between continuity and graph continuity, see [101,102,103,104,105], and also [106,107,108] for a state-of-the-art characterization without completeness or transitivity assumptions on preferences. For a detailed reference on the antecedent results, see [20,21]. |
46 | For details, see [21]. |
47 | This statement can be proved by using Corollary 1 on the converse of the IVT on an interval under the weak monotonicity assumption; we present a direct proof here for the convenience of the reader. |
48 | Ref. [110] note that the “notion is usually attributed to Luce (1956), who formally defined a semiorder in 1956 as a pair of binary relations satisfying suitable properties. The reason that motivated Luce to introduce such a structure was to study choice models in settings where economic agents exhibit preferences with an intransitive indifference;" see also [111] for a representation theorem for intransitive indifference relations. |
49 | |
50 | |
51 | |
52 | See Footnotes 19 and 20 and the text they footnote. |
53 | |
54 | The Arrow–Hahn proof can be usefully contrasted with the reconstruction of Wald’s proof presented in [124]. The evident irony in Hildenbrand’s citation of the IVT for a correspondence will not escape even the casual reader. For Arrow–Hahn, see Note 21 above. Note that the essentials of Chapter 2 of Arrow-Hahn were already available in Arrow’s Northwestern Lectures given in July 1962; see [125]. |
55 | See [126] and her references for further details on recursive equilibria in economics. |
56 | This appears as Corollary 1.4 in Rockafellar’s 1970 entry. |
57 |
References
- Grabiner, J.V. Cauchy and Bolzano: Tradition and transformation in the history of mathematics. In Transformation and Tradition in the Sciences: Essays in Honor of I. Bernard Cohen; Medelsohn, E., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1984; Volume 4, pp. 105–124. [Google Scholar]
- Grabiner, J.V. Is mathematical truth time-dependent? Am. Math. Mon. 1974, 81, 354–365. [Google Scholar]
- Bolzano, B. Rein Analytisches Beweis des Lehrsatzes dass Zwischen je Zwey Werthen, Die ein Entgegengesetzetes Resultat Gewähren, Wenigsten eine Reelle Wurzel der Gleichung Liege; Gottlieb Haase: Prague, Czech Republic, 1817. [Google Scholar]
- Cauchy, A.-L. Cours d’analyse de l’École Royale Polytechnique; de l’Imprimerie Royale: Paris, France, 1821. [Google Scholar]
- Vrahatis, M.N. Intermediate value theorem for simplices for simplicial approximation of fixed points and zeros. Topol. Its Appl. 2020, 275, 107036. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Barany, M.J. Stuck in the middle: Cauchy’s intermediate value theorem and the history of analytic rigor. Not. Am. Math. Soc. 2013, 60, 1334–1338. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Grabiner, J.V. The Origins of Cauchy’s Rigorous Calculus; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1981. [Google Scholar]
- Barany, M.J. God, king, and geometry: Revisiting the introduction to Cauchy’s Cours d’analyse. Hist. Math. 2011, 38, 368–388. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Laugwitz, D. Infinitely small quantities in Cauchy’s textbooks. Hist. Math. 1987, 14, 258–274. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Rowe, C. Note on a pair of properties which characterize continuous functions. Bull. Am. Math. Soc. 1926, 32, 285–287. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Fine, N. Continuity from Darboux property and closedness of g−1(r). Am. Math. Mon. 1966, 73, 782. [Google Scholar]
- Velleman, D.J. Characterizing continuity. Am. Math. Mon. 1997, 104, 318–322. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Yannakakis, M. Equilibria, fixed points, and complexity classes. Comput. Sci. Rev. 2009, 3, 71–85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Morales, C.H. A Bolzano’s theorem in the new millennium. Nonlinear Anal. Theory Methods Appl. 2002, 51, 679–691. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Turzański, M. The Bolzano–Poincaré–Miranda theorem–discrete version. Topol. Its Appl. 2012, 159, 3130–3135. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Eilenberg, S. Ordered topological spaces. Am. Math. 1941, 63, 39–45. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rosenthal, A. On the continuity of functions of several variables. Math. Z. 1955, 63, 31–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Khan, M.A.; Uyanik, M. Topological connectedness and behavioral assumptions on preferences: A two-way relationship. Econ. Theory 2021, 71, 411–460. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Chinn, W.G.; Steenrod, N.E. First Concepts of Topology: The Geometry of Mappings of Segments, Curves, Circles, and Disks; MAA: Washington, DC, USA, 1966; Volume 18. [Google Scholar]
