Next Article in Journal
Algorithmic Problems for Computation Trees
Previous Article in Journal
On a Correspondence Between Two Kinds of Bilateral Proof-Systems
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Distribution-Free Normal Modal Logics

by
Chrysafis Hartonas
Department of Digital Systems, University of Thessaly, 382 21 Volos, Greece
Submission received: 16 December 2024 / Revised: 9 March 2025 / Accepted: 28 March 2025 / Published: 1 April 2025

Abstract

:
This article initiates the semantic study of distribution-free normal modal logic systems, laying the semantic foundations and anticipating further research in the area. The article explores roughly the same area, though taking a different approach, as a recent article by Bezhanishvili, de Groot, Dmitrieva and Morachini, who studied a distribution-free version of Dunn’s positive modal logic (PML). Unlike PML, we consider logics that may drop distribution and that are equipped with both an implication connective and modal operators. We adopt a uniform relational semantics approach, relying on recent results on representation and duality for normal lattice expansions. We prove canonicity and completeness in the relational semantics of the minimal distribution-free normal modal logic, assuming just the K-axiom, as well as those of its axiomatic extensions obtained by adding any of the D, T, B, S4 or S5 axioms. Adding distribution can be easily accommodated and, as a side result, we also obtain a new semantic treatment of intuitionistic modal logic.

1. Introduction

The first sub-classical modal logic system studied, other than IML (intuitionistic modal logic), was Dunn’s positive modal logic (PML) [1], weakening the lattice-base axioms of the logic to those of a mere distributive lattice. Both negation and implication are absent from the language of PML. Dunn’s article has attracted some interest. Gehrke, Nagahashi and Venema [2] studied the Sahlqvist theory of a system DML (distributive modal logic), which is the fusion of its two monomodal fragments and is weaker than Dunn’s PML. Celani and Jansana [3] proposed a new semantics for PML to model the consequence relation of the logic. Finally, and more relevant to our purposes, Bezhanishvili, Dmitrieva, de Groot and Morachini [4] focused on a distribution-free version of PML. A single relation R in frames generates both , ; the interpretation for modal formulae is standard, except that, in pursuing a way to define frames that validate interaction axioms, they find it necessary to abandon the distribution of diamonds over joins. The authors do not work with canonical extensions but model their logic(s) of interest in (topological) semilattices and develop a related correspondence theory. A duality for distribution-free modal lattices is presented in [4], building on the Hofmann, Mislove and Stralka [5] duality for meet semilattices, and the authors use it to build a new semantic framework for the logic of their focus.
The logics that we consider may or may not be distributive and, axiomatically, they are the sub-classical analogues of the classical basic systems of normal modal logic. Their equivalent algebraic semantics is given by the variety of implicative modal bounded lattices L = ( L , , , , 0 , 1 , , , ) . The implication fragment of the logics may be as weak as the same fragment of the non-associative full Lambek calculus and as strong as the intuitionistic (or Boolean) propositional calculus. We adopt a uniform relational semantics approach based on a generalization of the Jónsson–Tarski framework [6] for the relational representation of normal lattice operators given in [7]. The results of [7], when instantiated to implicative modal lattices, provide the necessary framework in which to model the operators and derive the soundness and canonicity/completeness of distribution-free modal logic in the absence of any axioms other than the normality and distribution property axioms for the logical operators , and →. The present article contributes by extending the general framework of [7] to the case of the distribution-free analogues of the classical basic systems of normal modal logic.
The relational semantics of distribution-free systems is typically given in two-sorted frames [8,9,10,11,12], with a distinguished relation generating a Galois connection on the powersets of the sorts and modeling sentences as sets that are stable under the closure operator generated by the Galois connection. It has been observed that a two-sorted framework makes it hard to transfer and use results and techniques established for the classical setting. Indeed, the possibility of direct transfer and use of results is missing and much has to be established afresh. However, recent developments seem to gradually fill in the gap with the classical (distributive or Boolean) setting. Other than the generalization of the concept of canonical (perfect) extensions to bounded lattices [13] and the topological dualities of [7,11,14,15], a Sahlqvist theory for distribution-free logics in the RS framework has been developed by Conradie and Palmigiano [16], a Goldblatt–Thomason theorem for non-distributive logics in a two-sorted semantic framework has been published by Goldblatt [17], a van Benthem characterization result for logics without distribution has been detailed in [12] by the author and several distribution-free systems have been modeled in the two-sorted approach, among which we may mention [10,11,18,19,20].
This article fills in a gap in the literature by presenting a systematic study of the relational semantics of the basic normal modal logic systems that may lack distribution of conjunction over disjunction and conversely. Relying on the extension of canonical extensions to the case of bounded lattices [13], it specifies what a canonical frame for the distribution-free systems is, identifies frame classes corresponding to the basic normal modal logic systems and proves canonicity and completeness in the relational semantics.
Section 2 defines normal lattice expansions and, in particular, the variety of implicative modal lattices. It specifies the basic proof system for any normal lattice expansion built on top of a proof system for positive lattice logic (PLL) and including only axioms and rules from which the distribution and normality properties of the logical operators are obtained. The section is concluded with a duality between the lattice of axiomatic extensions of the basic logic and the lattice of subvarieties of the variety determined by the equivalent algebraic semantics of the basic logic system.
Section 3 introduces sorted residuated frames with sorted relations and defines their complete lattices of stable sets. Sorted image operators are defined as in the classical Jónsson–Tarski framework [6] (which precedes by a decade and logically underlies Kripke semantics for modal logic, or Routley–Meyer semantics for relevance logic). Stable-set sorted operators are defined from the image operators and it is proven that, under a mild assumption of smoothness of the frame relations, they are completely additive. Normal lattice operators of distribution types depending on the sort of the generating relation are subsequently derived and the full complex algebra of a frame is defined. Relational semantics is presented in terms of both a relation of satisfaction ⊩ and a relation of co-satisfaction (refutation) . The sorted relational framework is a smooth generalization of classical relational semantics (see Remarks 1 and 4). The section is concluded with instantiating definitions for the case of implication and the modal operators and deriving soundness of the logic obtained as the fusion of its fragments with the single operators , and ◇, and this completes the presentation of the basic background needed.
Section 4 considers the minimal distribution-free normal modal logic system, including just the K-axiom ( p q ) p q , on top of the standard distribution and normality axioms for each of □ and ◇, but without the interdefinability of box and diamond axiom. To define frames that validate the K-axiom, it is first pointed out that the lattice G ( Z 1 ) of stable sets and the MacNeille completion of a sub-poset Q G ( Z 1 ) of principal (closed and open) elements are identical. We refer to the sub-poset Q as the intermediate structure of the frame. The significant issue arising is that, in frames that can be axiomatically extended to validate the K-axiom, the upper MacNeille extension u of the definition of the box operator in the intermediate structure must lie below its lower MacNeille extension . A restricted (second-order) join-distributivity of over joins x A Γ x x A Γ x is postulated and the class of refined frames is defined. The section is concluded with a soundness proof for the class of refined frames whose intermediate structure validates the K-axiom, a requirement that can be easily phrased as a first-order frame axiom.
Section 5 specifies frame classes corresponding to the D, T, B, S4 and S5 axioms and proves soundness results.
Section 6 constructs the canonical frame as an instance of a general representation result for normal lattice expansions. It is argued that the full complex algebra of the canonical frame is a canonical extension of the Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra of the logic, that the frame is refined and that the frame axioms corresponding to the additional K, D, T, B, S4 and S5 logic axioms hold. This establishes canonicity and completeness in the relational semantics.
In Section 7, we argue that the semantic framework and approach of the previous sections are scalable and can be adapted to handle the cases where the underlying lattice logic is distributive or intuitionistic. For the Heyting algebra case, we show that validity of the K-axiom holds without a need to assume a second-order axiomatization of the frame.
Section 8 presents a summary review of related work.

2. Implicative Modal Lattices and Logics

2.1. Implicative Modal Lattices

Let { 1 , } be a two-element set, L 1 = L and L = L op (the opposite lattice). Extending established terminology [6], a function f : L 1 × × L n L n + 1 will be called additive and normal, or a normal operator, if it distributes over finite joins of the lattice L i , for each i = 1 , n , delivering a join in L n + 1 .
An n-ary operation f on a bounded lattice L is a normal lattice operator of distribution type δ ( f ) = ( j 1 , , j n ; j n + 1 ) { 1 , } n + 1 if it is a normal additive function f : L j 1 × × L j n L j n + 1 (distributing over finite joins in each argument place), where each j k , for k = 1 , , n + 1 , is in the set { 1 , } ; hence, L j k is either L or L .
If τ is a tuple (sequence) of distribution types, a normal lattice expansion (NLE) of (similarity) type τ is a lattice with a normal lattice operator of distribution type δ for each δ in τ . By its definition, the class of normal lattice expansions of some type τ is equationally definable (a variety) NLE τ .
Definition 1.
An implicative lattice is a bounded lattice with a binary (implication) operation, L = ( L , , , , 0 , 1 , ) , of distribution type δ ( ) = ( 1 , ; ) , i.e., the following axioms hold, in addition to the axioms for bounded lattices.
(A1) ( a b ) c = ( a c ) ( b c )
(A2) a ( b c ) = ( a b ) ( a c )
(N) ( 0 a ) = 1 = ( a 1 ) .
The lattice is distributive if axiom (A3) is assumed.
(A3) a ( b c ) = ( a b ) ( a c )
It is a Heyting algebra if axioms (H1)-(H2) are added to the axioms for bounded lattices
(H1) a ( a b ) b
(H2) b a ( a b )
An implicative modal lattice L = ( L , , , , 0 , 1 , , , ) is an implicative lattice with two unary (modal) operators , satisfying the axioms
(M□) ( a b ) = a b (M) ( a b ) = a b
(N□) 1 = 1 (N) 0 = 0
The weak modal logics that we will consider arise by adding to the axiomatization any of the K, D, T, B or S4, S5 axioms, as in the standard systems of normal modal logic, except for dropping the assumption that the underlying propositional logic is classical and replacing it by the weaker assumption that it is the logic of an implicative modal lattice.
(K) ( a b ) a b (B) a a and a a
(D) a a (S4□) a a
(T) a a (S4) a a
(T) a a (S5) a a and a a
To fix an understanding of what constitutes a canonical frame and model for our logics, we review some basic definitions on completions and canonical extensions of lattices.
A completion  ( α , C ) of an NLE L is a complete NLE C of the same similarity type with an embedding α : L C . In [6], a notion of a canonical (perfect) extension of Boolean algebras was identified, extended by Gehrke and Jónsson [21] to the case of distributive lattices and by Gehrke and Harding [13] to the case of mere bounded lattices. For the purposes of this article, the completions that we work with are canonical extensions, traditionally associated to a canonical frame construction in completeness proofs.
A canonical extension [13] of a lattice L is a completion ( α , C ) of the lattice such that the following density and compactness requirements are satisfied:
  • (Density) α [ L ] is dense in C , where the latter means that every element of C can be expressed both as a meet of joins and as a join of meets of elements in α [ L ] ;
  • (Compactness) for any set A of closed elements and any set B of open elements of C, A B iff there exist finite subcollections A 1 A , B 1 B such that A 1 B 1 .
Here, the closed elements of C are defined in [13] as the elements in the meet-closure of the embedding map α and the open elements of C are defined dually as the join-closure of the image of α . Canonical extensions are unique up to an isomorphism that commutes with the embeddings [13] [Proposition 2.7].
For a unary monotone lattice map f : L K , its σ , π -extensions f σ , f π : C L C K are defined in [13] [Definition 4.1, Lemma 4.3] by Equation (1), where K is the set of closed elements of C L and O is its set of open elements:
f σ ( k ) = { f ( a ) | k a L } f σ ( u ) = { f σ ( k ) | K k u } f π ( o ) = { f ( a ) | L a o } f π ( u ) = { f π ( o ) | u o O }
where, in these definitions, L is identified with its isomorphic image in C L and a , f ( a ) L are identified with their representation images.
Definition 2.
A canonical extension of a normal lattice expansion L = ( L , , , , 0 , 1 , ( f j ) j J ) is a canonical extension ( α , L σ ) of the underlying bounded lattice, with normal lattice operators F j extending f j , for each j J , and such that F j = f j σ whenever δ j ( n + 1 ) = 1 (the operator f j returns joins) and F j = f j π whenever δ j ( n + 1 ) = (the operator f j returns meets).
A variety of normal lattice expansions is canonical if it is closed under canonical extensions of its members. A logic is canonical if the variety of its equivalent algebraic semantics is canonical. Canonicity implies completeness in relational semantics if the full complex algebra of the canonical frame for the logic is a canonical extension of the Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra of the logic.

