2.1. System of Axioms of Hilbert-P Geometry and Its Consequences
Let us start from summarizing Hilbert’s system of axioms. Hilbert’s axioms of Euclidean geometry include the following:
- (i)
Group I: Axioms of Incidence. These axioms describe how points, lines, and planes relate.
I.1: For every two distinct points, there exists a line that contains both of them.
I.2: A line contains at least two points.
I.3: There exist at least three non-collinear points (not all on the same line).
I.4: For any three points not on a line, there is a plane that contains them.
I.5: Every plane contains at least three non-collinear points.
I.6: If two points of a line lie in a plane, the entire line lies in the plane.
I.7: If two planes intersect, their intersection is a line.
I.8: There exist at least four points not lying in the same plane.
- (ii)
Group II: Axioms of Order (“betweenness”). These axioms define the concept of one point lying between two others.
II.1: If point B lies between A and C, then all three points are distinct and lie on the same line.
II.2: For any two points A and C, there exists a point B on the line AC such that C lies between A and B.
II.3: Of any three points on a line, exactly one lies between the other two.
II.4: Given three points on a line, we can name them A, B, C such that B is between A and C.
II.5 (Pasch’s Axiom): If a line entering a triangle from one side intersects one side, then it must also intersect another side.
- (iii)
Group III: Axioms of Congruence. These axioms deal with the equality of segments and angles.
III.1: Given a segment AB and a ray CD, there is a unique point E on that ray such that segment AB = CE.
III.2: Congruence is symmetric and transitive.
III.3: If two segments are congruent to the same segment, they are congruent to each other.
III.4: Given two angles, there is a congruent copy of one angle placed at a given ray.
III.5: (Side–Angle–Side): If in two triangles, two sides and the included angle are congruent, then the triangles are congruent.
- (iv)
Group IV: Axiom of Parallels
This is Hilbert’s version of Euclid’s fifth postulate.
- (v)
Group V: Axioms of Continuity. These axioms ensure the completeness of the geometric space (similar to real numbers being complete).
V.1 (Axiom of Archimedes): There is no infinitely small or infinitely large length; segments can be added finitely to surpass any given segment.
V.2 (Axiom of Line Completeness/Dedekind Cut Axiom): If a line is divided into two classes such that every point of the first lies to the left of every point of the second, then there exists a unique point separating the two classes.
We adopt the aforementioned Hilbert system of axioms, with one, however, essential exception. We replace Euclid’s fifth postulate (Playfair’s axiom) with its probabilistic version:
Probabilistic Parallel Axiom. Given a line l and a point
, there is exactly one line through A with probability P, where .
Or, as formally written,
for any point A and line l , the event
occurs with probability .
Let us supply the exact meaning to the probability
P. It is understood as a frequency of prescribed events (to be unique parallel to line
l) in a statistical ensemble of lines passing through a fixed point
A. Let
be a set of lines passing
A. We equip
with a natural probability measure
, which is uniform if Γ(
A) is finite, and it is an angular measure if
continuous. Now, the probabilistic statement of the Playfair axiom is formulated as follows: The probability that, for a randomly chosen line
,
m is the unique line through
A parallel to some external line
l (implicitly defined by the slope/direction of
m) equals
P.
where
is a normalized, non-negative, additive measure on the ensemble of lines through
A.
If we accept the probabilistic version of the Playfair axiom, the statement
S of the geometry
G also becomes probabilistic. This introduces a modal probabilistic operator
, where
S is a logical statement and
P its probability. This yields Equation (2):
The probability
P in Hilbert–
P–Geometry is defined as follows. Let
S be the set of elementary geometrical statements constructed from the primitives (points, lines, planes) using the usual logical operations. A probability assignment is a function:
such that for any statement
S,
P(
S) expresses the likelihood that
S holds in a given realization of the geometry
G(
S). The basic objects (primitives, using the Hilbert language) of geometry (points, lines, and planes) remain undefined, in the Hilbertian sense; axioms themselves define the primitives. Probability, in turn, is not a geometric object, but a valuation on statements, analogous to generalized truth values in probabilistic or fuzzy logic [
20,
21,
22,
23]. The introduced probability
fulfils the usual demands to probability, namely,
- (i)
Normalization , where T is a tautological statement (always true).
- (ii)
Non-negativity; namely, for every statement S, .
- (iii)
Additivity: if
and
are mutually exclusive statements,
- (iv)
Monotonicity, i.e., if
, then .
Probability P(S) within the suggested approach is not a primitive geometrical object (using the Hilbert wording for undefined terms), but a valuation on statements, extending the binary truth values of classical geometry into the unit interval .