- Uyanik, M.; Khan, M.A. The continuity postulate in economic theory: A deconstruction and an integration. J. Math. Econ. 2022, 102704. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ghosh, A.; Khan, M.A.; Uyanik, M. Continuity postulates and solvability axioms in economic theory and in mathematical psychology: A consolidation of the theory of individual choice. Theory Decis. 2022. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schmeidler, D. A condition for the completeness of partial preference relations. Econometrica 1971, 39, 403–404. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Herstein, I.N.; Milnor, J. An axiomatic approach to measurable utility. Econometrica 1953, 21, 291–297. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Galaabaatar, T.; Khan, M.A.; Uyanik, M. Completeness and transitivity of preferences on mixture sets. Math. Soc. Sci. 2019, 99, 49–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Giarlotta, A.; Watson, S. A bi-preference interplay between transitivity and completeness: Reformulating and extending Schmeidler’s theorem. J. Math. Psychol. 2020, 96, 102354. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Khan, M.A.; Uyanik, M. On an extension of a theorem of Eilenberg and a characterization of topological connectedness. Topol. Its Appl. 2020, 273, 107–117. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Khan, M.A.; Uyanik, M. Binary relations in mathematical economics: On continuity, additivity and monotonicity postulates in Eilenberg, Villegas and DeGroot. In Positivity and Its Applications; Kikianty, E., Mokhwetha, M., Messerschmidt, M., Walt, J.H.V., Wortel, M., Eds.; Birkhäuser: Basel, Switzerland, 2021; pp. 229–250. [Google Scholar]
- Uyanik, M.; Khan, M.A. On the consistency and the decisiveness of the double-minded decision-maker. Econ. Lett. 2019, 185, 108657. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Marschak, J. Rational behavior, uncertain prospects, and measurable utility. Econometrica 1950, 18, 111–141. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nash, J.F. Non-cooperative games. Ann. Math. 1951, 54, 286–295. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bleichrodt, H.; Moscati, C.L.I.; Wakker, P.P. Nash was a first to axiomatize expected utility. Theory Decis. 2016, 81, 309–312. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Fishburn, P.; Wakker, P. The invention of the independence condition for preferences. Manag. Sci. 1995, 41, 1130–1144. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Luce, R.D.; Tukey, J.W. Simultaneous conjoint measurement: A new type of fundamental measurement. J. Math. Psychol. 1964, 1, 1–27. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Suppes, P. A set of independent axioms for extensive quantities. Port. Math. 1951, 10, 163–172. [Google Scholar]
- Krantz, D.; Luce, D.; Suppes, P.; Tversky, A. Foundations of Measurement, Volume I: Additive and Polynomial Representations; Academic Press: New York, NY, USA, 1971. [Google Scholar]
- Abdellaoui, M.; Wakker, P. Savage for dummies and experts. J. Econ. Theory 2020, 186, 104991. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Karni, E. Axiomatic foundations of expected utility and subjective probability. In Handbook of the Economics of Risk and Uncertainty; Machina, M., Viscusi, K., Eds.; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2014; Volume 1, pp. 1–39. [Google Scholar]
- Karni, E.; Maccheroni, F.; Marinacci, M. Ambiguity and nonexpected utility. In Handbook of Game Theory with Economic Applications; Young, H.P., Zamir, S., Eds.; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2015; Volume 4, pp. 901–947. [Google Scholar]
- Karni, E.; Schmeidler, D. Utility theory with uncertainty. In Handbook of Mathematical Economics; Hildenbrand, W., Sonnenschein, H., Eds.; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1991; Volume 4, pp. 1763–1831. [Google Scholar]
- Moscati, I. Measuring Utility; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Thurstone, L.L. The nature of general intelligence and ability (III). Br. J. Psychol. 1924, 14, 243. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Thurstone, L.L. The vectors of mind. Psychol. Rev. 1934, 41, 1–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Sen, A. Collective Choice and Social Welfare: An Expanded Edition; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Lax, P.D. Change of variables in multiple integrals. Am. Math. Mon. 1999, 106, 497–501. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wold, H. A synthesis of pure demand analysis, I–III. Scand. Actuar. J. 1943–1944, 26–27, 69–120, 220–263. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wold, H.; Jureen, L. Demand Analysis; John Wiley and Sons, Inc.: New York, NY, USA, 1953. [Google Scholar]
- Debreu, G. A social equilibrium existence theorem. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 1952, 38, 886–893. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Nash, J.F. Equilibrium points in n-person games. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 1950, 36, 48–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Burmeister, E.; Dobell, A.R. Mathematical Theories of Economic Growth; MacMillan: New York, NY, USA, 1970. [Google Scholar]
- Arrow, K.J.; Hahn, F.H. General Competitive Analysis; North-Holland: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1971. [Google Scholar]
- Arrow, K.J.; Debreu, G. Existence of an equilibrium for a competitive economy. Econometrica 1954, 22, 265–290. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McKenzie, L.W. On equilibrium in Graham’s model of world trade and other competitive systems. Econometrica 1954, 22, 147–161. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Uzawa, H. Walras’ existence theorem and Brouwer fixed-point theorem. Econ. Stud. Q. 1962, 13, 59–62. [Google Scholar]
- Le, T.; Pham, C.L.N.-S.; Saglam, C. Direct proofs of the existence of equilibrium, the Gale-Nikaido-Debreu lemma and the fixed point theorems using Sperner’s lemma. Hal Work. 2020. Available online: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/345492942_Direct_Proofs_of_the_Existence_of_Equilibrium_the_Gale-Nikaido-Debreu_Lemma_and_the_Fixed_Point_Theorems_using_Sperner’s_Lemma (accessed on 7 May 2022).