2.2. Languages, Logics and Algebraic Semantics

Let J be a countable set and δ : J { 1 , } n ( j ) + 1 be a map. The propositional language L = L ( J , δ ) of normal lattice expansions of similarity type τ = ( δ j ) j J is defined by the following grammar
L φ = p i ( i N ) | | | φ φ | φ φ | ( f j ( φ 1 , , φ n ( j ) ) ) j J ,
where δ j = ( j 1 , , j n ( j ) ; j n ( j ) + 1 ) , and we let δ j ( k ) = j k for 1 k j n ( j ) + 1 . The language L is an instance of the language L τ ( J , δ ) of NLEs of an arbitrary type τ , where, in the current context, we may let the index set be J = { , , } and f = Logics 03 00003 i002, f = , f = Logics 03 00003 i003 (and with δ = ( 1 ; 1 ) , δ = ( , ) and δ = ( 1 , ; ) ), displayed below:
Logics 03 00003 i004
For a fixed τ and an algebra A (a normal lattice expansion of type τ ), a model on A is defined as usual as a pair M = ( A , v ) given an interpretation function v : P A , where A is the underlying set of A , and letting also v ( ) = 0 , v ( ) = 1 . The interpretation [ [ ] ] M of all sentences is obtained as usual as the unique homomorphic extension of v from the absolutely free term-algebra on L to A . Treating L also as a term language for A , a formal equation is a pair of sentences (terms, designating lattice elements) written as φ ψ . A formal equation is true in a model M = ( A , v ) , written as M φ ψ iff [ [ φ ] ] M = [ [ ψ ] ] M . An algebra A validates a formal equation, A φ ψ , iff, for any model M = ( A , v ) on A , we have M φ ψ , and similarly for a class C of algebras. A formal inequation is syntactically defined as usual by ( φ ψ ) = ( φ φ ψ ) .
For our purposes, we define a logic on the language L τ as a set of pairs ( φ , ψ ) , which we write as φ ψ and refer to as ‘sequents’. A proof system for the logic is a set of initial sequents (axioms) and rules S 1 S n S , where S i , S are sequents. Proofs (in a proof system) are defined as usual. The logic generated by a proof system is the set of the sequents that it proves. A sequent is valid in a model, written as M φ ψ (or φ M ψ , omitting the subscript if clear from context), iff [ [ φ ] ] M [ [ ψ ] ] M , which is exactly the condition for the validity of inequations M φ ψ , analogously for validity in an algebra or in a class of algebras. A proof system is sound in a class of algebras iff every provable sequent (theorem) φ ψ is valid in this class iff the initial sequents are valid and every rule is valid in this class.
The minimal logic Λ τ (for any similarity type τ ), whose proof system we define in Table 1, is defined as an extension of a proof system for positive lattice logic PLL , the logic of bounded lattices. To simplify, we use vectorial notation φ for a tuple of sentences and let φ [ ] k be the vector with an empty place at the k-th argument position and φ [ ψ ] k either to display the sentence at the k-position or to designate the result of filling the empty place in φ [ ] k or the result of replacing the entry φ k with ψ at the k-th argument place.
Specializing rules for the case of the logical operators , and → can be safely left to the reader.
Writing φ ψ to mean that both φ ψ and ψ φ are provable sequents and [ φ ] for the equivalence class of φ , the axioms and rules of the minimal logic Λ τ ensure that ≡ is a congruence and that the Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra of the logic is a normal lattice expansion of type τ = ( δ j ) j J . This implies a completeness theorem, stated below.
Theorem 1.
For any similarity type τ, the minimal logic Λ τ is sound and complete in the variety NLE τ of normal lattice expansions of similarity type τ.
If Γ is a set of sequents, then Λ τ + Γ stands for the logic that results by adding members of Γ as new initial sequents (notice that we have included an explicit substitution rule in the proof system). Denote by Ext Λ τ the family of such extensions of Λ τ and observe that Ext Λ τ is a complete lattice under intersection.
Every extension Λ = Λ τ + Γ determines a subvariety V Sub NLE τ whose equational theory is E ( V ) = E ( NLE τ ) { φ ψ | ( φ , ψ ) Γ } .
Definition 3.
The maps V : Ext Λ τ Sub NLE τ : Λ are defined on a logic Λ Ext Λ τ and a variety V Sub NLE τ by
V ( Λ ) = { L NLE τ | ( φ , ψ ) Λ φ L ψ }
Λ ( V ) = { ( φ , ψ ) | φ V ψ }
The following Propositions have rather easy proofs, left to the interested reader. Analogous proofs can be found in [11] [Propositions 2.7–2.9].
Proposition 1
(Definability). For any subvariety V Sub NLE τ and any normal lattice expansion L NLE τ , L V iff L Λ ( V ) . Equivalently, V Λ ( V ) = V .
Proposition 2
(Completeness). For every logic Λ Ext Λ τ and every pair of sentences ( φ , ψ ) , φ ψ Λ iff φ V ( Λ ) ψ . Equivalently, Λ V ( Λ ) = Λ .
Proposition 3
(Duality). The maps V , Λ constitute a complete lattice dual isomorphism V : Ext Λ τ Sub NLE τ op : Λ .
This dual isomorphism allows us to switch from logics to varieties of normal lattice expansions and back without any loss of information.

3. Frames and Relational Semantics

3.1. Frames and Models

By a (relational) frame, we mean a structure F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) , where s is a list of sorts, Z = ( Z t ) t s is a nonempty sorted set (i.e., none of the sorts Z t are allowed to be empty), where we make no assumption of disjointness of sorts, I t s Z t is a distinguished sorted relation, σ is a sorting map on J with σ ( j ) s n ( j ) + 1 and ( R j ) j J is a family of sorted relations such that, if σ ( j ) = ( j n ( j ) + 1 ; j 1 , , j n ( j ) ) , then R j Z j n ( j ) + 1 × k = 1 n ( j ) Z j k . The sort σ ( R j ) (or just σ ( j ) or σ j ) of the relation R j is the tuple σ ( j ) = ( j n ( j ) + 1 ; j 1 j n ( j ) ) . The similarity type of the structure F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) is the tuple σ ( j ) j J of the sorts of the relations R j in the structure.
We will work with structures where s = { 1 , } , Z = ( Z 1 , Z ) is a sorted set and I Z 1 × Z is a distinguished sorted relation. We often display the sort of a relation as a superscript, as in F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j σ ( j ) ) j J ) . For example, R 11 , T 1 designate sorted relations R Z 1 × Z 1 and T Z × Z 1 × Z . In the intended application of the present article, the frame relations considered are R 11 , R and R 1 , but we shall use T for the latter (or T 1 , displaying its sort) as this makes it easier to relate to results obtained in [15].
The relation I generates a residuated pair λ : Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) : ρ , defined as usual by
λ ( U ) = { y Z | x Z 1 ( x I y x U ) } ρ ( V ) = { x Z 1 | y Z ( x I y y V ) } .
We may also use the notation ◇U for λ U and V for ρ V , as we have often done in previous published work. The complement of I will be designated by ⍊ and we refer to it as the Galois relation of the frame. It generates a Galois connection ( ) : Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) op :   ( ) defined by
U = { y Z | u Z 1 ( u U u y ) } V = { x Z 1 | y Z ( y V x y ) } .
Observe that the closure operators generated by the residuated pair and the Galois connection are identical, i.e., ρ λ U =   ( U ) and λ ρ V = ( V ) . This follows from the fact that U = ( U ) and V = ( V ) .
To simplify, we often use a priming notation for both Galois maps ( ) and ( ) , i.e., we let U = U for U Z 1 and V = V for V Z . Hence, U =   ( U ) = ρ λ U and V = ( V ) = λ ρ V .
The complete lattice of all Galois stable sets Z 1 U = U will be designated by G ( Z 1 ) and the complete lattice of all Galois co-stable sets Z V = V will be similarly denoted by G ( Z ) . We refer to Galois stable and co-stable sets as Galois sets. Note that each of Z 1 , Z is a Galois set but the empty set need not be Galois. Hence, the bottom element in each of G ( Z 1 ) , G ( Z ) is the closure of the empty set, .
For an element u in either Z 1 or Z and a subset W of Z or Z 1 , respectively, we write u | W , under a well-sorting assumption, to stand for either u W (which stands for u w for all w W ) or W u (which stands for w u for all w W ), where well-sorting means that either u Z 1 and W Z or W Z 1 and u Z , respectively. This similarly applies to the notation u | v , where u , v are elements of different sorts.
A preorder relation is defined on each of Z 1 , Z by u w iff { u } { w } . We call a frame separated if ⪯ is in fact a partial order ≤. For an element u (of either Z 1 or Z ), we write Γ u for the set of elements ⪯-above it. We hereafter assume that frames are separated.
Sets Γ w and { w } will be referred to as principal elements. Γ w will be referred to as a closed element and { w } as an open element. K G ( Z 1 ) , O G ( Z 1 ) designate the families of closed and open elements of G ( Z 1 ) , and analogously for G ( Z ) . A closed element Γ x G ( Z 1 ) is clopen if there exists an open element { y } G ( Z 1 ) (which is unique, when it exists, in separated frames) such that Γ x = { y } . We set KO G ( Z 1 ) for the family of clopen elements, and similarly for G ( Z ) .
A point w such that Γ w is a clopen element will also be referred to as a clopen point.
The following basic facts will be often used without reference to Lemma 1.
Lemma 1.
Let F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) be a frame, u Z = Z 1 Z and be the Galois relation of the frame. Let v | G refer to either G v if G G ( Z 1 ) , v Z or v G if v G 1 and G G ( Z ) .
  • is increasing in each argument place (and thereby its complement I is decreasing in each argument place).
  • ( Γ u ) = { u } and Γ u = { u } is a Galois set.
  • Galois sets are increasing, i.e., u G implies that Γ u G .
  • For a Galois set G, G = u G Γ u .
  • For a Galois set G, G = u G Γ u = v | G { v } .
  • For a Galois set G and any set W, W G iff W G .
Proof. 
By simple calculation, proof details are included in [22] [Lemma 2.2]. For claim 4, u G Γ u G by claim 3 (Galois sets are upsets). □
Definition 4.
For a sorted ( n + 1 ) -ary frame relation R j , its Galois dual relation  R j is defined by R j u 1 u n = ( R j u 1 u n ) , where R j u 1 u n = { u | u R j u 1 u n } .
Notation is simplified by using vectors u = u 1 u n , so the definition is R j u = ( R j u ) . We let u [ ] k be the vector with a hole (or just a place-holder) at the k-th position and write u [ w ] k either to display the element at the k-th place or to designate the result of filling the k-th place of u [ ] k or to denote the result of replacing the element u k in u by the element w. For 1 k n , the k-th section of an ( n + 1 ) -ary relation S is the set w S u [ ] k . For k = n + 1 , the section is simply the set S u .
Definition 5.
Call a frame relation R j  smooth iff every section of its Galois dual relation R j is a Galois set (stable or co-stable according to the sort σ ( R j ) of the relation).
Hereafter, when considering a structure F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) , we always assume that the frame is separated and that all frame relations are smooth. Since no other kind of frame (relational structure) will be considered in this article, we shall refer to relational structures F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) simply as frames, or sorted residuated frames.
Remark 1
(Classical Kripke Frames). Structures F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) , as described above, generalize classical Kripke frames for (poly)modal logic with polyadic modalities, arising by letting Z 1 = Z and where I Z 1 × Z is the identity relation.
For a frame relation R j , for example, a binary relation R , its Galois dual relation is defined (when F is a classical Kripke frame) by y R x iff, for all z, if z R x , then z y , so the section R x is the complement R x of the section R x . The smoothness requirement for frame relations is trivially satisfied; since all sets are stable, U = U .
Furthermore, the preorder x z iff { x } { z } iff (in a classical Kripke frame) { x } { z } is the identity relation, so Γ x = { x } and { y } = { y } . In other words, the principal elements (closed and open) in the frame are precisely the atoms and co-atoms of a powerset Boolean algebra.
A relational model M = ( F , V ) consists of a frame F and a sorted valuation V = ( V 1 , V ) of propositional variables, interpreting a variable p as a Galois stable set V 1 ( p ) G ( Z 1 ) and co-interpreting it as a Galois co-stable set V ( p ) = V 1 ( p ) G ( Z ) . Interpretations and co-interpretations determine each other in the sense that, for any sentence φ L τ , if [ [ φ ] ] G ( Z 1 ) is an interpretation extending a valuation V 1 of propositional variables as stable sets, then [ [ φ ] ] = ( | φ | ) G ( Z ) is the co-interpretation extending the valuation V .
Satisfaction Z 1 × L τ and co-satisfaction (refutation) Z × L τ relations are then defined as expected by Z 1 x φ iff x [ [ φ ] ] and Z y φ iff y ( | φ | ) . Since satisfaction and co-satisfaction determine each other, for each operator, it suffices to provide either its satisfaction or its co-satisfaction (refutation) clause in line with the principle of order-dual relational semantics introduced in [23], as we carry out in Table 2. The relation R 111 that appears in the satisfaction clause for implication is defined in the definition below.
Definition 6.
Define the relation R 111 Z 1 × ( Z 1 × Z 1 ) from the frame relation T as follows:
T 11 Galois dual relation of  T 1 x T 11 z v  iff  y Z ( y T 1 z v x y )
R 11 argument permutation v R 11 z x  iff  x T 11 z v
R 111 Galois dual relation of  R 11 u R 111 z x  iff  v Z ( v R 11 z x u v ) .
In the satisfaction clause for implication, T is the Galois dual relation of T. In the clauses for the modal operators, we define the double dual y R =   ( y R ) (and recall that the Galois dual R is defined from R Z 1 × Z 1 by setting R z = ( R z ) ), and similarly for the double dual R defined from R Z × Z by first letting R y =   ( R y ) be the Galois dual relation and then defining x R =   ( x R ) .
There are two alternative but equivalent semantic clauses for implication: the first uses the Galois dual T of T 1 while the second uses a ternary relation R 111 on Z 1 , derived from T. The equivalence of the two clauses is shown using [15] [Proposition 3.6] and Proposition 5. The first clause is more familiar in a non-distributive setting; see, for example, [9,24]. The second clause is familiar from the relational semantics of the implication connective of relevance logic [25,26].
Remark 2
(Double duals in Kripke Frames). If the frame F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) is a Kripke frame, i.e., Z 1 = Z and I Z 1 × Z is the identity relation (hence x y iff x y ) it was pointed out in Remark 1 that the Galois connection is set-complementation, hence every subset is Galois. Then also the Galois dual relation is a complement relation, e.g., R z = R 11 z . It then follows that double-dual relations are identical to the original relations. Indeed,
y R v iff for any z, if  y R z , then  z v
iff for any z, if  z = v , then it is not the case that y is in  R 11 z
iff  y R 11 v .
Similar arguments apply to the other double-dual relations, with R 111 and T 1 only differing by the permutation of arguments involved in the definition of R 111 .
This has the further consequence that the semantics we define in Table 2 collapses to classical semantics, with co-interpretation y φ being simply y φ and boxes and diamonds being interpreted classically.
Remark 3
( R in the Canonical Frame). By Lemma 4.4 of [7] the relation R 11 is equivalently defined by the familiar clause from the classical case, x R 11 z iff a ( a z a x ) , where x , z are filters, and similarly for R , but now defined on ideals. For the dual relation R , it follows from [7] [Lemma 4.5] that for a filter x and an ideal y, x R y holds iff a ( a y a x ) . The reader may wish to verify that it thereby follows that x R z holds iff a ( a x a z ) , which is the classical definitional clause for the box relation.