Now, let us rigorously re-formulate the Hilbert-P system of axioms. Let denote Hilbert’s axiom system without the fifth postulate (we keep Groups I–III and V untouched and omit Group IV). Thus, is the common scaffold of incidence, order, congruence, betweenness, and continuity axioms. A probabilistic geometric model is defined as follows:
- (i)
Consider the class of models of . A model of denoted means a mathematical structure (a set of points and lines, with relations like incidence, betweenness, congruence, etc.) that satisfies all those axioms.
- (ii)
Assign a probability measure μ to the space of models . Although only Playfair’s axiom is taken as probabilistic, the statements of geometries labeled G(S) become probabilistic (with the exception of the axioms , which remain deterministic). For any geometric statement S (in the language of Hilbert’s geometry), we define its probability of truth P(S) (see Equations (2) and (3)):
where
M is one possible geometry (a mathematical structure) built on the primitives (points, lines, incidence, betweenness, congruence, etc.), i.e.,
the Euclidean plane (all Hilbert axioms belonging to
hold), including the fifth Playfair postulate;
is the hyperbolic geometry occurring on the hyperbolic plane, i.e., two-dimensional geometric surface with constant negative curvature (Groups I–III and V hold, but the fifth postulate does not); and
is the sphere with great circles (elliptic geometry). It should be emphasized that Hilbert axioms from Groups I–III and V are left deterministic, and their probability
P equals unity. Indeed, the probability of truth for each deterministic Hilbert axiom in
equals unity, since every model in
satisfies them. The probabilistic geometry
G(S) is defined over the entire class of models
, equipped with a probability measure
. Now, Hilbert-
P-Geometry is a pair
is the probability measure on
. Rigorously speaking, we suggest the probabilistic interpretation of the classical Hilbert system of axioms.
This approach creates a hybrid geometric model, blending elements of Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometry, governed by a random choice at each parallel construction event.
It can easily be seen that well-known geometries appear as the particular cases of the Hilbert–P probabilistic geometry, namely,
- (i)
corresponds to the standard Euclidean geometry : Playfair’s axiom holds always. All classical theorems of the Euclidian geometry remain valid (e.g., triangle angle sum remains valid).
- (ii)
corresponds to the elliptic-like geometry . No parallels through external points (like great circles on a sphere). holds.
- (iii)
corresponds to hyperbolic-like geometry , with the interpretation that multiple parallels are allowed. In hyperbolic geometry, through a point not on a line, there are infinitely many lines that do not intersect the given line—i.e., infinitely many parallels. In the suggested probabilistic axiom, only one parallel with probability P is possible, not multiple. So, to properly correspond to hyperbolic geometry, we interpret
- (iv)
corresponds to the introduced probabilistic Hilbert geometry. Parallel constructions in this case are Bernoulli trials. Geometric consequences become probabilistic statements. Theorems take the following form: with probability , there exist n successive parallels to a given line.
Let and be two lines constructed through a sequence of k probabilistic parallel choices. Then, the probability they are parallel is . Now, the existence of unique parallels is not guaranteed. Consider a line l and a point : there is a line through A with probability P, where ; otherwise, either none or many exist. If the parallel fails (with probability ), we may enter a non-Euclidean branch.
Let us exemplify the suggested approach and address the angle sum
S of a triangle, which becomes random within the introduced probabilistic geometry. With probability
P, the triangle is Euclidean and
with probability
the triangle may be non-Euclidean (say hyperbolic), and then
(if hyperbolic-like behavior dominates). This gives rise to a probabilistic angle sum, with expected value
:
What is the exact meaning of It supplies within the suggested approach the average value of the angle sum S of a triangle, over many repeated constructions, where each construction involves drawing parallels with probability . In the suggested Hilbert-P-probabilistic geometry, since parallelism is probabilistic, the outcome of a triangle’s angle sum is not deterministic. It depends on whether the “parallel step” succeeded. With probability , and with probability Thus, given by Equation (6) is the weighted average of these two possible outcomes. Hence, the following theorem is demonstrated, based on the Hilbert-P system of axioms:
Theorem 1 (Expected angle sum of a triangle).
The expected angle sum of a triangle is given by .
A number of theorems of the Hilbert-P geometry are of the probabilistic nature. Let us list some of these theorems.
Theorem 2 (Probability of parallel side in triangle).
Given a triangle and a line drawn from a vertex parallel to the opposite side, the event that this line is actually parallel occurs with probability P. Otherwise, the line may intersect the side or diverge.
Formal statement:
BC is a triangle, formed by points
A,
B,
C and line
BC. Then,
Theorem 3. Non-deterministic Midpoint Theorem.