- Khan, M.A.; McLean, R.P.; Uyanik, M. The KKM lemma and the Fan-Browder theorems: Equivalences and some circular tours. Linear Nonlinear Anal. 2021, 7, 33–62. [Google Scholar]
- Khan, M.A. On the Finding of an Equilibrium: Düppe-Weintraub and the Problem of Scientific Credit. J. Econ. Lit. 2020, 1, 1–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hahn, H.; Rosenthal, A. Set Functions; University of New Mexico Press: Albuquerque, NM, USA, 1948. [Google Scholar]
- Mizel, V.J.; Martin, A.D. A representation theorem for certain nonlinear functionals. Arch. Ration. Anal. 1964, 15, 353–367. [Google Scholar]
- Sohrab, H.H. Basic Real Analysis; Springer Science & Business Media: New York, NY, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Oman, G. The converse of the intermediate value theorem: From Conway to Cantor to cosets and beyond. Mo. J. Math. Sci. 2014, 26, 134–150. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Fierro, R.; Martinez, C.; Morales, C.H. The aftermath of the intermediate value theorem. Fixed Point Theory Appl. 2004, 2004, 1–8. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Milgrom, P.; Roberts, J. Comparing equilibria. Am. Econ. Rev. 1994, 84, 441–459. [Google Scholar]
- Guillerme, J. Intermediate value theorems and fixed point theorems for semi-continuous functions in product spaces. Proc. Am. Math. Soc. 1995, 123, 2119–2122. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wu, Z. A note on fixed point theorems for semi-continuous correspondences on [0, 1]. Proc. Am. Math. Soc. 1998, 126, 3061–3064. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Debreu, G. Theory of Value: An Axiomatic Analysis of Economic Equilibrium; Yale University Press: Yale, CT, USA, 1959. [Google Scholar]
- Ricci, R.G. A note on a Tarski type fixed-point theorem. Int. J. Game Theory 2021, 50, 751–758. [Google Scholar]
- Amir, R.; Castro, L.D. Nash equilibrium in games with quasi-monotonic best-responses. J. Econ. Theory 2017, 172, 220–246. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Willard, S. General Topology; Addison Wesley Publishing Co.: New York, NY, USA, 1970. [Google Scholar]
- Mongin, P. A note on mixture sets in decision theory. Decis. Econ. Financ. 2001, 24, 59–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Munkres, J.R. Topology; Prentice Hall: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Liapounoff, A. Sur les fonctions-vecteurs complétement additives. Izv. Ross. Akad. Nauk. Seriya Mat. 1940, 4, 465–478. [Google Scholar]
- Loeb, P.A.; Rashid, S. Lyapunov’s Theorem. In The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics; Palgrave Macmilla: London, UK, 2016; pp. 1–4. [Google Scholar]
- Khan, M.A.; Sagara, N. Maharam-types and Lyapunov’s theorem for vector measures on Banach spaces. Ill. J. Math. 2013, 57, 145–169. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ross, D.A. An elementary proof of Lyapunov’s theorem. Am. Math. Mon. 2005, 112, 651–653. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nyman, K.L.; Su, F.E. A Borsuk–Ulam equivalent that directly implies Sperner’s lemma. Am. Math. Mon. 2013, 120, 346–354. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Su, F.E. Borsuk-Ulam implies Brouwer: A direct construction. Am. Math. Mon. 1997, 104, 855–859. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Volovikov, A.Y. Borsuk-Ulam Implies Brouwer: A Direct Construction Revisited. Am. Math. Mon. 2008, 115, 553–556. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kulpa, W. The Poincaré-Miranda theorem. Am. Math. Mon. 1997, 104, 545–550. [Google Scholar]
- Matoušek, J. Using the Borsuk-Ulam Theorem: Lectures on Topological Methods in Combinatorics and Geometry; Springer Science & Business Media: Berlin, Germany, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Vrahatis, M.N. Generalization of the Bolzano theorem for simplices. Topol. Its Appl. 2016, 202, 40–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Milgrom, P.; Mollner, J. Equilibrium selection in auctions and high stakes games. Econometrica 2018, 86, 219–261. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Khan, M.A.; McLean, R.P.; Uyanik, M. On a Generalization of the Poincaré-Miranda Theorem, Working Paper. 2022.