3.2. Full Complex Algebras

The logic Λ is just the fusion Λ = Λ Λ Λ of its single-operator sub-systems, axiomatized only by the distribution and normality axioms (on top of the axiomatization for positive lattice logic) as in Table 1; hence, its soundness follows from the soundness of its constituent systems. The proofs are given in Section 3.3 and Propositions 4, 7 and 8, one for each subsystem. In all three propositions, the argument proceeds by using the frame relations to define operations in the complete lattice G ( Z 1 ) of stable sets. This process is uniform, relies on the duality for normal lattice expansions given in [7] and results in defining the dual full complex algebra F + of a frame F . A brief review of the case of an arbitrary normal lattice operator is given below, to be instantiated to the specific case of the implication, box and diamond operators in Section 3.3.1, Section 3.3.2 and Section 3.3.3, respectively.
Given a frame F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) , each relation R j Z j n ( j ) + 1 × k = 1 n ( j ) Z j k generates a sorted image operator, defined as in the Boolean case, except for the sorting
F j ( W ) = { w Z i n ( j ) + 1 | w ( w R j w s = 1 n ( j ) ( w s W s ) ) } = w W R j w .
Then, P = ( : Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) : , ( F j ) j J ) is a two-sorted powerset (poly)modal algebra, where ◇ and all F j are completely normal additive sorted operators and ■ is completely multiplicative and normal. Alternatively, we represent P using the Galois connection P = ( ( ) : Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) :   ( ) , ( F j ) j J ) , since the Galois connection and the residuated modal operators are interdefinable.
If F j is the (sorted) image operator generated by the frame relation R j , let F ¯ j be the closure of the restriction of F j to Galois sets (stable or co-stable according to the sort).
Logics 03 00003 i001
Then, F ¯ j ( G ) = ( F j ( G ) ) , and it follows that F ¯ j is defined on a tuple P of Galois sets by F ¯ j ( P ) = w G ( R j w ) , where, by w P , we mean the conjunction of coordinatewise membership statements w k P k for k = 1 , , n ( j ) .
Theorem 2.
The sorted operator F ¯ j : k = 1 n ( j ) G ( Z j k ) G ( Z j n ( j ) + 1 ) distributes over arbitrary joins of Galois sets in each argument place, returning a join in G ( Z j n ( j ) + 1 ) .
Proof. 
The claim was proven in [7] [Theorem 3.12] using the smoothness property of the frame relation R j . □
By the complete distribution property, F ¯ j is residuated at each argument place and, from residuation, it follows that F ¯ j is normal, i.e., F ¯ j ( G [ ] k ) = .
Note that, for each j J , the sorted set operator F j : k = 1 n ( j ) Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z j k ) Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z j n ( j ) + 1 ) in the (sorted) powerset algebra P is completely additive (it distributes over arbitrary unions) in each argument place. Hence, it is residuated, i.e., for each 1 k n ( j ) , there exists a set map G j , k such that F j ( W [ V ] k ) U iff V G j , k ( W [ U ] k ) , which is defined by Equation (7):
G j , k ( W [ U ] k ) = { V Z j k | F j ( W [ V ] k ) U } .
Theorem 3.
If G j , k is the right residual of F j at the k-th argument place, then its restriction G ¯ j , k to Galois sets is the right residual of F ¯ j at the k-th argument place. Letting P , Q , E range over Galois sets (and P , Q over tuples thereof), the right k-residual G ¯ j , k of F ¯ j can be defined in any of the equivalent ways in Equation (8):
G ¯ j , k ( P ¯ [ Q ] k ) = { E G ( Z j k ) | F j ( P [ E ] k ) Q } = { Γ u G ( Z j k ) | F j ( P [ Γ u ] k ) Q } = { u Z j k | F j ( P [ Γ u ] k ) Q } .
Proof. 
With the smoothness assumption on the relation R j , for each j J , Theorem 2 establishes that the (sorted) operator R ( F j ) = F ¯ j distributes over arbitrary joins in each argument place k. Hence, it is residuated and the residual is canonically defined by G ¯ j , k ( P ¯ [ Q ] k ) = { E G ( Z j k ) | F j ( P [ E ] k ) Q } , where the join is taken in G ( Z j k ) . The first line of Equation (8) means that the join in question is actually a union. That the three lines of the equation are equivalent ways of defining the residual was proven in [7] [Proposition 3.14, Lemma 3.15]. □
The Galois connection is a dual isomorphism of the complete lattices of stable and co-stable sets, ( ) : G ( Z 1 ) G ( Z ) op :   ( ) . This allows for extracting single-sorted operators F ¯ j 1 : k = 1 n ( j ) G ( Z 1 ) G ( Z 1 ) and F ¯ j : k = 1 n ( j ) G ( Z ) G ( Z ) by composition with the Galois connection maps
F ¯ j 1 ( A 1 , , A n ( j ) ) = F ¯ j ( , A k j k = 1 , , A r j r = , ) if j n ( j ) + 1 = 1 ( F ¯ j ( , A k j k = 1 , , A r j r = , ) ) if j n ( j ) + 1 = .
From the residual G ¯ j , k of F ¯ j , we can similarly extract a single-sorted operator G ¯ j , k 1 .
It follows from Theorem 2 and the definition of F ¯ j 1 that, if the sort of R j is σ ( j ) = ( j n + 1 ; j 1 j n ) , then F ¯ j 1 is a normal lattice operator of distribution type δ ( j ) = ( j 1 , , j n ; j n + 1 ) (co)distributing over arbitrary meets/joins according to its distribution type.
Definition 7.
For a frame F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) , its full complex algebra F + is defined as the normal lattice expansion F + = ( G ( Z 1 ) , , , , , Z 1 , ( F ¯ j 1 ) j J ) .
Remark 4
(Generalized Jónsson-Tarski Framework). If the frame F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) is a classical Kripke frame (see Remark 1), i.e., Z 1 = Z , with I Z 1 × Z 1 being the identity relation, then the Galois connection is set complementation and the closure operator is the identity operator on subsets of Z 1 . In that case, Equation (6) simply defines the Jónsson–Tarski image operators [6].
Operations on Boolean algebras that are not additive arise by appropriately composing with set complementation. In generalizing the Jónsson–Tarski framework, we include all normal lattice operators but notice that, in the special case of Kripke frames, the maps F ¯ j that we define as closure of the restriction to stable sets are identical to F j , since every subset is stable and closure means taking the complement of the complement. Since there is only one sort, in the sense that Z 1 = Z , the maps F j are single-sorted normal additive operators (Jónsson–Tarski operators). In Equation (9), composition with the set-complementation operation is actually performed in the case of a classical Kripke frame, returning a set operation that either distributes or co-distributes over either intersections or unions (which are the same as joins of stable sets in the Kripke frame case).
For an example, consider the case of defining the box operator of distribution type ( ; ) . The relation R generates an additive (diamond) operator Logics 03 00003 i008 on Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) = Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) , F j ( U ) = Logics 03 00003 i008 U . To obtain the box operator on stable subsets of Z 1 (which, in the Kripke frame case, are all subsets of Z 1 ), we compose appropriately with the Galois connection, i.e., we set A = ( Logics 03 00003 i008 A ) . But, in the case of a classical Kripke frame, the Galois connection is simply the set-complement operation, and hence we obtain the classical definition U = ( Logics 03 00003 i008 ( U ) ) .

