The POVM Theorem in Bohmian Mechanics
Abstract
:1. Introduction
In a measurement, we cannot consider the system in isolation; rather, in order to mathematically trace its interaction with a measuring device , we must examine the system . The theory of measurement is, after all, a statement concerning , as it is meant to describe how the state of is related to certain features of the state of (namely, the positions of certain pointers, which the observer reads off).([5] p. 187; our translation.)
- What is the physical status of the mathematical assumptions underlying the POVM theorem and its applications?
- Given that the Bohmian theory involves no laws or postulates about ”measurements”, how can it imply such a strong result about them?
- Is the POVM theorem a result about what quantities are and are not measurable?
- Does the theorem imply the empirical equivalence of Bohmian mechanics and standard quantum mechanics?
2. Bohmian Mechanics and Quantum Equilibrium
- Quantum Equilibrium Hypothesis (QEH): If a subsystem of the universe has (conditional) wave function , then the probability of its particle configuration at time t being in the volume element of its configuration space is given by
3. The POVM Theorem and Its Assumptions
3.1. Basic Setting
3.2. The Basic Theorem
- Assumptions 1 and 2 are sufficient to prove the following general version of the POVM theorem:
3.3. Towards Practical Predictions
- 1.
- All have FAPP support in , i.e., ;
- 2.
- For all , the decoherent branching (16a) has (essentially) the same form
4. More on the Assumptions
4.1. On Assumption 1: The “Lab” as a Closed System
- In BM, “external influences” may arise either from interactions on the level of the wave function or from the nonlocal guiding equation when the lab system is entangled with its environment (the former typically implies the latter, but not vice versa). Assumption 1 amounts to requiring that both are negligible for predicting the outcome statistics of the experiment.
- Of course, everything that has a non-negligible influence on the outcome statistics should be included in the “laboratory system”, which can be defined as large as necessary to make the assumption plausible.
- If the experiment involves measurements on entangled particles performed in different laboratories, then the “lab system” must comprise all of these individual laboratories even if they are located far apart.
- Das and Aristarhov [10] object that, in practice, no laboratory subsystem is perfectly closed. Indeed, as with essentially all theoretical predictions, the POVM theorem is derived under idealized measurement conditions. The relevant question is then: does the fact that no laboratory is ever perfectly isolated only introduce noise, or can it change the “signal” into some non-POVM distribution? We see no reason to believe the latter (see point 8 below), while accounting for noise or potential measurement errors due to false detections is standard in experimental physics and beside the point of the theorem.
- One might be, nonetheless, unsatisfied with the fact that Assumption 1 is an idealization rather than a strict truth claim about typical experiments. There are then two ways to relax the assumption, leading to variations of the theorem presented here.
- One can take the “lab system” to be the entire universe [9], and thus the universal wave function, which always obeys a linear Schrödinger equation according to the fundamental laws of BM. However, in this case, the quantum equilibrium measure should not be interpreted as a probability distribution but rather as a typicality measure, and the POVM theorem as a typicality result [19]. In short: for the vast majority of possible initial configurations of the universe (consistent with the experiment in question), the outcome statistics of a long series of measurements will be close to a POVM distribution. If the status of the QEH is understood following DGZ [18], probability statements are, in any case, grounded in these kinds of typicality statements, and the “universal” version of the POVM theorem is both natural and straightforward.
- One can describe the lab system as an open quantum system in terms of a density matrix following a linear (e.g., Lindblad-type) master equation. The resulting version of the POVM theorem would be similar to the Choi–Kraus theorem in standard quantum mechanics [23,24]. This is in line with results implying that the Bohmian conditional wave function—undergoing effective collapses due to interactions with a large environment—typically behaves like the wave function in some spontaneous collapse model [25,26].
- While a detailed discussion is beyond the scope of this paper, it is instructive to explain briefly why the results of our analysis hold up in the setting of open quantum systems. The entanglement of the lab system with its environment has essentially two effects. First, it will introduce some noise into the evolution of , which would now have to be described as a conditional (not effective) wave function. However, this noise is effectively random and will not skew the outcome statistics. Second, the lab wave function, after the primary measurement interaction, would not persist in a superposition (16a) but quickly collapse into the “pointer state” belonging to the actual outcome. Crucially, though, the corresponding “collapse probabilities” coincide (essentially) with the outcome probabilities that we are going to derive for a closed system. Averaging over the environment configurations (with respect to the quantum equilibrium measure) leads to the aforementioned description in terms of a (conditional) density matrix.