- Szymańska-Debowska, K. Resonant problem for some second-order differential equation on the half-line. Electron. Differ. Equ. 2007, 2007, 1–9. [Google Scholar]
- Szymańska-Debowska, K. On a generalization of the Miranda Theorem and its application to boundary value problems. J. Differ. Equ. 2015, 258, 2686–2700. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wakker, P. The algebraic versus the topological approach to additive representations. J. Math. Psychol. 1988, 32, 421–435. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Banerjee, K.; Mitra, T. On Wold’s approach to representation of preferences. J. Math. Econ. 2018, 79, 65–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nash, J.F. The bargaining problem. Econometrica 1950, 18, 155–162. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- von Neumann, J.; Morgenstern, O. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, 2nd ed.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1947. [Google Scholar]
- Fishburn, P.C. The Foundations of Expected Utility; D. Riedel Publishing Company: Boston, MA, USA, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Luce, R.D.; Narens, L. Measurement: The theory of numerical assignments. Psychol. Bull. 1986, 99, 166–180. [Google Scholar]
- Suppes, P. The measurement of belief. J. R. Stat. Soc. 1974, 36, 160–175. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ciesielski, K.C.; Miller, D. A continuous tale on continuous and separately continuous functions. Real Anal. 2016, 41, 19–54. [Google Scholar]
- Genocchi, A.; Peano, G. Calcolo Differentiale e Principii di Calcolo; Fratelli Bocca: Torino, ON, USA, 1884. [Google Scholar]
- Kruse, R.; Deely, J. Joint continuity of monotonic functions. Am. Math. Mon. 1969, 76, 74–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Young, W. A note on monotone functions. Q. J. Pure Appl. Math. 1910, 41, 79–87. [Google Scholar]
- Yokoyama, T. Continuity conditions of preference ordering. Osaka Econ. Pap. 1956, 4, 39–45. [Google Scholar]
- Dubra, J. Continuity and completeness under risk. Math. Soc. Sci. 2011, 61, 80–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Dubra, J.; Maccheroni, F.; Ok, E.A. Expected utility theory without the completeness axiom. J. Econ. Theory 2004, 115, 118–133. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gilboa, I.; Maccheroni, F.; Marinacci, M.; Schmeidler, D. Objective and subjective rationality in a multiple prior model. Econometrica 2010, 78, 755–770. [Google Scholar]
- Karni, E.; Safra, Z. Continuity, completeness, betweenness and cone-monotonicity. Math. Soc. Sci. 2015, 74, 68–72. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bergstrom, T.C.; Parks, R.P.; Rader, T. Preferences which have open graphs. J. Math. Econ. 1976, 3, 265–268. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Deshpandé, J.V. On continuity of a partial order. Proc. Am. Math. Soc. 1968, 19, 383–386. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schmeidler, D. Competitive equilibria in markets with a continuum of traders and incomplete preferences. Econometrica 1969, 37, 578–585. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shafer, W. The nontransitive consumer. Econometrica 1974, 42, 913–919. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ward, L. Partially ordered topological spaces. Proc. Am. Math. Soc. 1954, 5, 144–161. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gerasimou, G. Consumer theory with bounded rational preferences. J. Math. Econ. 2010, 46, 708–714. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Gerasimou, G. On continuity of incomplete preferences. Soc. Choice Welf. 2013, 41, 157–167. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gerasimou, G. (Hemi)continuity of additive preference preorders. J. Math. Econ. 2015, 58, 79–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Luce, D. Semiorders and a theory of utility discrimination. Econometrica 1956, 24, 178–191. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Giarlotta, A.; Watson, S. Universal semiorders. J. Math. Psychol. 2016, 73, 80–93. [Google Scholar]