In triangle ABC, let M and N be midpoints of sides AB and AC, respectively. Then, line MN is parallel to BC with probability P, and not parallel with probability
Corollary 1. The segment MN has length with probability P.
Theorem 4 (Stochastic behavior of parallelograms, parallelogram closure).
If a quadrilateral has opposite sides built using “parallel” constructions, it closes into a parallelogram with probability , since both pairs must independently satisfy the parallel condition.
Theorem 5 (Parallelism is not transitive).
If with probability , and with probability , then with a probability at most assuming the independence of events.
Let us exemplify the suggested approach with the following examples.
Example 1. Consider line l and point A at the distance x from l, as depicted in Figure 1. Assume that the probability a constructed line through a point at perpendicular distance x from a given line is the unique parallel is given by Equation (9): It is easy to demonstrate that the parametrized density of the probability measure
is given by
;
. The properties of the probability distribution are listed as follows:
; i.e.,
far away, the probability of producing a parallel tends to 1. Far away from the line l, the Euclidean situation is almost recovered. The other limiting case is . If
is assumed,
is true. The probability density
fulfills the normalization demands, namely, Consider a 1D grid of the equally spaced points
, where the spacing
. The expected number of successful parallels is given by Equation (11):using the geometric series for
. Let us calculate the normalized continuous-density limit. If candidate points are dense over an interval
, we replace sums by integrals: As
, the average success fraction tends to 1, which is intuitively clear. Indeed, far-away points almost surely give parallels.
Nearby points “see” the line as slightly “fuzzy” and fail to construct a clean parallel, but faraway points almost surely obtain the Euclidean parallel. This somewhat mimics optical parallax: if you are close to a mirror, reflected rays are distorted, while at infinity, the geometry stabilizes.
Example 2. Consider the line l and point A at the fixed distance from the line. Axis x is perpendicular to line l. Line and point A fix the plane . We introduce the Euclid fifth postulate of geometry re-formulated as follows: the density of the probability of building a single line via fixed point A parallel to the given line l is given by , where is the delta-function of Dirack. Thus, it is possible to build the parallel line only via point A. The probability of building the straight line parallel to l via points belonging to other than A is zero. Rigorously speaking, we replace the Playfair axiom with the following statement:
Fix a point A. Let x denote the perpendicular distance from A to the reference line l. The probability that a construction procedure produces exactly one line through A parallel to l is given by the generalized density
. The logical-symbolic formulation appears as follows:where
is the fixed perpendicular distance
from l. For every other point B not on l,
, we haveso, if
, then
and
; if
,
, and hence,
.
It is possible to parameterize lines through a fixed point A by their angle
. There is a unique
for which the line is parallel to l. Then, one may model the probability density on
i.e., the random construction always chooses the specific direction . This is equivalent (for a fixed A) to deterministic uniqueness of the parallel. However, this is not the usual Euclidean/Playfair postulate for all points; it singles out a locus of points (distance
) that behave classically, while all other points behave “non-Euclidean” (no parallels).
Now, consider the problem already addressed in Example 1. Take a lattice of horizontal rows at
, starting from the line l, spacing
. Let
for some integer m. Under the strict delta axiom, only the row
produces parallels (each lattice point there yields one parallel with probability 1). So, the expected number of parallels per column equals unity (from the one special row) and 0 elsewhere.
Example 3. Now, we replace the Playfair axiom with the following statement:
Consider the line l and a point A at the distance
from the line. Line and point A fix the plane
. Axis x is perpendicular to line l. Now, the density of the probability of building a single line via any point A parallel to the given line l is given by
, where
is the delta-function of Dirack. Thus, it is possible to build the parallel line via any point A. We replace the Playfair axiom with the following statement:
The probability of building exactly one line m through any point A parallel to l is given by the generalized density
for any point belonging to
This δ-formulation simply reproduces Euclidean geometry, because for each chosen point, the δ-function peaks at its own
, ensuring one parallel, and may be summarized as follows: Example 4. Now, we replace the Dirack function from the previous example with the probability density , which concentrates at when : Clearly,
, and as
,
. Now, consider the example already addressed in Example 1. Take a lattice of horizontal rows at
, starting from the line l, spacing
. Let
for some integer m; the expected number of parallels per column is 2.4. Probabilistic Geometry Adopting the Fuzzy Version of the First Axiom of the Hilbert Geometry
Additional versions of the probabilistic geometry are possible. The first axiom of the Hilbert geometry states the following: for every two distinct points, there exists a line that contains both of them.