3.3. Soundness of the Fusion Logic Λ in the Relational Semantics

3.3.1. Implication

Proposition 4.
The single-operator minimal logic Λ (the logic of implicative lattices) is sound in the relational semantics.
Proof. 
This proof is a brief review based on [15], where representation and duality results for implicative lattices and Heyting algebras were presented.
Let F = ( s , Z , I , R , , σ ) be a frame where σ ( R ) = ( : 1 ) . To make the connection with [15] easier, where the case of implicative lattices was discussed, we henceforth use T for the relation R , occasionally displaying its sort as a superscript T 1 Z × ( Z 1 × Z ) . The relation T generates an image operator F = : Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) × Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) (therefore an additive and normal set operator), defined as in Equation (6), instantiating to (10):
U V = { y Y | x , v ( x U v V y T x v ) } = x U v V T x v .
The closure of its restriction to Galois sets (according to its distribution type) gives the sorted Galois-set operator F ¯ = | : G ( Z 1 ) × G ( Z ) G ( Z ) .
By Theorem 2, | distributes over arbitrary joins of stable sets in the first argument place and of co-stable sets in the second argument place, returning a join of co-stable sets. Composing with the Galois connection, we define : G ( Z 1 ) × G ( Z 1 ) G ( Z 1 ) by setting
A C = ( A | C ) = ( A C ) = ( A C ) .
A sentence φ ψ is then interpreted as [ [ φ ψ ] ] = [ [ φ ] ] [ [ ψ ] ] = ( [ [ φ ] ] | ( | ψ | ) ) . In [15] [Proposition 3.6], the following were proven, where T is the Galois dual of T.
1 . i I A i j J C j = i I , j J ( A i C j ) 2 . A C = x A , C y ( Γ x   { y } ) 3 . u T x y iff u ( Γ x   { y } ) , for all u , x X and y Y 4 . u ( A C ) iff x Z 1 y Z ( x A C y u T x y ) } .
Item 4 determines the first semantic clause for implication that we have presented. By the result in item 1, the operation ⇒ has the same distribution type as →. The normality of ⇒ follows from the normality of the additive operator | , given the definition of ⇒. Since the axiomatization of the minimal logic Λ only enforces normality and (co)distribution properties for →, we may conclude that Λ is sound in frames F = ( s , Z , I , R , R 11 , T 1 ) . □
It remains to justify our claim that the two satisfaction clauses given for → in Table 2 are indeed equivalent. The proof reveals that the stable set operation ⇒ is the restriction to stable sets of a set operator T , residuated with a product operator ⨀ (i.e., the restriction of T to stable sets returns a stable set).
Let ⨀ be the binary image operator generated by the derived relation R 111 (Definition 6), defined on Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) × Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) by
U V = { x Z 1 | u , z ( u U z V x R 111 u z ) } = u U z V R 111 u z .
Being completely additive, ⨀ is residuated (in both argument places) and we let T be the residual U T W = { X | U X W } , satisfying the residuation condition V U T W iff U V W . Since x U T W iff U { x } W , a straightforward calculation, left to the interested reader, gives
U T W = { x Z 1 | z , u Z 1 ( u U z R 111 u x z W ) }
Let ⦶ be the closure of the restriction of ⨀ to stable sets.
Proposition 5.
The operators , are residuated. In other words, for any Galois stable sets A , F , C , we have A F C iff F A C . Consequently, ⇒ is the restriction to Galois stable sets of the residual T of .
Proof. 
The first claim of this proposition is part of the second claim of [15] [Proposition 3.10], and we refer the reader to it for the proof. The second claim follows by Theorem 3, which is a special instance of [7] [Theorem 3.14]. □
Given Equations (14), (12) and Proposition 5, we have the following equivalent characterizations of the stable set A C :
A C = { x Z 1 | u Z 1 y Z ( u A C y x T u y ) } = { x Z 1 | u , z Z 1 ( u A z R 111 u x z C ) } .
Remark 5.
Since the sorted operator : Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) × Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) is completely additive in the left argument place, it has a left adjoint : Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) × Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) , i.e.,
U V Y   i f f   V U Y ,   f o r   U Z 1   a n d   V , Y Z .
It is defined by U Y = { W Z | U W Y } .
We have defined | as the closure of the restriction of to Galois sets. In other words, A | B = ( A B ) .
By Proposition 3, the restriction of to Galois sets is the right residual of | in its first argument place, i.e., A | B D iff B A D , and it is defined by A D = { y Z | A Γ y D } .
Recall that, in (11), we defined A C = ( A | C ) = ( A C ) . So, we have
F A C iff F ( A | C )
iff A | C F
iff C A F
iff ( A F ) C
By the uniqueness of adjoints, the stable set operator can be alternatively defined from the residual of | by A F = ( A F ) .

3.3.2. Necessity

The relation R = R generates an image operator F = Logics 03 00003 i008: Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) (therefore additive and normal), defined as in Equation (6), instantiating to
Logics 03 00003 i009
The closure of its restriction to Galois sets (according to its distribution type) gives the sorted Galois set operator
Logics 03 00003 i010
By Theorem 2, F ¯ distributes over arbitrary joins of co-stable sets (members of the complete lattice G ( Z ) ). Define : G ( Z 1 ) G ( Z 1 ) from Logics 03 00003 i011 by setting
Logics 03 00003 i012
By Theorem 2, q Q A q = q Q ( A q ) .
A more direct proof of the distribution property can, however, be given for the particular case of ⧈, as we show in the sequel. The interest of the alternative proof is that it shows that ⧈ is the restriction to stable sets of a multiplicative operation R on Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) and it provides a direct proof of soundness for Λ . We explain below.
Let R = R 1 be the Galois dual of R and R Z 1 × Z 1 be its double dual defined by x R = ( x R ) for any x Z 1 .
The relation R generates a dual image operator R : Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 )
R U = { x | u ( x R u u U ) } = { x | x R U } .
Proposition 6.
is the restriction of R to stable sets.
Proof. 
By definition, ⧈ A = ( F ¯ A ) = ( F A ) = ( F A ) . Since F is the image operator generated on Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) by the relation R Z × Z , we obtain from ⧈ A = ( F A ) that
x A iff y ( v ( y R v and A v ) x y )
iff v ( A v y ( y R v y { x } ) )
iff v ( A v ( R v { x } ) )
iff v ( A v ( Γ x R v ) )
iff v ( A v x R v )
iff A x R
iff x R A
and, given the definition of R , the proof is complete. Note that R v { x } is equivalent to Γ x R v by the fact that R v is a closed element. □
Proposition 7.
The single-operator minimal logic Λ is sound in the relational semantics.
Proof. 
Since R distributes over arbitrary intersections of subsets of Z 1 , as a classical dual image operator, so does over any intersections of stable sets. The normality of follows from the normality of the classical dual image operator R . It follows from the satisfaction clause for □ in Table 2 that [ [ φ ] ] = [ [ φ ] ] ; hence, soundness follows. □
For later use, we list here a lemma on the monotonicity properties of the relation R .
Lemma 2.
The relation R is decreasing in the first and increasing in the second argument place, i.e., R R .
Proof. 
By definition, z R = ( z R ) ; hence, it is a Galois set and therefore increasing. For the first argument place, assume that u z and let z R p . To show that u R p , let y Z be arbitrary such that u R y . It suffices to obtain p y . The relation R , defined by setting v Z R v = ( R v ) , is a Galois set, and hence increasing. Then, from the hypotheses that u z and u R y , we obtain z R y . By the hypothesis that z R p , the conclusion p y follows. □
Since ⊟ is the restriction of R to stable sets, we hereafter just write ⊟ for either. For stable sets, we typically use uppercase letters A , C , F from the beginning of the alphabet (and B , D , E for co-stable sets) and we use uppercase letters U , V , W from the end of the alphabet for arbitrary subsets; therefore, no confusion should hopefully arise. However, in some cases, we may restore the subscript R for clarity purposes.

3.3.3. Possibility

Proposition 8.
The single-operator minimal logic Λ is sound in the relational semantics.
Proof. 
The relation R = R 11 generates an image operator F = Logics 03 00003 i013 : Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) (therefore additive and normal) defined as in Equation (6), instantiating to
Logics 03 00003 i014
The closure of its restriction to Galois sets (according to its distribution type) gives the sorted Galois set operator F ¯ = 🞜 : G ( Z 1 ) G ( Z 1 ) , defined by 🞜 A = ( Logics 03 00003 i013 A ) .
By Theorem 2, F ¯ distributes over arbitrary joins of stable sets (members of the complete lattice G ( Z 1 ) ), i.e., 🞜 q Q A q = q Q 🞜 ( A q ) . The normality of 🞜 follows from the normality of the classical image operator Logics 03 00003 i013.
The semantic clause for diamond is stated in terms of co-satisfaction (refutation); hence, we compute the dual operator (in G ( Z ) ), which is defined by F ¯ ( B ) = ( F ¯ ( B ) ) . Therefore, ( | φ | ) = [ [ φ ] ]   = ( 🞜 [ [ φ ] ] )   = ( Logics 03 00003 i013 [ [ φ ] ] ) = ( Logics 03 00003 i013 [ [ φ ] ] ) . By a computation similar to that in the proof of Proposition 6, we obtain [ [ φ ] ]   = ( | φ | ) = { y | v Z ( y R v v ( | φ | ) ) } , and this establishes soundness. □
The double dual relation R Z × Z , used in the above proof, is defined from R 11 in a similar way to R . Namely, we let R Z × Z 1 be the Galois dual of R and we set y R = ( y R ) .
For later use, we define in G ( Z ) a box operator by B = ( Logics 03 00003 i013 B ) . Letting also R be the dual image operator generated in Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) , which is the relation R , the proof of the following result is completely similar to the proof of Proposition 6 and it can be safely left to the reader.
Proposition 9.
The co-stable set operator is the restriction of the dual image operator R generated by the relation R .

4. Frames for Distribution-Free K

For the fused modal system Λ , we have included the classical distribution and normality properties for implication and for both the box and diamond in the axiomatization. It is, however, the system K = Λ + { ( p q ) p q } that is the minimal distribution-free normal modal logic that raises some issues of interest.
For distribution-free systems, the issue in question is, roughly, to find a frame class that will allow for approximating the box operator both from above (upper box) and from below (lower box). In the canonical extension of a lattice, this issue corresponds to the question of whether the σ (lower approximation) and π (upper approximation) extensions of a lattice map can be shown to be identical.

4.1. Intermediate Structure and Lower and Upper MacNeille Extensions for

The set Q = { Γ x | x Z 1 } {   { y } | y Z } = Q 1 Q of principal (closed and open) elements of G ( Z 1 ) is partially ordered by inclusion. Let Q ¯ be its Dedekind–MacNeille completion. Q ¯ can be constructed as the family of sets that are stable under the Dedekind–MacNeille Galois connection U = ( U ) u , where U u , U are the sets of upper bounds and lower bounds, respectively, of U. Q ¯ is uniquely characterized as the completion of Q in which Q is both join- and meet-dense [27] [Theorem 7.41]. Any Galois stable set can be equivalently approximated both from above and from below since it is both the join of closed elements below it ( A = x A Γ x = x A Γ x ) and the meet of open elements in which it is contained ( A = A y { y } = {   { y } | A   { y } } ). It follows from this that Q ¯ G ( Z 1 ) . The structure Q = Q 1 Q will be referred to as the intermediate structure.
What is now needed is to be able to approximate operations on stable sets both from above, taking their upper MacNeille extension, and from below, taking their lower MacNeille extension, having first defined them in the intermediate structure.
Recall that, for any stable sets A , C G ( Z 1 ) ,
A C = x A C y ( Γ x   { y } ) by (12) ([15] [Proposition 3.6])
A = A y   { y } = A y { y } by Proposition 6
🞜 A = x A 🞜 Γ x by Theorem 2.
Since A y iff A   { y } , the box operator is approximated from above (by computing first its values on open elements that cover its argument A). We write u for when we need to distinguish it from the lower approximation of the box operator, technically defined in Definition 9, so as to satisfy Γ x = u Γ x , { y } = u { y } and A = Γ x A Γ x . The extensions , u are the lower and upper MacNeille extensions [28] of their restriction to elements of the intermediate structure.
The membership in each of Γ x { y } , { y } and 🞜 Γ x is definable by the respective conditions shown below:
z ( Γ x   { y } ) iff z T x y
z { y } iff z R y
z 🞜 Γ x iff y ( y R Γ x z y ) .
To ensure soundness of the K-axiom, it suffices to fulfill the prerequisite that the axiom holds in the intermediate structure and that the upper MacNeille extension of the box operator is contained in its lower extension, u A A , for any A G ( Z 1 ) .
Note that, if the full complex algebra of the frame is a canonical extension of its subalgebra of clopen elements (assuming that enough axioms are included so that we can prove that the clopens form a subalgebra of the full complex algebra of the frame), then it can be shown that identity u = actually holds. This can be carried out in detail, but as a second-order axiomatization of frames will be necessarily involved, we prefer to take a more direct (and simpler) approach.