- Özbay, E.Y.; Filiz, E. A representation for intransitive indifference relations. Math. Soc. Sci. 2005, 50, 202–214. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Giarlotta, A. New trends in preference, utility, and choice: From a mono-approach to a multi-approach. In New Perspectives in Multiple Criteria Decision Making; Doumpos, M., Figueira, J.R., Greco, S., Zopounidis, C., Eds.; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2019; pp. 3–80. [Google Scholar]
- Giarlotta, A.; Greco, S. Necessary and possible preference structures. J. Math. Econ. 2013, 49, 163–172. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Giarlotta, A.; Watson, S. Necessary and possible indifferences. J. Math. Psychol. 2017, 81, 98–109. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chipman, J. Consumption theory without transitive indifference. In Preferences, Utility and Demand: A Minnesota Symposium; Chipman, J., Hurwicz, L., Richter, M., Sonenschein, H., Eds.; Harcourt Brace Jovanovich: New York, NY, USA, 1971; pp. 224–253. [Google Scholar]
- Gorman, W.M. Preference, revealed preference, and indifference. In Preferences, Utility and Demand: A Minnesota Symposium; Chipman, J., Hurwicz, L., Richter, M., Sonenschein, H., Eds.; Harcourt Brace Jovanovich: New York, NY, USA, 1971; pp. 81–113. [Google Scholar]
- Huang, X.-C. From intermediate value theorem to chaos. Math. Mag. 1992, 65, 91–103. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Li, T.-Y.; Yorke, J.A. Period three implies chaos. Am. Math. Mon. 1975, 82, 985–992. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Deng, L.; Khan, M.A. On growing through cycles: Matsuyama’s M-map and Li–Yorke chaos. J. Math. Econ. 2018, 74, 46–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Du, B.-S. A simple proof of Sharkovsky’s theorem revisited. Am. Math. Mon. 2007, 114, 152–155. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Du, B.-S. An interesting application of the intermediate value theorem: A simple proof of Sharkovsky’s theorem and the towers of periodic points. arXiv 2017, arXiv:1507.04879. [Google Scholar]
- Lucas, R.; Prescott, E. Equilibrium search and unemployment. J. Political Econ. 1974, 7, 188–209. [Google Scholar]
- Stokey, N.L.; Lucas, R. Recursive Methods in Economic Dynamics; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Hildenbrand, W. An exposition of Wald’s existence proof. In Karl Menger; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1998; pp. 51–61. [Google Scholar]
- Arrow, K.J. Lectures on the Theory of Competitive Equilibrium. UC San Diego: Department of Economics, UCSD. Available online: https://escholarship.org/uc/item/1tj1x5r0 (accessed on 14 May 2022).
- Pröhl, E. Existence and Uniqueness of Recursive Equilibria with Aggregate and Idiosyncratic Risk. Available at SSRN 3250651. 2021. Available online: https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3250651 (accessed on 13 May 2022).
- Rockafellar, R.T. Convex Analysis; Princeton University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1970. [Google Scholar]
- McManus, M. Equilibrium, numbers and size in Cournot oligopoly. Bull. Econ. Res. 1964, 16, 68–75. [Google Scholar]
- Roberts, J.; Sonnenschein, H. On the existence of Cournot equilbrium without concave profit functions. J. Econ. Theory 1976, 13, 112–117. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Khan, M.A.; Schlee, E.E. Money-metric complementarity and price-dependent normality with nonordered preferences. In Proceedings of the SAET Meetings, Canberra, Australia, 16–22 July 2022. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Ghosh, A.; Khan, M.A.; Uyanik, M. The Intermediate Value Theorem and Decision-Making in Psychology and Economics: An Expositional Consolidation. Games 2022, 13, 51. https://doi.org/10.3390/g13040051
Ghosh A, Khan MA, Uyanik M. The Intermediate Value Theorem and Decision-Making in Psychology and Economics: An Expositional Consolidation. Games. 2022; 13(4):51. https://doi.org/10.3390/g13040051
Chicago/Turabian StyleGhosh, Aniruddha, Mohammed Ali Khan, and Metin Uyanik. 2022. "The Intermediate Value Theorem and Decision-Making in Psychology and Economics: An Expositional Consolidation" Games 13, no. 4: 51. https://doi.org/10.3390/g13040051
APA StyleGhosh, A., Khan, M. A., & Uyanik, M. (2022). The Intermediate Value Theorem and Decision-Making in Psychology and Economics: An Expositional Consolidation. Games, 13(4), 51. https://doi.org/10.3390/g13040051