4.2. On Assumption 2: State Preparation
- From Assumptions 1 and 2, it follows that at initial time , the apparatus system can also be described by its own (effective) wave function . Of course, as soon as the target system and apparatus system begin to interact, they will become entangled and no longer have separable quantum states.
- Uncertainty due to unreliable state preparation can be handled in the usual way by describing the state of the target system by a density matrix representing a (proper) mixture of pure states.
4.3. On Assumption 3: Stable Pointer Configurations
- Our Assumption 3 required stable pointer configurations (during some time interval I) that record the final outcome of the measurement. From this assumption, we inferred the decoherent branching (16) of the lab wave function according to well-localized pointer states. At the same time, there are strong independent reasons to expect that the pointer states will decohere extremely well and fast due to the macroscopically large number () of degrees of freedom of the “pointer” and its environment inside the lab [27]. Put simply, once the separate on the extremely high-dimensional configuration space of the lab system, the dynamics will not bring them back into overlap (on empirically relevant timescales). In general, this separation of the pointer states gets only better (i.e., decoherence is stronger) the larger the system that we consider as our lab system.
- In Bohmian mechanics (with the standard guiding equation), it is highly plausible that (16) entails (the typicality of) stable pointer configurations because trajectories typically avoid regions of configuration space where is vanishingly small. Realistically speaking, different pointer states will have highly suppressed but non-vanishing tails (which overlap outside the disjoint configuration space regions ). It is then not impossible for the apparatus configuration to quickly evolve from to . However, those would be atypical solutions of the kind that all known microphysical theories admit in principle—solutions corresponding to, say, a pointer pointing to “1”, spontaneously evaporating, and reassembling to point to “2”.
- That said, we emphasize that our analysis in Section 3.3 assumes stable pointer configurations rather than inferring them. If the measurement does not result in any reasonable stable, macroscopically discernible outcome, we simply do not have a meaningful experiment.
- A bit of pragmatism is required to identify a suitable time interval I during which we can assume a stable record of the measurement outcome for a given experiment. As mentioned earlier, I need not include the exact time (from the start of the measurement) at which a detector is triggered—since this might vary across different runs of the measurement—as long as we can identify a (non-random) time interval during which some part of the apparatus configuration (e.g., the clock in an arrival time experiment) still records the relevant outcome. On the other hand, if the experiment involves, say, radioactive decay of 235U, decay events may occur even after a billion years. However, since it is difficult to obtain funding for an experiment that runs for a billion years, one will, in practice, cut off the tail end of the “waiting time distribution” much sooner—that is, agree on a much earlier time at which the experiment is considered concluded.
- In principle, the relevant “pointer configurations” need not even be a part of the measurement apparatus in the narrow sense. One could consider any (more permanent) record of the outcomes (e.g., a printout on a sheet of paper) as long as they are recorded in some positional configuration (cf. [28] (Ch. 4)).
4.4. On Assumption 4: Apparatus Ready State as a Macrostate
- While this assumption would be very difficult to prove from fundamental principles (due to the complexity of any macroscopic lab system), it can be empirically corroborated. Repeat the experiment—not just a single measurement, but the whole series of measurements—at different times and/or places. If the outcome distributions are (approximately) the same, it is good evidence that they do not depend significantly on details of that are beyond the experimenter’s control.
- For projective measurements, the target system will have corresponding eigenstates for which one can require , i.e., that the apparatus system can be prepared in a ready state such that it will (almost certainly) indicate the outcome “k” whenever the target system is prepared in the initial state . This requirement is stronger than our Assumption 4 (though it can be more directly empirically corroborated).