4.2. Refined Frames

A frame in the frame class defined in Table 3 will be called a refined frame. For our current purposes in this article, R j is any one of the frame relations R , R 11 or T 1 . The relation S 11 mentioned in axiom (F5) is defined below.
Definition 8.
Define the relation S 11 by z S 11 x iff z R Γ x . Equivalently, z S 11 x iff z Γ x .
Definition 9.
Define the lower approximation of the box operator on stable sets by Γ x = S 11 x and extend to any stable set A by setting A = x A Γ x .
Since x A Γ x = A and u Γ x = { u | u R Γ x } = { u | u S 11 x } = S 11 x = Γ x , axiom (F6) is equivalent to the inclusion u A A for any stable set A.
Remark 6.
Axiom (F6) is second-order. We leave it as an open problem whether a first-order axiomatization of frames validating the K-axiom in the distribution-free case can be found. The situation is quite different for the case of modal extensions of the intuitionistic propositional calculus, as shown in Section 7.
For each j J , we may define a map j ^ ( u ) = v iff R j u = Γ v , given (F3). By separation (F1), the map j ^ is well defined, since v is unique, for each tuple u . In other words,
w R j u iff j ^ ( u ) w , equivalently R j u = Γ ( j ^ ( u ) ) .
Definition 10
(Point Operators). Let j ^ , j ^ and j ^ be the point operators of Equation (19) corresponding to the relations T , R and R , respectively. To make the arguments more readable, we rename them, using mnemonic notation, by setting j ^ = , j ^ = and j ^ = Logics 03 00003 i013. Given axiom (F5), we also let S 11 x = Γ ( x ) , thus using the point operator as a sorted map on Z 1 Z .
It is straightforward to verify that , , Logics 03 00003 i013 are monotone in each of their argument places.

4.3. K-Frames

Definition 11.
A refined frame F = ( s , Z , I , R , R , R , σ ) is a K-frame provided that the additional axiom (FK) below holds:
(FK) x Z 1 y , v , w Z [ v T 1 ( x ) ( y ) w x y ) v R w ] .
Recall that v T 1 z y holds iff ( z y ) v .
Proposition 10.
For any stable sets A , C in a K-frame, ( A C ) ( A C ) .
Proof. 
If the frame is a K-frame, then (FK) directly implies the point inequality ( x y ) x y . By the properties in (12), Γ x   { y } = T x y =   { x y } , where T is the Galois dual relation of the frame relation T 1 and : Z 1 × Z Z is the point operator defined by x y = v iff T x y = Γ v . Hence, we obtain
( Γ x   { y } ) = (   { x y } ) =   { ( x y ) } Γ x (   { y } ) = Γ ( x )   { y } =   { x y }
By definition of the order, the inequality ( x y ) x y is equivalent to the inclusion { ( x y ) }   { x y } . It follows that the K-axiom holds in the intermediate structure:
( Γ x   { y } ) Γ x (   { y } ) .
From (12), given stable sets A , C G ( Z 1 ) , we have ( A C ) = x A C y ( Γ x   { y } ) , given that A C = ( x A ) ( C y   { y } ) = x A C y ( Γ x   { y } ) and that distributes over arbitrary intersections. The following calculation proves the claim:
( A C ) = x A C y ( Γ x   { y } ) Properties in (12)
x A C y ( Γ x { y } ) By (20)
= ( x A Γ x ) ( C y { y } ) Properties in (12)
= ( x A Γ x ) ( C y   { y } ) ⧈ distributes over meets
( x A Γ x ) C By axiom (F6)
= A C
and this completes the proof. □

5. Frames for the Standard Extensions of K

5.1. D-Frames

Let F be a refined frame. If the additional axiom
(FD) x Z 1 S 11 x R x
holds in the frame, then we call F a D-frame.
Lemma 3.
The following are equivalent:
1. 
(FD);
2. 
x Z 1 Logics 03 00003 i013 x x ;
3. 
x Z 1 ( x ) R x ;
4. 
x Z 1 Γ x Logics 03 00003 i013 Γ x .
Proof. 
The equivalence of the first three is immediate from definitions. Since the frame is refined, Γ x Γ x = Γ ( x ) = S 11 x . Since also Logics 03 00003 i013 Γ x = R x , the equivalence of (3) and (4) is clear, too. □
Proposition 11.
In a D-frame, for any A G ( Z 1 ) , it holds that A 🞜 A .
Proof. 
In a D-frame, A x A Γ x x A Logics 03 00003 i013 Γ x = x A 🞜 Γ x 🞜 A , using Lemma 3. □

5.2. Axioms T, S4 and Reflexive/Transitive Frames

A flat extension of the system Λ = Λ Λ Λ is an extension by axioms introduced in a constituent logic of the fusion, and hence involves a single operator. This is the case of the T and S4 axioms for each of the operators , , but also axioms strengthening the lattice base for implication, such as including a rule φ ψ φ ψ , whose algebraic counterpart is an integrality constraint in the lattice— a b iff 1 a b —or requiring that the lattice be distributive, or a Heyting algebra. For such extensions, involving the lattice base axioms only, we refer the reader to Section 7 and to [15].
Modeling the logics of implicative modal lattices that assume any of the T, B or S4 axioms is particularly simple and proofs can be carried out assuming only axioms (F1)–(F4) for refined frames in Table 3.
Let Γ be a subset of the axioms in the following list.
(T◇) φ φ (T□) φ φ
(S4◇) φ φ (S4□) φ φ
We already know that each of the logics Λ Γ is canonical, as this is a consequence of [13] [Theorem 6.3], in which Gehrke and Harding established that, if a lattice equation involves only operators (distributing over joins), or only dual operators (distributing over meets), then the equation is preserved under canonical extensions.
In this section, we identify the corresponding classes of frames that validate Γ .
A fast answer to the correspondence problem for axioms in Γ can be given by considering the powerset algebras (Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) , , Logics 03 00003 i013 ) , ( Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z ) , , Logics 03 00003 i013), where recall that Logics 03 00003 i013, Logics 03 00003 i008 are the image operators generated by the relations R 11 , R , respectively, that we defined A = ( Logics 03 00003 i013 A ) , B = ( Logics 03 00003 i013 B ) , and that we have shown that , are the restrictions to their respective lattices of Galois sets of the powerset dual operators R , R generated by the double dual relations R , R , respectively (and we dropped the subscript R, as it is not necessary). Thus, the T and S4 axioms are valid for iff its generating relation R is reflexive or transitive, respectively, and similarly for ◫. Classically, it suffices to state only the T or S4 axiom for box and derive it for diamond by duality ( = ¬ ¬ ). Essentially, the same proof can be given in the distribution-free setting.
Indeed, assume, for example, that the relation R Z × Z is reflexive, so the dual operator : G ( Z ) G ( Z ) satisfies the T-axiom B B . Let A = B . Then, we have B B iff ( Logics 03 00003 i013 B ) B iff B ( Logics 03 00003 i013 B ) iff A ( Logics 03 00003 i013 A ) , and recall that we have defined 🞜 : G ( Z 1 ) G ( Z 1 ) by 🞜 A = ( Logics 03 00003 i013 A ) .
The argument just given completely settles the problem, so we have proved the following.
Proposition 12.
In G ( Z 1 ) , , 🞜 satisfy the T-axiom iff R , R are reflexive and they satisfy the S4-axiom iff the relations are transitive.
The next four propositions offer alternative characterizations of the frames. We prove the first two and leave the proofs of the other two to the interested reader.
Proposition 13.
The following are equivalent:
1. 
A A for any A G ( Z 1 ) ;
2. 
{ y }   { y } for all y Z ;
3. 
y y for all y Z ;
4. 
The frame relation R Z × Z is reflexive;
5. 
The double dual R Z 1 × Z 1 of R is reflexive.
Proof. 
Assuming that A A , we have, in particular,   { y }   { y } . This is equivalent to { y }   { y } , i.e., y y . Since R y = Γ ( y ) , we obtain that y R y holds for any y Z , i.e., R is reflexive. To show that this implies the reflexivity of R , first, we calculate its defining condition.
We have that y R v iff v y , and then u R v iff u v . Consequently, x R z iff v ( x R v z v ) iff v ( x v z v ) .
By the above, x R x holds iff v ( x v x v ) . Let v Z be such that x v , i.e., x R v , which is equivalent, by definition, to y ( y R v x y ) . The case assumption is that R is reflexive, and hence v R v holds and then x v follows; hence, R is indeed reflexive.
The reflexivity of R immediately implies that A A , for any A G ( Z 1 ) , by the fact that x A iff z ( x R z z A ) . □
Proposition 14.
The following are equivalent:
1. 
A A for all A G ( Z 1 ) ;
2. 
{ y } { y } ;
3. 
y y for all y Z ;
4. 
R Z × Z is transitive;
5. 
The double dual R Z 1 × Z 1 of R is transitive.
Proof. 
Assuming that A A , for any A G ( Z 1 ) , we have, in particular,   { y }   { y } for any y Z . This is equivalent to { y }   { y } and then, by definition of the order, it follows that y y .
For the transitivity of R , assume that y R v R w , i.e., w v and v y . Then, by the case assumption and monotonicity of the point operator ⊟, we obtain w w v y , i.e., y R w holds.
Note that the transitivity of R implies that the inclusion A A holds, so (1)–(3) are pairwise equivalent.
To show that R is transitive, assume that x R u R z and recall that x R z iff v ( x R v z v ) iff v ( x v z v ) . Then, let v Z be such that x v . By case assumption, v v , and since ⍊ is increasing in both argument places, we obtain that x v . This means that x R v and, given the definition of x R as the Galois dual of x R and the assumption that x R u , we obtain u v . But, u R z by assumption, and then, given the defining condition above for R and our last conclusion that u v , it follows that z v . Thereby, x R z does indeed hold.
Finally, we assume that R is transitive and we show that if A G ( Z 1 ) , then A A holds, where recall that x A iff z ( x R z z A ) .
Let x A . If x A , let u be such that x R u , but u A . Then, there is z such that u R z but z A . This contradicts the assumption x A since, by transitivity, we obtain, given the u and z above, that x R z , and hence z A . □
Proposition 15.
The following are equivalent:
1. 
A 🞜 A for all A G ( Z 1 ) ;
2. 
Γ x 🞜 Γ x for all x Z 1 ;
3. 
Logics 03 00003 i013 x x for all x Z 1 ;
4. 
R is reflexive;
5. 
The double dual R Z × Z of R is reflexive.
Proof. 
This is left to the interested reader. □
Proposition 16.
The following are equivalent:
1. 
🞜 🞜 A 🞜 A for any stable set A;
2. 
🞜 🞜 Γ x 🞜 Γ x for any point x Z 1 ;
3. 
Logics 03 00003 i013 x Logics 03 00003 i013Logics 03 00003 i013 x for any point x Z 1 ;
4. 
R Z 1 × Z 1 is transitive;
5. 
The double dual R Z × Z of R is transitive.
Proof. 
This is left to the interested reader. □
Remark 7.
In Conradie and Palmigiano [16], a correspondent for the T-axiom in a non-distributive setting is calculated as an example of applying the ALBA algorithm. The authors work within the framework of RS-frames and calculate that the axiom φ φ is valid in any RS-frame where the accessibility relation S is a subrelation of the Galois relation (which they denote by I). This is only in appearance different from the reflexivity condition for R that we have calculated. As explained in [14], every example of the relational modeling of a logical operator in a non-distributive setting that has been given in the RS-frames approach uses an accessibility relation S that is the Galois dual relation R of the relation used in this author’s approach. We leave it to the reader to verify that R , R are reflexive iff R and ( R ) 1 , respectively.
Remark 8.
A different approach is taken in Brezhanishvili, Dmitrieva, de Groot and Morachini [4], where weak, distribution-free, modal logic systems are discussed. The system of their focus is a distribution-free version of Dunn’s PML (positive modal logic) [1]. A single relation R in frames generates both , , and the interpretation for modal formulae is standard, except that, in pursuing a way to define frames that validate at least one of Dunn’s interaction axioms, they find it necessary to abandon the distribution of diamonds over joins. The authors do not work with canonical extensions but model their logic(s) of interest in (topological) semilattices, develop a related correspondence theory and calculate that φ φ and φ φ are valid in semilattice frames satisfying the conditions x y ( x R y and y x ) and x y ( x R y and x y ) , respectively. In other words, reflexivity is a property of the composite relations R and R , respectively.