We modify the first axiom as follows: For every two distinct points, there exists with probability a line that contains both of them. This creates a new version of stochastic/randomized/probabilistic geometry. Under this probabilistic axiom, for two points A and B, a line may or may not exist through them. The existence of such a line is not deterministic, but follows a pre-fixed probability distribution. The introduced axiom interferes with other axioms of the Hilbert geometry. Consider Axiom II.1: If point B lies between A and C, then all three points are distinct and lie on the same line. Betweenness requires a line between the points. If no line exists between A and C (or others), betweenness is undefined. Thus, the entire system of Hilbert axioms should be changed. Thus, we supply only a very preliminary sketch of this version of the probabilistic geometry. For example, the theorem establishing the probability of triangle existence appears now as follows:
Theorem 6. Probability of Triangle Existence.
Given three non-collinear points
A,
B,
C, the probability of all three pairwise connecting lines
AB,
BC, CA is
It should be emphasized that the probabilistic version of the first Hilbert axiom destroys the entire version of the Hilbert/Euclidian geometry, due to the fact that it interferes with other axioms. In classical Euclidian/Hilbert geometry, any two points determine a unique line. Now, for a pair
A,
B, the probability that there is a line through both is
P. Thus, there may exist pairs of points not connected by a line, i.e., geometrically disconnected pairs. Hence, collinearity becomes probabilistic. Congruence axioms (Group III,
Section 2.1) fail. If segment
AB does not exist, then its congruence relations are undefined. The probabilistic modification of Axiom I.1 interacts with any version of the parallel postulate. Even if the parallel postulate holds, lines connecting points may not exist. The concept of parallelism now has a domain of definition: only among point–line pairs where both exist. Thus, this version of a probabilistic system of axioms touches the entire axiomatic system, it reflects a randomized or discrete space, where geometry may fail locally due to missing connections, and it resembles percolation models in statistical physics: some connections exist, and others do not. When
it recovers classical Euclidean geometry, and when, in turn,
all space is disconnected, namely, no lines exist. We conclude that the probabilistic version of the first axiom of the Euclid/Hilbert axiomatic system entails deep changes in the entire structure of geometry due to the fact that this version interferes with other axioms. The situation is quite different when we change the Axiom of Archimedes (Axiom V.1, see
Section 2.1).
2.5. Geometry Emerging from the Probabilistic Version of the Axiom of Archimedes
The situation is quite different when the continuity axioms (Group V) are adopted in their probabilistic version. Hilbert introduced continuity axioms (implying Dedekind completeness or Archimedean properties, see
Section 2.1, Group V). These axioms are independent of incidence, order, and congruence. Modifying or removing them leads to non-Archimedean or discrete geometries. Thus, they can be changed independently. Recall the Axiom of Archimedes as it appears in Book V of Euclid’s Elements as Definition 4:
Given any two segments AB and CD, there exists a positive integer n, such that when laying off the segment CD consecutively n times along a ray starting at A, the total length exceeds the length of AB.
The Axiom of Archimedes states that there is no infinitely long segment: even a tiny length can add up to pass any large segment with enough repetitions. There is also no infinitely small segment: if a segment were truly “infinitely small”, no matter how many times you stacked it, it would never pass a finite segment—which contradicts the axiom.
Now, we introduce the following probabilistic version of the Axiom of Archimedes:
Given any two segments AB and CD, there exists with a probability a positive integer n such that when laying off the segment CD consecutively n times along a ray starting at A, the total length exceeds the length of AB. What do we have in extremal cases?
Let us start from This is the standard Archimedean case, just expressed probabilistically; namely, with certainty, we can lay off CD repeatedly to surpass AB.
The geometry behaves like standard Euclidean geometry; namely,
- (i)
No infinitesimal segments exist.
- (ii)
Segment lengths can be compared meaningfully.
- (iii)
Triangle inequality and other classical theorems still hold.
- (iv)
The real number system underlies the segment-length arithmetic.
The second extremal case corresponds to . This is the non-Archimedean case. There is zero probability that any finite number of consecutive CD segments laid from A will ever surpass AB. In this case,
- (i)
CD is infinitesimal compared to AB.
- (ii)
No finite sum n CD ever comes close to AB.
- (iii)
Segment length comparison fails: the field of segment lengths is now non-Archimedean. The geometry becomes non-Euclidean in a fundamental way.
- (iv)
Triangle inequality may break down or become trivial.
- (v)
This setting resembles non-standard analysis or hyperreal geometries, where infinitesimals exist.
Of course, we supplied only a brief sketch of probabilistic, non-Archimedean geometry to be developed in the future investigations. However, it should be emphasized that modification of the Archimedean axiom does not touch other groups of the Euclid/Hilbert geometry.