5. Examples
5.1. Measurement of a Particle Position
5.2. Indirect Measurements
6. On the Scope of the POVM Theorem
6.1. Measurability and Non-POVM Statistics
- Weak Measurements with Post-Selection: The POVM Theorem 2 applies to the “pointer statistics” of weak measurements. However, in this class of experiments (first suggested in [32]), one knows that the quantity one seeks to measure is—by design—very weakly correlated with the final pointer position of the measurement device. The distribution of the so-called weak values is then not obtained directly from the pointer distribution but, simply put, after some ”data processing” that involves averaging and post-selection (according to the results of strong measurements performed after each weak interaction). In this way, it is possible to—in a certain sense—measure quantities, e.g., Bohmian velocities [33,34,35], whose distribution does not correspond to a POVM.
- Non-linear Measurements do not repeat the same measurement process independently of the state of the target system. Instead, the apparatus and thereby, in general, the measurement interactions (which determine ) are tuned depending on —either based on the initial state preparation or depending on outcomes of intermittent measurements. Such a setup deliberately violates our Assumption 4. As a result, the total wave function (10) will not depend linearly on across different instances of the measurement and the empirical statistics will not be given by a (fixed) POVM. (See our trivial example for spin measurements above). Interesting applications of non-linear/adaptive measurement techniques include state-dependent protective measurements [36] or adaptive quantum state tomography [37,38]. Weak measurements with post-selection may also be understood as a special type of non-linear measurement [22,34].
6.2. On “Empirical Equivalence”
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Bohm, D. A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of “Hidden” Variables. II. Phys. Rev. 1952, 85, 180–193. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dürr, D.; Goldstein, S.; Zanghì, N. Quantum Equilibrium and the Role of Operators as Observables in Quantum Theory. J. Stat. Phys. 2004, 116, 959–1055. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ludwig, G. Theory of Quantum Mechanical Measurements. Metrologia 1986, 22, 128. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Busch, P.; Grabowski, M.; Lahti, P.J. Operational Quantum Physics; Lecture Notes in Physics Monographs; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1995; Volume 31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- von Neumann, J. Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1932. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Das, S.; Dürr, D. Arrival Time Distributions of Spin-1/2 Particles. Sci. Rep. 2019, 9, 2242. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Das, S.; Nöth, M.; Dürr, D. Exotic Bohmian Arrival Times of Spin-1/2 Particles: An Analytical Treatment. Phys. Rev. A 2019, 99, 052124. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Goldstein, S.; Tumulka, R.; Zanghì, N. On the Spin Dependence of Detection Times and the Nonmeasurability of Arrival Times. Sci. Rep. 2024, 14, 3775. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Goldstein, S.; Tumulka, R.; Zanghì, N. Arrival Times Versus Detection Times. Found. Phys. 2024, 54, 63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Das, S.; Aristarhov, S. Comment on “the Spin Dependence of Detection Times and the Nonmeasurability of Arrival Times”. arXiv 2023, arXiv:2312.01802. [Google Scholar]
- Teufel, S.; Dürr, D. Bohmian Mechanics: The Physics and Mathematics of Quantum Theory; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2009. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tumulka, R. Foundations of Quantum Mechanics; Lecture Notes in Physics; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2022; Volume 1003. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ghirardi, G.C.; Rimini, A.; Weber, T. Unified Dynamics for Microscopic and Macroscopic Systems. Phys. Rev. D 1986, 34, 470–491. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bell, J.S. Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics, 2nd ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Allori, V.; Goldstein, S.; Tumulka, R.; Zanghì, N. On the Common Structure of Bohmian Mechanics and the Ghirardi-Rimini-Weber Theory. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2008, 59, 353–389. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Holland, P.; Philippidis, C. Implications of Lorentz covariance for the guidance equation in two-slit quantum interference. Phys. Rev. A 2003, 67, 062105. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dürr, D.; Goldstein, S.; Tumulka, R.; Zanghí, N. On the Role of Density Matrices in Bohmian Mechanics. Found. Phys. 2005, 35, 449–467. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dürr, D.; Goldstein, S.; Zanghì, N. Quantum Equilibrium and the Origin of Absolute Uncertainty. J. Stat. Phys. 1992, 67, 843–907. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lazarovici, D. Typicality Reasoning in Probability, Physics, and Metaphysics; New Directions in the Philosophy of Science, Palgrave Macmillan: Cham, Switzerland, 2023. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lazarovici, D.; Reichert, P. The Point of Primitive Ontology. Found. Phys. 2022, 52, 120. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lazarovici, D. Hidden Variables in Quantum Mechanics from the Perspective of Boltzmannian Statistical Mechanics. Quantum Rep. 2024, 6, 465–481. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Beck, C. Local Quantum Measurement and Relativity; Fundamental Theories of Physics; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2021; Volume 201. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Choi, M.D. Completely Positive Linear Maps on Complex Matrices. Linear Algebra Its Appl. 1975, 10, 285–290. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kraus, K.; Böhm, A.; Dollard, J.D.; Wootters, W.H. (Eds.) States, Effects, and Operations; Lecture Notes in Physics; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1983; Volume 190. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Toroš, M.; Donadi, S.; Bassi, A. Bohmian Mechanics, Collapse Models and the Emergence of Classicality. J. Phys. A Math. Theor. 2016, 49, 355302. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tilloy, A.; Wiseman, H.M. Non-Markovian Wave-Function Collapse Models Are Bohmian-like Theories in Disguise. Quantum 2021, 5, 594. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hornberger, K. Introduction to Decoherence Theory. In Entanglement and Decoherence: Foundations and Modern Trends; Buchleitner, A., Viviescas, C., Tiersch, M., Eds.; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2009; pp. 221–276. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Albert, D.Z. After Physics; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Naimark, M. Self-adjoint extensions of the second kind of a symmetric operator. Izv. Ross. Akad. Nauk. Seriya Mat. 1940, 4, 53–104. [Google Scholar]
- Naimark, M. Spectral functions of a symmetric operator. Izv. Ross. Akad. Nauk. Seriya Mat. 1940, 4, 277–318. [Google Scholar]
- Holevo, A.S. Probabilistic and Statistical Aspects of Quantum Theory; Springer Science & Business Media: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2011; Volume 1. [Google Scholar]
- Aharonov, Y.; Albert, D.Z.; Vaidman, L. How the result of a measurement of a component of the spin of a spin-1/2 particle can turn out to be 100. Phys. Rev. Lett. 1988, 60, 1351–1354. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wiseman, H.M. Grounding Bohmian Mechanics in Weak Values and Bayesianism. New J. Phys. 2007, 9, 165. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dürr, D.; Goldstein, S.; Zanghì, N. On the Weak Measurement of Velocity in Bohmian Mechanics. J. Stat. Phys. 2009, 134, 1023–1032. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kocsis, S.; Braverman, B.; Ravets, S.; Stevens, M.J.; Mirin, R.P.; Shalm, L.K.; Steinberg, A.M. Observing the Average Trajectories of Single Photons in a Two-Slit Interferometer. Science 2011, 332, 1170–1173. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Aharonov, Y.; Vaidman, L. Protective Measurements. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. 1995, 755, 361–373. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Huszár, F.; Houlsby, N.M.T. Adaptive Bayesian Quantum Tomography. Phys. Rev. A 2012, 85, 052120. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Qi, B.; Hou, Z.; Wang, Y.; Dong, D.; Zhong, H.S.; Li, L.; Xiang, G.Y.; Wiseman, H.M.; Li, C.F.; Guo, G.C. Adaptive Quantum State Tomography via Linear Regression Estimation: Theory and Two-Qubit Experiment. npj Quantum Inf. 2017, 3, 19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Beck, C.; Lazarovici, D. The POVM Theorem in Bohmian Mechanics. Entropy 2025, 27, 391. https://doi.org/10.3390/e27040391
Beck C, Lazarovici D. The POVM Theorem in Bohmian Mechanics. Entropy. 2025; 27(4):391. https://doi.org/10.3390/e27040391
Chicago/Turabian StyleBeck, Christian, and Dustin Lazarovici. 2025. "The POVM Theorem in Bohmian Mechanics" Entropy 27, no. 4: 391. https://doi.org/10.3390/e27040391
APA StyleBeck, C., & Lazarovici, D. (2025). The POVM Theorem in Bohmian Mechanics. Entropy, 27(4), 391. https://doi.org/10.3390/e27040391