5.3. Axiom B and Residuated Box/Diamond

Let F = ( s , Z , I , R , R 11 , T 1 ) , where we displayed the sort of the frame relations, be a frame satisfying at least axioms (F1)–(F4) of Table 3, and assume that the frame also satisfies the following axiom:
(FB) x Z 1 y Z ( x R y y R x ) ,
In other words, R = ( R ) 1 . Given the definitions, axiom (FB) is equivalent to the condition Γ x   { y } iff Γ(Logics 03 00003 i013 x )   { y } in the intermediate structure. In turn, this is equivalent to the following condition, which is more convenient to use:
(FB) x Z 1 y Z ( x y Logics 03 00003 i013xy).
Proposition 17.
In a frame satisfying at least axioms (F1)–(F4) of Table 3 together with (FB), the operators , 🞜 in the full complex algebra of the frame are residuated, i.e., for all stable sets A , C , we have A C iff 🞜 A C .
Proof. 
The claim is equivalent to A C y   { y } iff x A Γ ( Logics 03 00003 i013 x ) C iff C x A { Logics 03 00003 i013 x }   .
Assuming that A C y   { y } , let C y and x A . From the assumption, we obtain x y and, by axiom (FB), this is equivalent to Logics 03 00003 i013 x y . This shows that C x A { Logics 03 00003 i013 x }   . Conversely, from the hypothesis C x A { Logics 03 00003 i013 x }   , if x A and C y , we obtain Logics 03 00003 i013 x y and then, by axiom (FB), x y follows. Thus, A C y   { y } . □

5.4. S5-Frames

Let F be a refined frame (axiomatized in Table 3) and assume that the following frame axiom also holds:
(FS5) x Z 1 [ ( Logics 03 00003 i013 x ) R R 11 x and R 11 ( x ) S 11 x ] .
Given the definition of S 11 and the fact that R 11 x = Γ ( Logics 03 00003 i013 x ) , (Logics 03 00003 i013 x ) R R 11 x can be equivalently restated as x Z 1 ( Logics 03 00003 i013 x , Logics 03 00003 i013 x ) S 11 .
Lemma 4.
For a stable set A, if x A , then Logics 03 00003 i013 x 🞜 A .
Proof. 
The hypothesis is equivalent to Γ x A , from which, by monotonicity, we obtain that 🞜 Γ x 🞜 A . The left-hand side is equal to Γ ( Logics 03 00003 i013 x ) ; hence, if x A , indeed ⊟ Logics 03 00003 i013 x 🞜 A . □
Proposition 18.
Let F be a refined frame satisfying, in addition, axiom (FS5). Then, for any stable set A, the inclusion 🞜 A 🞜 A is true.
Proof. 
Since 🞜 A = x A 🞜 Γ x = x A Logics 03 00003 i013 Γ x = x A Γ ( Logics 03 00003 i013 x ) , it suffices to argue that, for all x A , Logics 03 00003 i013 x 🞜 A . By Lemma 4, ⊟ Logics 03 00003 i013 x 🞜 A . The new axiom (FS5) is equivalent to the point inequality ⊟ Logics 03 00003 i013 x Logics 03 00003 i013 x. Galois sets are increasing; hence, Logics 03 00003 i013 x 🞜 A . □
The dual case for the validity of 🞜 A A is similar and left to the interested reader.

6. Canonical Frame, Canonicity of Axioms and Completeness

6.1. Canonical Frame Construction

Theorem 4
(Realizing Distribution Types). Let L τ = ( L , , , , 0 , 1 , ( f j ) j J ) be a normal lattice expansion, where, for each j J , δ ( j ) = ( j 1 , , j n ( j ) ; j n ( j ) + 1 ) is the distribution type of the normal lattice operator f j .
Define the dual frame ( L τ ) + = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) of L τ as follows:
  • s = { 1 , } , Z = ( Z 1 , Z ) , where Z 1 = Filt ( L τ ) , Z = Idl ( L τ ) are the sets of non-empty lattice filters and ideals, respectively;
  • x I y iff x y = ;
  • For each j J and where δ ( j ) = ( j 1 , , j n ( j ) ; j n ( j ) + 1 ) is the distribution type of f j , the relation R j of sort σ ( j ) = ( j n ( j ) + 1 ; j 1 j n ( j ) ) is defined as in the classical case, except for the sorting, by
    w R j u   i f f a 1 , , a n L ( k = 1 n ( j ) ( a k u k ) f j a w )
    and it is smooth.
Then, the full complex algebra ( ( L τ ) + ) + of the dual frame ( L τ ) + of the normal lattice expansion L τ is a canonical extension of L τ with embedding map sending a lattice element to the set of filters containing it and such that, if δ ( j ) = ( j 1 , , j n ( j ) ; 1 ) (the operator f j outputs joins), then F ¯ j 1 is the σ-extension of f j ; otherwise, it is its π-extension (in the sense of [13] [Definition 4.1]).
Proof. 
A detailed exposition of bounded lattice representation and duality is given in [11] and, in a context of implicative lattices, in [15], both presenting special cases of the duality for normal lattice expansions in [7]. The lattice representation and duality underlying the results of each of [7,11,15] first appeared in print in [29,30]. The way that we define point operators and canonical relations was first introduced in [31]. Point operators, as we define them, are the same as the duals of lattice quasi-operators defined in the dual lattice space by Moshier and Jipsen [32,33], as we detailed in [7] [Remark 4.2, Remark 4.8]. That the complete lattice of stable sets is identical to the complete lattice of the Moshier–Jipsen saturated sets (defined as the intersections of open filters that cover them) was proven in [11] [Proposition 4.6].
For an implicative modal lattice L , following [11,15], we let Z 1 = Filt ( L ) , Z = Idl ( L ) be the sets of non-empty lattice filters and ideals, respectively, and we define the relation I Filt ( L ) × Idl ( L ) by x I y iff x y = (with the Galois relation of the frame defined, then by x y iff x y ). The underlying lattice of L is embedded in the complete lattice G ( Z 1 ) of stable sets of filters via the map ζ 1 defined by ζ 1 ( a ) = { x Filt ( L ) | a x } = X a and dually embedded in G ( Z ) via the map ζ ( a ) = { y Idl ( L ) | a y } = Y a . Meets are taken to intersections and lattice joins to joins (closures of unions) of stable sets in G ( Z 1 ) .
Note that X a = { x Filt ( L ) | x a x } = Γ x a and Y a = { y Idl ( L ) | y a y } = Γ y a , where, for a lattice element e, we write x e , y e for the principal filter and ideal, respectively, generated by e. The sets X a are clopen elements of G ( Z 1 ) , since Γ x a =   { y a } =   ( Γ y a ) (and then so are the sets Y a in G ( Z ) ).
Taking the families B = { X a | a L } and C = { Y a | a L } as bases for topologies on Z 1 = Filt ( L ) and Z = Idl ( L ) , respectively, it was shown in [11] that B , C generate spectral topologies ([11] [Proposition 4.2]), that B , C are the families of compact open, Galois stable and co-stable sets, respectively, and that they are dually isomorphic lattices and sublattices of G ( Z 1 ) , G ( Z ) , respectively ([11] [Proposition 4.4]). Furthermore, the map a X a is a bounded lattice isomorphism ([11] [Theorem 4.5]).
That the full complex algebra of the dual frame of the lattice is a canonical extension of the lattice was proven in [13] [Proposition 2.6].
The canonical relations R , R 11 and R 1 = T are defined using the canonical point operators : Z Z , Logics 03 00003 i013 : Z 1 Z 1 and : Z 1 × Z Z , setting y R v iff v y , x R z iff Logics 03 00003 i013 z x and y T 1 x v iff x v y , given the point operator definitions in (21)
Logics 03 00003 i015
A point operator ⊟, generating the relation S 11 , is defined on filters by x = { x a | a x } .
The reader can easily verify that the relations R , R 11 and R 1 = T are equivalently defined by the respective instance of the clause in the statement of this theorem. The general proof (for any normal lattice expansion and the associated canonical relations) of this fact is given in [7] [Lemma 4.4].
Operators , 🞜 and ⇒ are defined in the canonical frame from the frame relations as detailed in Section 3 for any frame. That the so-defined maps are the σ (for 🞜 ) and π -extension (for , ), depending on the output type of their distribution type, was argued for, for any normal lattice expansion, in [14] [Proposition 28].
That the lattice representation map a X a is an isomorphism of implicative modal lattices follows from the observations below:
a X a = Γ x a = Γ ( Logics 03 00003 i013 x a ) = Logics 03 00003 i013 Γ x a = 🞜 Γ x a = 🞜 X a
a X a = Γ x a =   { y a } =   { y a } = (   { y a } ) = Γ x a = X a
a b X a b = X a X b , by [15] [Proposition 4.8].
The axioms (F1)–(F4) for a refined frame (though the term was not used) were argued for in [7] for any normal lattice expansion.
For axiom (F5), the defining condition for the relation S 11 in the canonical frame is z S 11 x iff x z , where we define x to be the filter generated by the set { a | a x } , equivalently, x = a x x a . To verify that z S 11 x iff z R Γ x , we verify that S 11 x = Γ x . Since Γ x = x y   { y } = x y   { y } , the claim to prove is equivalent to showing that, for any filters x , z , x z iff y ( x y z y ) , where, in the canonical frame, ⍊ means a non-empty intersection. If x z and y is an ideal such that a x y , then, by a x and a y , we obtain a x and a y . Hence, a z y .
Conversely, assume that y ( x y z y ) , but suppose, for a contradiction, that x z . Hence, there is an element a x such that a z . But, since a x y a (where y a is the principal ideal generated by the element a), the case hypothesis implies that z y a . Since y a = y a , we obtain a z , a contradiction.
Finally, axiom (F6) posits that u A A for any stable set A. In the canonical frame, u = π and = σ are the π and σ extensions of the box operator.
Having argued that the full complex algebra of the canonical frame is a canonical extension of the represented implicative modal lattice, the identity of the σ and π extensions of the box operator holds by [13] [Lemma 4.4].
By the above, the proof that the canonical frame is a refined frame (axiomatized in Table 3) is complete. □
It remains to examine the cases where additional axioms are satisfied in the implicative modal lattice.
For the lattice distribution axiom and for the case where the lattice is a Heyting algebra and the respective proofs that the full complex algebra of the canonical frame is (completely) distributive and a (complete) Heyting algebra, respectively, we refer the reader to Section 7 and to [15] [Propositions 4.7 and 4.11].

6.2. Canonicity of the K, D, T, B and S4, S5 Axioms

Proposition 19
(Canonicity of the K-Axiom). The frame axiom (FK) holds in the canonical frame and it is equivalent to the inclusion ( Γ x   { y } ) Γ x (   { y } ) for any filter x and ideal y.
Proof. 
It follows from the definition of the point operators that c x y iff there exist elements a x , b y such that c a b , and then e ( x y ) iff there are elements a x , b y such that e ( a b ) . Since the K-axiom is assumed for the lattice (logic), we obtain that e ( a b ) a b . Since a x and b y , we obtain e x y . By the definition of the canonical relation R , we may conclude that (FK) holds in the canonical frame.
The inclusion in the statement of the current lemma is equivalent to the inclusion ( x y ) x y . □
Proposition 20
(Canonicity of the D-Axiom). The canonical frame for the minimal logic Λ + { φ φ } is a D-frame. In other words, the D-axiom is canonical.
Proof. 
Proving canonicity of the D-axiom is equivalent to proving that the inequality Logics 03 00003 i013 x x holds for any filter x in the canonical frame. Since Logics 03 00003 i013 x = a x x a , it is enough to show that, for any filter x, if a x , then a x . But, the latter is defined by x = a x x a and, since the D-axiom holds in the lattice (logic), it is clear that, if a x , then, since a x and a a , we have a x . Hence, (FD) holds in the canonical frame. □
To prove canonicity of the T and S4 axioms, it suffices by Propositions 13–16 to prove the corresponding point inequations in the intermediate structure, as shown in the following list:
(T◇) φ φ Logics 03 00003 i013 x x ,for all filters x
(S4◇) φ φ Logics 03 00003 i013 x Logics 03 00003 i013Logics 03 00003 i013 x ,for all filters x
(T□) φ φ y y ,for all ideals y
(S4□) φ φ y y ,for all ideals y.
Proposition 21
(Canonicity of the T and S4 Axioms). Let Δ be a subset of the above set of T and S4 axioms and Δ = Λ + Δ be the corresponding axiomatic extension of the minimal implicative modal logic. Then, Δ is canonical.
Proof. 
By Propositions 1–3, we may equivalently work with implicative modal algebras satisfying the corresponding axioms.
Assume that a a holds and let x be any (nonempty) filter. By the definition of Logics 03 00003 i013 x = a x x a (where x b designates the principal filter generated by a lattice element b), e Logics 03 00003 i013 x iff there is some lattice element a x such that a e . But, then, a a e , so e x . This proves the inclusion Logics 03 00003 i013 x x .
Assume that a a and let x be a filter. To prove that Logics 03 00003 i013 x Logics 03 00003 i013Logics 03 00003 i013 x , let e Logics 03 00003 i013 x, so a e for some a x . Then, a Logics 03 00003 i013Logics 03 00003 i013 x and, given a a e , we obtain e Logics 03 00003 i013Logics 03 00003 i013 x .
Assume that a a and let y be an ideal. Recall that y = a y y a , where we use y b to stand for the principal ideal generated by the lattice element b. To prove that y y , let e y , so e a for some a y . By the hypothesis a a and since y is an ideal, we obtain a y and then also e y .
Assume that a a and let y be an ideal. To prove y y , let e y . Then, e a for some a y . Using the definition of the point operator ⊟, we have a y and a y . But, then, we have e a a y , which is an ideal, so e y . □
Proposition 22
(Canonicity of the B-Axioms). The logic Λ = Λ + { φ φ , φ φ } is canonical.
Proof. 
Assume that a b iff a b holds in an implicative modal algebra and let F + be the full complex algebra of its dual frame. We show that, for any filter x and ideal y, the condition x y iff Logics 03 00003 i013 x y , i.e., axiom (FB) holds in the canonical frame.
If e x y , let a y such that e a y . By residuation in the modal lattice, e a , but, since e x , then Logics 03 00003 i013 e Logics 03 00003 i013 x, which is a filter, and hence also a x . But, then, a Logics 03 00003 i013 x y , i.e., Logics 03 00003 i013 x y .
Conversely, if a Logics 03 00003 i013 x y , let e x be such that Logics 03 00003 i013 e a . By residuation, this is equivalent to e a , and since a y , we obtain a y . Since e x , we have a x y , i.e., x y . □
Proposition 23
(Canonicity of Axiom S5). For any filter x, Logics 03 00003 i013 x Logics 03 00003 i013 x and x Logics 03 00003 i013 x . In other words, the frame axiom (FS5) is valid in the canonical frame.
Proof. 
If e Logics 03 00003 i013 x, then there is some element c Logics 03 00003 i013 x such that c e by definition of u = c u x c . Also, for c to be in Logics 03 00003 i013 x = a x x a , there must be an a x such that a c . For such a, we have a c e . But, the lattice satisfies a a , and hence a e . Since a x , a Logics 03 00003 i013 x, and, thereby, also e Logics 03 00003 i013 x.
The argument for x Logics 03 00003 i013 x is similar, and is left to the reader. □
Note that, for a stable set A, if x A , then ⊟ Logics 03 00003 i013 x Logics 03 00003 i013 A by Lemma 4. Then, the argument in Proposition 18 establishes that, for any stable set A of filters, the inclusions 🞜 A 🞜 A and 🞜 A A hold, and this shows that the axioms S5 are canonical.

7. Distributive and Heyting Frames

By a distributive frame, we mean a frame F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) such that its complete lattice of stable sets G ( Z 1 ) is (completely) distributive. Proposition 24 identifies a condition for the frame to be distributive. That the canonical frame of a distributive lattice satisfies the condition in this proposition was proven in [11] [Proposition 5.4, Case 5].
Proposition 24
([15] [Proposition 3.13]). Let F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) be a frame and G ( Z 1 ) be the complete lattice of stable sets. If all sections of the Galois dual relation R of the upper bound relation R (where u R x z iff both x u and z u ) are Galois sets, then G ( Z 1 ) is completely distributive.□
The condition for a frame to be a Heyting frame is that its full complex algebra F + = ( G ( Z 1 ) , , , , , Z 1 , , ) is a (complete) Heyting algebra (with additional structure due to the modal operators). The implication construct ⇒ is residuated with a product operator ⦶ (Proposition 5), which is the closure of the image operator ⨀ generated by the relation R 111 of Definition 6. Therefore, F + is a residuated lattice. Hence, it will be a Heyting algebra if ⦶ is the same as intersection on stable sets. Working out the detail of this observation, we have the following result.
Theorem 5.
Let F = ( s , Z , I , T 1 , ) be a frame. Then, the full complex algebra of the frame is a complete Heyting algebra iff the relation R 111 coincides with the upper bound relation R on the frame. In that case, the implication construct is equivalently defined by x ( A C ) iff z Z 1 ( x z ( z A z C ) ) .
Proof. 
The claims were proven in [15] [Propositions 3.15 and 3.17]. □
That the canonical frame of a Heyting algebra satisfies the condition of the above theorem was proven in [15] [Proposition 4.11].
Remark 9.
When R 111 coincides with the upper bound relation R , then is intersection of stable and, more generally, upper closed sets in the ≤ order. This follows from the fact that U W = { u | x , z ( x U z W u R x z ) } . But, note that need not be an intersection of arbitrary subsets of Z 1 . Note also that, for any increasing subsets (any upsets) U , W , the set U T W is also an upset when R 111 = R . Hence, in the case of a Heyting frame, the residuated pair , T in Logics 03 00003 i005 ( Z 1 ) restricts to a residuated pair in the family (complete lattice) UP ( Z 1 ) of increasing subsets of Z 1 (upper closed subsets in the ⪯-order) and to a residuated pair , in G ( Z 1 ) . The latter is the case because, for stable sets A , C , A C = A C is a stable set, and hence A C = ( A C ) = A C = A C .
Theorem 6.
If the frame F = ( s , Z , I , T 1 , R , ) is a Heyting frame, then the K-axiom is valid in G ( Z 1 ) . Consequently, the minimal intuitionistic modal logic, assuming only the K-axiom, is valid in the class of Heyting frames.
Proof. 
Assume that u ( A C ) . To show that u A C , let z Z 1 be such that u z and z A . To obtain z C , which is equivalent to z R C , let p Z 1 be such that z R p . It suffices to obtain p C . From u z , z R p and Lemma 2, it follows that u R p . Using the hypothesis u ( A C ) , we then have p A C . Furthermore, using the hypothesis z A , we also obtain p A . Given the definition of ⇒ in the Heyting case, A C = { p | z ( p z z A z C ) } , and since p satisfies the premises of the defining implication for A C , we obtain p C as needed. Alternatively, use the fact that p A ( A C ) C . □
By Theorem 6, no need arises in the case of a modal extension of the intuitionistic propositional calculus to consider second-order axioms for frames. Frames for extensions with any of the axioms D, T, B, S4 or S5 can be dealt with roughly as carried out for the distribution-free case, but we shall not dwell on this here.

8. Related Research

To the best of this author’s knowledge, an attempt to present a way to model the analogues of the classical normal modal logic systems (the K system and its extensions) obtained by dropping the distribution axiom from the proof system is new with this article.
It should nevertheless be pointed out that relational semantics for minimal distribution-free modal logic (assuming, at most, the distribution and normality axioms for the box and diamond) have been presented in a number of papers in the literature, in addition to [4] already mentioned in the introductory section, as we briefly review below.
Vakarelov and Orłowska [34] (2003) and Düntsch and Radzikowska [35] (2004) provided relational semantics for modal operators, including modally interpreted negation operators, with an approach based on Urquhart’s lattice representation [36]. Modal and temporal operators in a distribution-free setting were also modeled by this author in [37] (2016), with relational structures based on the lattice representation and duality of [31]. This author and Orłowska revisited the problem in [38] (2019) using sorted frames (polarities) based both on the lattice representation and duality [30] published by this author and Dunn and on its extension [22]. A discrete duality for bounded lattices with modal operators was reported in [39] (2019) and sorted frame and game-theoretic semantics for distribution-free modal logics were also discussed in [40] (2019), both by this author.
Following [13], where canonical extensions for bounded lattices were defined and studied, Gehrke initiated a new relational framework, the generalized Kripke frames approach [9] (2006), which later became generally known as RS-frames (separated and reduced sorted frames), and their relational structures are the frames used by Hartung in his lattice representation [41]. Though the RS-frames modeling approach was only exemplified for the Lambek calculus in [9], whose fusion operator is a normal binary additive (diamond) operator, Gehrke’s [9] set the precedent for subsequent work in modeling distribution-free modal logic in the generalized (RS)-frames approach. The RS-frames literature is extensive. While, in part of this literature [42] (2006), [43] (2020), the authors provide motivation for the RS-semantics applied to distribution-free modal logic, pointing to new possible application areas, the most significant contribution is perhaps the study of canonicity and correspondence in a distribution-free setting [16] (2019). This naturally includes modal logic without distribution, but, as the authors explain, the K-axiom or its two classical equivalents used by Dunn [1] to axiomatize (distributive) positive modal logic (without either negation or implication) cannot be processed by the ALBA algorithm (they are not Sahlqvist). The RS-frames approach also underlies a recent report on game semantics for the modal μ -calculus [44] (2023) and an attempt to prove a van Benthem characterization result for modal logic without distribution [45] (2024). A full generalization of van Benthem’s characterization result to distribution-free logics was presented in [12] (2025).
Urquhat’s [36], Hartung’s [41] and Ploščica’s [46] restructurings of Urquhart’s lattice representation reduce to the Priestley distributive lattice representation [47] when the bounded lattice is distributive. Stone’s [48], with its extension to a representation theory for Boolean algebras with operators by Jónsson and Tarski [6,49], and Priestley’s representations underly, in an essential way, the relational semantics tradition for Boolean or merely distributive modal logics. It was then natural to carry out the same for the above mentioned mere bounded lattice representations. We already referred to the first two and, to complete this brief review, we first mention the work of Craig, Gouveia and Haviar [50] (2015), who introduced TiRS frames, based on Ploščica’s lattice representation, as a new relational framework for distribution-free systems. Ploščica’s representation has also inspired the relational semantics investigated by Holliday [51] (2024), who showed how modal operators can be modeled.
All approaches mentioned above only addressed the problem of modeling at most the minimal system (the fusion of the monomodal systems, assuming only the distribution and normality axioms for the box and monotonicity only for diamond), while a few made contributions in other directions (such as game semantics or applications of distribution-free modal logic to new areas, etc.).
Evidently, there can be as many distinct approaches to the relational semantics of distribution-free systems, and of modal logics in particular, as there are bounded lattice representations (and dualities). A first discussion of existing relations between this author’s approach and the RS-frames approach was presented in [14] (2022), and a comparative study for the construction of canonical extensions (the second duals in lattice representation) was reported in [52] (2014). Lattice representations and dualities (when the extension of representation to duality has been also obtained) have been hitherto unrelated: a first review was given in [53] and a comparative study was presented only too recently in [54] (2025). It would be interesting to see the latter study extended to the case of dualities for normal lattice expansions as well, as this would be of more interest in the context of relational semantics for distribution-free logics, modal or otherwise.

Funding

This research received no external funding.

Data Availability Statement

Data sharing is not applicable to this article as datasets were neither generated nor analyzed.

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares that he has no conflicts of interest.

References

  1. Dunn, J.M. Positive Modal Logic. Stud. Log. 1995, 55, 301–317. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Gehrke, M.; Nagahashi, H.; Venema, Y. A Sahlqvist theorem for distributive modal logic. Ann. Pure Appl. Log. 2005, 131, 65–102. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Celani, S.; Jansana, R. A New Semantics for Positive Modal Logic. Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 1997, 38, 1–18. [Google Scholar]
  4. Bezhanishvili, N.; Dmitrieva, A.; de Groot, J.; Moraschini, T. Positive modal logic beyond distributivity. Ann. Pure Appl. Log. 2024, 175, 103–374. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  5. Hofmann, K.H.; Michael Mislove, A.S. The Pontryagin Duality of Compact 0-Dimensional Semilattices and Its Applications; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1974. [Google Scholar]
  6. Jónsson, B.; Tarski, A. Boolean Algebras with Operators I. Am. J. Math. 1951, 73, 891–939. [Google Scholar]
  7. Hartonas, C. Duality for Normal Lattice Expansions and Sorted Residuated Frames with Relations. Algebra Universalis 2023, 84, 5. Available online: https://rdcu.be/c4qec (accessed on 15 December 2024).
  8. Suzuki, T. On Polarity Frames: Applications to Substructural and Lattice-Based Logics. In Advances in Modal Logic; Goré, R., Kooi, B., Kurucz, A., Eds.; CSLI Publications: Stanford, CA, USA, 2014; Volume 10, pp. 533–552. [Google Scholar]
  9. Gehrke, M. Generalized Kripke Frames. Stud. Log. 2006, 84, 241–275. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Chernilovskaya, A.; Gehrke, M.; van Rooijen, L. Generalised Kripke semantics for the Lambek-Grishin calculus. Log. J. IGPL 2012, 20, 1110–1132. [Google Scholar]
  11. Hartonas, C. Choice-free Dualities for Lattice Expansions: Application to Logics with a Negation Operator. Stud. Log. 2024. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Hartonas, C. A Van Benthem Characterization Result for Distribution-Free Logics. Logics 2025, 3, 1. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  13. Gehrke, M.; Harding, J. Bounded Lattice Expansions. J. Algebra 2001, 238, 345–371. [Google Scholar]
  14. Hartonas, C. Reconcilliation of Approaches to the Semantics of Logics without Distribution. In Relevance Logics and Other Tools for Reasoning: Essays in Honor of J. Michael Dunn; Bimbó, K., Ed.; Number 46 in Tributes; College Publications: Rickmansworth, UK, 2022; pp. 215–236. [Google Scholar]
  15. Hartonas, C. Choice-free topological duality for Implicative Lattices and Heyting Algebras. Algebra Universalis 2023, 85, 3. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  16. Conradie, W.; Palmigiano, A. Algorithmic correspondence and canonicity for non-distributive logics. Ann. Pure Appl. Log. 2019, 170, 923–974. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  17. Goldblatt, R. Morphisms and Duality for Polarities and Lattices with Operators. FLAP 2020, 7, 1017–1070. [Google Scholar]
  18. Almeida, A. Canonical Extensions and Relational Representations of Lattices with Negation. Stud Log. 2009, 91, 171–199. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  19. Coumans, D.; Gehrke, M.; van Rooijen, L. Relational semantics for full linear logic. J. Appl. Log. 2014, 12, 50–66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Hartonas, C. Modal translation of substructural logics. J. Appl. Non-Class. Logics 2020, 30, 16–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  21. Gehrke, M.; Jónsson, B. Bounded distributive lattice expansions. Math. Scand. 2004, 94, 13–45. [Google Scholar]
  22. Hartonas, C. Stone Duality for Lattice Expansions. Log. J. IGPL 2018, 26, 475–504. [Google Scholar]
  23. Hartonas, C. Order-Dual Relational Semantics for Non-Distributive Propositional Logics. Log. J. IGPL 2017, 25, 145–182. [Google Scholar]
  24. Suzuki, T. Morphisms on Bi-approximation Semantics. In Proceedings of the Advances in Modal Logic 9, Papers from the Nineth Conference on “Advances in Modal Logic”, Copenhagen, Denmark, 22–25 August 2012; pp. 494–515. [Google Scholar]
  25. Anderson, A.R.; Belnap, N.D.; Dunn, J.M. Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1992; Volume II. [Google Scholar]
  26. Dunn, M.; Restall, G. Relevance Logic. In Handbook of Philosophical Logic; Gabbay, D., Guenthner, F., Eds.; Kluwer Academic Publishers: Dordrecht, The Netherlands; New York, NY, USA; London, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
  27. Davey, B.A.; Priestley, H.A. Introduction to Lattices and Order, 2nd ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  28. Gehrke, M.; Harding, J.; Venema, Y. MacNeille completions and canonical extensions. Trans. Am. Math. Soc. 2006, 358, 573–590. [Google Scholar]
  29. Hartonas, C.; Dunn, J.M. Duality Theorems for Partial Orders, Semilattices, Galois Connections and Lattices; Technical Report IULG-93-26; Indiana University Logic Group: Bloomington, IN, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
  30. Hartonas, C.; Dunn, J.M. Stone Duality for Lattices. Algebra Universalis 1997, 37, 391–401. [Google Scholar]
  31. Hartonas, C. Duality for Lattice-Ordered Algebras and for Normal Algebraizable Logics. Stud. Log. 1997, 58, 403–450. [Google Scholar]
  32. Moshier, M.A.; Jipsen, P. Topological duality and lattice expansions, I: A topological construction of canonical extensions. Algebra Universalis 2014, 71, 109–126. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  33. Moshier, M.A.; Jipsen, P. Topological duality and lattice expansions, II: Lattice expansions with quasioperators. Algebra Universalis 2014, 71, 221–234. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  34. Orlowska, E.; Vakarelov, D. Lattice-based modal algebras and modal logics. In Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Proceedings of the Twelfth International Congress, Oviedo, Spain, 7–13 August 2003; Hájek, P., Valdés-Villanueva, L., Westerståhl, D., Eds.; King’s College Publications: London, UK, 2005; pp. 147–170. [Google Scholar]
  35. Düntsch, I.; Orlowska, E.; Radzikowska, A.M.; Vakarelov, D. Relational representation theorems for some lattice-based structures. J. Relational Methods Comput. Sci. JORMICS 2004, 1, 132–160. [Google Scholar]
  36. Urquhart, A. A Topological Representation of Lattices. Algebra Universalis 1978, 8, 45–58. [Google Scholar]
  37. Hartonas, C. Modal and Temporal Extensions of Non-Distributive Propositional Logics. Log. J. IGPL 2016, 24, 156–185. [Google Scholar]
  38. Hartonas, C.; Orłowska, E. Representation of Lattices with Modal Operators in Two-Sorted Frames. Fundam. Inform. 2019, 166, 29–56. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  39. Hartonas, C. Discrete duality for lattices with modal operators. J. Log. Comput. 2019, 29, 71–89. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  40. Hartonas, C. Game-theoretic semantics for non-distributive logics. Log. J. IGPL 2019, 27, 718–742. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  41. Hartung, G. A topological representation for lattices. Algebra Universalis 1992, 29, 273–299. [Google Scholar]
  42. Conradie, W.; Frittella, S.; Palmigiano, A.; Piazzai, M.; Tzimoulis, A.; Wijnberg, N. Categories: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Two Sorts. In Proceedings of the Logic, Language, Information, and Computation—23rd International Workshop, WoLLIC 2016, Puebla, Mexico, 16–19 August 2016; Proceedings. 2016; pp. 145–164. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  43. Conradie, W.; Palmigiano, A.; Robinson, C.; Wijnberg, N. Non-distributive logics: From semantics to meaning. arXiv 2020, arXiv:2002.04257. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  44. Ding, Y.; Manoorkar, K.; Panettiere, M.; Tzimoulis, A.; Wang, R. Game semantics for lattice-based modal mu-calculus. arXiv 2023, arXiv:2310.13944. [Google Scholar]
  45. Ding, Y.; Manoorkar, K.; Panettiere, M.; Wang, R. Toward the van Benthem Characterization Theorem for Non-Distributive Modal Logic. arXiv 2024, arXiv:2404.05574. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  46. Ploščica, M. A natural representation of bounded lattices. Tatra Mt. Math. Publ. 1995, 5, 75–88. [Google Scholar]
  47. Priestley, H. Representation of Distributive Lattices by means of Ordered Stone Spaces. Bull. Lond. Math. Soc. 1970, 2, 186–190. [Google Scholar]
  48. Stone, M.H. The Representation of Boolean Algebras. Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 1938, 44, 807–816. [Google Scholar]
  49. Jónsson, B.; Tarski, A. Boolean Algebras with Operators II. Am. J. Math. 1952, 74, 8127–8162. [Google Scholar]
  50. Craig, A.; Gouveia, M.J.; Haviar, M. TiRS graphs and TiRS frames: A new setting for duals of canonical extensions. Algerba Universalis 2015, 74, 123–138. [Google Scholar]
  51. Holliday, W.H. Modal logic, fundamentally. arXiv 2024, arXiv:2403.14043. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  52. Craig, A.; Haviar, M. Reconciliation of approaches to the construction of canonical extensions of bounded lattices. Math. Slovaka 2014, 64, 1335–1356. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  53. Craig, A. Representations and dualities for bounded lattices. Acta Univ. Matthiae Belii Ser. Math. 2022, 30, 1–35. [Google Scholar]
  54. Bezhanishvili, G.; Carai, L.; Morandi, P. Duality Theory for Bounded Lattices: A Comparative Study. arXiv 2025, arXiv:2502.21307. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Table 1. Proof system for the minimal logic Λ τ .
Table 1. Proof system for the minimal logic Λ τ .
PLL axioms and rules
φ φ φ ϑ φ ψ ϑ ψ ϑ φ ψ ϑ φ ψ φ ϑ φ ψ ϑ φ ψ ψ ϑ φ ϑ (Cut)
φ φ ϑ φ ϑ φ ψ ϑ ψ ϑ φ ψ φ ϑ ψ ϑ φ ψ ϑ
Substitution rule φ ( p ) ψ ( p ) φ [ ϑ / p ] ψ [ ϑ / p ]
Additional axioms/rules for Λ τ
For each j J and where δ j = ( j 1 , , j k , , j n ( j ) ; j n ( j ) + 1 ) is the distribution type of f j
• Monotonicity/Antitonicity rules
ψ ϑ f j ( φ [ ψ ] k ) f j ( φ [ ϑ ] k ) if j k = j n ( j ) + 1 ψ ϑ f j ( φ [ ϑ ] k ) f j ( φ [ ψ ] k ) if j k j n ( j ) + 1
• Distribution axioms
f j ( φ [ ψ χ ] k ) f j ( φ [ ψ ] k ) f j ( φ [ χ ] k )     if j k = 1 = j n ( j ) + 1
f j ( φ [ ψ ] k ) f j ( φ [ χ ] k ) f j ( φ [ ψ χ ] k )     if j k = = j n ( j ) + 1
• Co-Distribution axioms
f j ( φ [ ψ χ ] k ) f j ( φ [ ψ ] k ) f j ( φ [ χ ] k )     if j k = 1 = j n ( j ) + 1
f j ( φ [ ψ ] k ) f j ( φ [ χ ] k ) f j ( φ [ ψ χ ] k )     if j k = 1 = j n ( j ) + 1
• Normality axioms
f j ( φ [ ] k ) if j k = 1 = j n ( j ) + 1
f j ( φ [ ] k ) if j k = = j n ( j ) + 1
f j ( φ [ ] k ) if j k = 1 = j n ( j ) + 1
f j ( φ [ ] k ) if j k = 1 = j n ( j ) + 1
Table 2. (Co)satisfaction relations.
Table 2. (Co)satisfaction relations.
x p i iff x V 1 ( p i )
x Logics 03 00003 i006iff x = x
y Logics 03 00003 i007iff y = y
x φ ψ iff x φ and x ψ
y φ ψ iff y φ and y ψ
y Logics 03 00003 i002 φ iff v Z ( y R v v φ )
x φ iff z Z 1 ( x R z z φ )
x φ Logics 03 00003 i003 ψ iff u Z 1 y Z ( u φ y ψ x T u y )
iff u , z Z 1 ( u φ z R 111 u x z ψ )
Table 3. Axiomatization of refined frames F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) .
Table 3. Axiomatization of refined frames F = ( s , Z , I , ( R j ) j J , σ ) .
( R j { R , R 11 , T 1 } )
(F1)The frame is separated.
(F2)Every frame relation R j is increasing in the first and decreasing in every other argument place.
(F3)For every tuple p of the proper sort, R j p is a closed element Γ ( j ^ ( p ) ) .
(F4)Every frame relation R j is smooth.
(F5)For each x Z 1 , the section S 11 x of the relation defined by z S 11 x iff z R Γ x is a closed element of G ( Z 1 ) .
(F6)(Restricted join-distributivity of ) For all stable sets A, x A Γ x x A Γ x .
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Hartonas, C. Distribution-Free Normal Modal Logics. Logics 2025, 3, 3. https://doi.org/10.3390/logics3020003

AMA Style

Hartonas C. Distribution-Free Normal Modal Logics. Logics. 2025; 3(2):3. https://doi.org/10.3390/logics3020003

Chicago/Turabian Style

Hartonas, Chrysafis. 2025. "Distribution-Free Normal Modal Logics" Logics 3, no. 2: 3. https://doi.org/10.3390/logics3020003

APA Style

Hartonas, C. (2025). Distribution-Free Normal Modal Logics. Logics, 3(2), 3. https://doi.org/10.3390/logics3020003

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop