Transcendence in Jean-Luc Marion: Negotiating Theology and Phenomenology
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. “The Possible and Revelation”
Thus, Marion has set for himself the problem which must be solved if phenomenology is to become an appropriate method for religion in this highest form, that is, for revelation.Revelation escapes being disqualified by metaphysics when it limits itself strictly to what admits of reason (Kant) or identifies itself simply with the work of the concept (Hegel). In both cases, it must renounce its specificity: announcing an event, explicating a word that surpasses the conditions of the possibility of experience and submitting to the requirements of the principle of reason.(Ibid., p. 3)
What philosophy of religion tends to close, phenomenology of religion could open. Phenomenology offers a method not only to ontology (Heidegger), but to any region of phenomena not directly visible and hence immediately invisible—hence exceedingly to religion inasmuch as it concerns revelation. In short, phenomenology would be the method par excellence for the manifestation of the invisible through the phenomena that indicate it—hence also the method for theology.
For phenomenology to remain open to revelation itself, it must be released from the constituting powers of the I. A very similar argument is made with respect to the concept of the horizon. Here, Marion’s definition of transcendence once again guides his argument. If one assumes that the most expansive opening of the horizon is only that of Being (Heidegger), one has betrayed the possibility of revelation in phenomenology, since transcendence here requires the transcendence of Being, as an a priori delineation of the conditions of possibility for phenomena: “Container [Écrin] of any being, Being plays, in the case of God, the function of a screen [écran]. It precedes the very initiative of revealing, it fixes the frame of revelation, and it imposes the conditions of reception on the revealed gift” (Marion 2008, p. 11). As long as the transcendental subject and the horizon function in this way, “Phenomenology cannot give its status to theology, because the conditions of manifestation contradict or at least are different from the free possibility of revelation”.5The phenomenological method here is applied to theology only by reducing the revealed to the lived experience of the revealed, hence obscuring the revealed revealing itself. The phenomenological reduction provokes demythologization, and sola fides reduces revelatory transcendence to real immanence in consciousness. Although it believes, consciousness does not reach any transcendent (thus revealed) object but is nourished by the immanent lived experience of its solitary faith.(Ibid., p. 9)
3. Subordinated to Transcendence
…Marion’s entire oeuvre may be seen as being directed towards the realisation of such a task, namely, the laborious construction work of developing new conceptual tools and opening a novel imaginative space for the phenomenological analysis of the par excellence phenomenon: revelation in general and Christian revelation in particular…To include revelation in the phenomenal field, he must modify earlier conceptions concerning the nature of phenomena, phenomenality and selfhood and his innovative (and by now well-known) notions of ‘saturated phenomena’, the ‘adonne’ (as self), ‘paradox’ and ‘counter-experience’ all serve the purpose of expanding the field of phenomenality and of redefining the scope of the possible.13
4. Transcendence and Theology
Whether there are other explanations for the possibility of Marion’s phenomenology of givenness being able to account for both theological and other phenomena, it is at least due to Marion’s own transposition of his phenomenological innovations from the theological to a larger field of phenomena.14 Marion’s phenomenology demonstrates, following “The Possible and Revelation” as discussed above, in Being Given and beyond, the universalization of the phenomenon of revelation in the mode of transcendence to a great deal of other phenomena, all belonging to Marion’s classification of the saturated phenomenon.15 As Kosky says, this expansion has produced a great deal of debate among Marion’s interpreters as to the status of theology in his phenomenology, and on fewer occasions, an identification of Marion’s specific notion of transcendence as the primary conduit for an illegitimate contamination between the disciplines (Kosky 2004, pp. 641–43).…Marion said in response to my oral presentation of this paper that givenness first appeared to him in the theological realm, particularly the realm of liturgical life, but that it was then discovered in other regions…
Marion goes on to say how decisive Balthasar’s The Glory of the Cross was for his early theological, and arguably, philosophical development. In agreement with Fritz, Marion’s development never departs from this critical insight which he seems to acquire from Balthasar—that revelation discloses itself from itself with no conditions of possibility apart from its own (Fritz 2012). Though it is agreed with Caputo that Marion decides in favor of a certain type of theological construal of God as divine revelation in his phenomenology, Caputo locates his suspicion in the privilege Marion establishes for givenness, not transcendence, and his argument is about the (ultimate) stakes in Marion’s phenomenology, but he does not identify givenness as unambiguously theological, acknowledging the validity of the saturated phenomenon and its corollaries in the work of other philosophers.19 Claims such as this, articulated as suspicions, generally locate a theological element in Marion’s phenomenology, but fail to demonstrate a more pervasive relation of such elements to his phenomenology. Marion’s preference for a noncorrelational theology is not primarily located in givenness, but in his negotiation of transcendence and in the preeminent position it occupies in relation to his other phenomenological concepts. It is also exemplified in the relation which revelation, as transcendence bears to his other phenomenological innovations—establishing revelation as unique (alterity of kind) and unilateral (asymmetry of power).Should Christian theology rely on a metaphysical fore-understanding, on logical conditions of possibility or impossibility? The transcendental Thomist, whose supreme heir Rahner remains, presupposes that there is in some way continuity between metaphysics, the question of being, even the transcendental subject, that is to say, the conditions of possibility for religious experience, on the one hand, and, on the other hand, Christ or God. In other words, the conditions of experience finally define Revelation itself. Balthasar’s argument, to the contrary, states that Revelation has no conditions of possibility except itself. That is why he begins with the doctrine of the figure (Gestalt) of Revelation, which, according to him, provides its own norms. This intuition obviously agrees with Barth’s starting point. God reveals himself that means the self-manifestation of God from himself and according to his own rules. Balthasar is obviously right.
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Although “revelation” is not capitalized throughout this article, it is acknowledged that what Marion very likely has in view when speaking of revelation is the disclosure of the Christian God. In Being Given Marion does distinguish between different types of saturated phenomena of revelation, reserving the final and fifth, also the “highest” type as “Revelation” (Marion 2002, pp. 225–45). |
2 | Transcendence, as used throughout this article, should not be understood as primarily the “elsewhere” which Marion has used to describe revelation, most recently in Revelation Comes from Elsewhere (Marion 2024). Transcendence here refers to the structure of relation which fundamentally characterizes revelation and experience; see (Marion 2024, pp. 11–15). |
3 | Llewelyn suspects that Derrida also saw this generosity of disclosure as extended to the inapparent to be a preparation for theology. As will be argued further on, the inverse is likely the case—having made a theological judgement about what revelation as transcendence required, the extension of the phenomenological field to include the inapparent became necessary; see (Llewelyn 2009). |
4 | Ibid., p. 9. One would be tempted to locate in this instance the preeminent condition which suits phenomenology for theology, namely the possibility of the manifestation of the inapparent. However, the possibility of the manifestation of the inapparent, as will be argued, is a subsequent reappraisal of the phenomenological tradition after a certain relation to experience between revelation and experience, namely transcendence, has already been determined as being necessary. |
5 | Ibid., p. 13. It is noteworthy once more how Marion conceives of transcendence and how this definition then provides the criteria of legitimacy for any phenomenological account of revelation. |
6 | At another juncture Marion appears more confident about the possibility of a phenomenology without a horizon: “I said to Levinas some years ago that in fact the last step for a real phenomenology would be to give up the concept of horizon. Levinas answered me immediately: ‘Without horizon there is no phenomenology.’ And I boldly assume he was wrong”. (Caputo and Scanlon 1999, p. 66). |
7 | Ibid., p. 2. As Jones indicates, in Marion’s early and explicitly theological work, this notion appears as “distance”. (Jones 2008). |
8 | Ibid., p. 1. In a later version and expansion of this text, Marion juxtaposes the notion of transcendence he wishes to make use of over and against its usage by other phenomenologists: “Transcendence—the concept will not take us very far, nor truly ‘beyond.’ Not, at least, if we take it in the two ways admitted by philosophy. First, according to phenomenology, transcendence is defined with respect to consciousness, precisely as what surpasses the immanence of consciousness to itself… Taken in this first way (Husserl), transcendence never goes beyond the entitative object. Transcendence therefore remains immanent to the horizon of being. And if we radicalize this first level of transcendence by directing it, not only to the entitative object, but, by reducing being in its totality, to Being itself (Heidegger), then by definition transcendence will never reach beyond Being”. (Marion 2007, pp. 17–18). |
9 | Gschwandtner refers to the saturated phenomena as “asymmetrical and non-reciprocal,” which is aggregable, yet Marion insists not only on difference, but a certain kind of otherness which must have preeminence (Gschwandtner 2010, p. 186). |
10 | As Gschwandtner says: “Marion’s phenomenology, then, seeks to provide access to the divine. It makes possible the experience of revelation. It certainly does not ‘prove’ that such an event of Revelation has actually taken place. Yet it provides for the possibility to articulate such excessive experience” (Gschwandtner 2010, p. 187). |
11 | (Marion 1988, pp. 84–103). Further development of the saturated phenomenon occurs in (Marion 2000, pp. 176–216), which Marion repurposes and revises for his discussion of the saturated phenomenon in book IV of Being Given. |
12 | Initially, in French translation (Marion 1992) and expanded upon shortly after the initial German publication for Communio with respect to the question of miracles (Marion 1989). A translation of the text in Communio appears in (Marion 2017, pp. 87–101). Also, a related further development concerned with the notion of the impossible’ appears in (Marion 2007) and is expanded upon in (Marion 2015, pp. 51–82). |
13 | (Tóth 2024, pp. 7–8). Cassara also remarks on how Marion’s phenomenological innovations are keyed to making possible a certain kind of divine phenomenological disclosure: “The rejection of some of the most fundamental structures of Husserlian phenomenology—the horizon, the transcendental ego—along with the absorption and reinterpretation of essential parts of Heidegger’s thought—phenomenality as event and the phenomenon as gift, in addition to the call and the ontological difference—come together to form the very ground on which Marion’s phenomenology of givenness stands. The liberation of the divine transcendency and its unimpeded manifestation depend entirely on these gestures of rejection and absorption” (Cassara 2022, p. 11). |
14 | Kosky notes two other explanations for the applicability of Marion’s phenomenology to both theological and non-theological phenomena; see (Kosky 2004, pp. 644–46). Kosky’s purpose is to provide an account of the peculiar similarities between God in God Without Being and the saturated phenomenon in Being Given, both which are disclosed in an absolute and unconditional appearing, that does not amount to a simple cross-contamination between theology and phenomenology. The argument which follows distinguishes itself by contending for a structural logic for these similarities, as opposed to Kosky’s alternatives of: (1) a minority recognition of givenness in the Christian tradition; (2) givenness as a common historical or cultural a priori; and (3) phenomenological givenness as a secularization of a form of Christian reasoning. |
15 | This can result in the ambiguity of the phenomenon, something which Paul Ricœur remarks on in advance of Marion: “Perhaps the philosopher as philosopher has to admit that one does not know and cannot say whether this Other, the source of the injunction, is another person whom I can look in the face or who can stare at me, or my ancestors for whom there is no representation, to so great an extent docs my debt to them constitute my very self, or God—living God, absent God—or an empty place. With this aporia of the Other, philosophical discourse comes to an end” (Ricoeur 1992, p. 355). |
16 | The corollary effect of this arrangement is a prevalence of reverential overtones with respect to saturated phenomena, which Schrijvers also notes: “This privilege of admiration is present in Marion’s phenomenological works as well when, for instance, the appropriate response to the event of the saturated phenomenon is once again admiration…In Marion’s In Excess, finally, admiration attains the rank of the ‘most powerful exercise possible of the look’ (IE, 59). But from the perspective of an originary finitude what or who is there to admire in an indeed finite world?” (Schrijvers 2011, p. 148). Blond makes a similar observation: “This revelation is apparently simply there, unconditioned by any subjective approach or situation, as such transcendence is understood to be present only in this one phenomenon, and the sole response appropriate for the subject in respect of this manifestation is absolute acceptance and submission. [emphasis added]” (Blond 1997, pp. 1–33). |
17 | Though critics are not cited directly, Marion is almost certainly responding to the charges of Janicaud and the adjoining chorus of readers and interpreters with similar criticisms. |
18 | (Janicaud 2000); see also Janicaud’s rejoinder to the ongoing debate a few years later (Janicaud 2005). |
19 | See a similar point by Thomas A, Carlson on Marion’s adherence to a noncorrelational theology in his introduction to Marion’s The Idol and Distance: (Marion and Carlson 2001, p. xv); Carlson develops this same question later, see (Carlson 1999, pp. 209–14). |
20 | See for example (Kearney 2001, p. 31). Also Caputo and Scanlon refer to a ‘hyperbolic transcendence’ which they detect in Levinas as well; see (Caputo and Scanlon 2007, pp. 3–5). Others, like Smith and Cassidy-Deketelaere see too near a proximity between Marion’s philosophy and Christian theophany; see (Smith 1999; Cassidy-Deketelaere 2018). |
21 | (Zarader 2003, p. 116). Also, it is evident that while the entirety of the text is oriented around the concept of transcendence, most of the various authors in the edited volume by Caputo and Scanlon are concerned with the question of God’s relation to experience; see especially the chapter by Wood in (Caputo and Scanlon 2007, pp. 169–87). Collins also argues for a different notion of transcendence, closer to that of Jean-Luc Nancy; see (Collins 2016). |
22 | Marion responds to Zarader’s critiques, among others in: (Hart 2007, pp. 383–418). |
23 | Transcendence in Marion’s usage would appear to function as a locative—it is the position occupied by revelation, and this position is both unique (alterity of kind) and unilateral (asymmetry of power) with respect to the rest of the phenomenal field. |
24 | See the taxonomy of relation between theology and phenomenology by Simmons in (Benson and Wirzba 2010, pp. 23–28). Also, (Simmons 2011, pp. 159–65). Richard Kearney has also offered a demarcation between theology and phenomenology by referring to quasi-phenomenological theology, which is a hybrid of the two disciplines that attempts to suspend the question of which has priority in a phenomenological investigation; see (Manoussakis 2006, p. 366). |
25 | As Simmons and Benson argue, the corollary to such an account of revelation is usually the concern with reduction—that is, that God may otherwise be denied what is properly due to God’s nature. Though Marion does not make this claim, it is not unreasonable to suppose that such a theological presupposition motivates his concern to construe revelation in relation to experience in such a particular manner; see (Simmons and Benson 2013, pp. 140–41). |
26 | Alternatively, were phenomenology to include presuppositions concerning the nature of revelation, one wonders with Graves what would be owed to theology since theology would have to accommodate itself to the conditions determined beforehand by phenomenology; see (Graves 2021, p. 110). |
27 | Hector raises a similar question about the manner in which Marion and Caputo seem to treat the manner of God’s disclosure in experience in the manner of transcendence as self-evident; see (Hector 2011, pp. 25–26). |
28 | Jones and Horner analyze the lengthy debate on this tension in Marion in significant and illuminating detail and identify certain provisional ways to negotiate the meaning of the tension (Horner) as well as certain mitigating strategies to reduce its effects (Jones); see (Jones and Horner 2025). |
29 | The question concerning the epochē and its relation to the possibility of God in phenomenology has been heavily debated, and arguments frequently appeal to Husserl’s own writings on the question. In this regard, part of the initial dispute Janicaud registers against Marion and others implicated in the “French theological turn” is precisely that the epochē precludes “positions and propositions of metaphysica specialis—the nature of the soul, of the world, and of God”. See (Janicaud 2000, p. 94); see also the debate between Zahavi and Crowell on the status of metaphysics, including the existence of God, with respect to the epochē in (Zahavi 2019, pp. 47–61). On the question concerning the possibility of the reduction and the irreducibility of God, see (Lacoste 2018, pp. 39–67). |
References
- Benson, Bruce Ellis, and Norman Wirzba, eds. 2010. Words of Life: New Theological Turns in French Phenomenology, 1st ed. Perspectives in Continental Philosophy. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Blond, Phillip, ed. 1997. Introduction. In Post-Secular Philosophy: Between Philosophy and Theology. London: Routledge, pp. 1–33. [Google Scholar]
- Caputo, John D. 2007. The Hyperbolization of Phenomenology. In Counter-Experiences: Reading Jean-Luc Marion. Edited by Kevin Hart. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. [Google Scholar]
- Caputo, John D., and Michael J. Scanlon, eds. 1999. God, the Gift, and Postmodernism. The Indiana Series in the Philosophy of Religion; Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Caputo, John D., and Michael J. Scanlon, eds. 2007. Transcendence and Beyond. The Indiana Series in the Philosophy of Religion; Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Carlson, Thomas A. 1999. Indiscretion: Finitude and the Naming of God. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Cassara, Bruno. 2022. Phenomenology and Transcendence: On Openness and Metaphysics in Husserl and Heidegger. Religions 13: 1127. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cassidy-Deketelaere, Nikolaas. 2018. Givenness and Existence: On the Possibility of a Phenomenological Philosophy of Religion. Palgrave Communications 4: 1–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cassidy-Deketelaere, Nikolaas. 2024. Phenomenology, Theology, and Religious Studies. In Theological Fringes of Phenomenology. Edited by Joseph Rivera and Joseph Stephen O’Leary. New York: Routledge, pp. 225–36. [Google Scholar]
- Collins, Ashok. 2016. Being Exposed to Love: The Death of God in Jean-Luc Marion and Jean-Luc Nancy. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 80: 297–319. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fritz, Peter Joseph. 2012. Karl Rahner Repeated in Jean-Luc Marion? Theological Studies 73: 318–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Graves, Adam J. 2021. The Phenomenology of Revelation in Heidegger, Marion, and Ricoeur. Studies in the Thought of Paul Ricoeur. Lanham: Lexington Books. [Google Scholar]
- Gschwandtner, Christina M. 2010. À Dieu or From the Logos? Emmanuel Lévinas and Jean-Luc Marion—Prophets of the Infinite. Philosophy and Theology 22: 177–203. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Han, Béatrice. 2003. Transcendence and the Hermeneutic Circle: Some Thoughts on Marion and Heidegger. In Transcendence in Philosophy and Religion. Edited by James E. Faulconer. Indiana Series in the Philosophy of Religion; Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 120–44. [Google Scholar]
- Hart, Kevin, ed. 2007. The Banality of Saturation. In Counter-Experiences: Reading Jean-Luc Marion. Jeffrey L. Kosky, trans. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 383–418. [Google Scholar]
- Hector, Kevin. 2011. Theology Without Metaphysics: God, Language, and the Spirit of Recognition. Current Issues in Theology. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Janicaud, Dominique, ed. 2000. Phenomenology and the “Theological Turn” The French Debate. Perspectives in Continental Philosophy. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Janicaud, Dominique. 2005. Phenomenology “Wide Open”: After the French Debate. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jones, Tamsin. 2008. Dionysius in Hans Urs Von Balthasar and Jean-Luc Marion. Modern Theology 24: 743–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jones, Tamsin, and Robyn Horner. 2025. How to Interpret What Is Given: Revelation and Hermeneutics in Jean-Luc Marion. Modern Theology, 1–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kearney, Richard. 2001. The God Who May Be: A Hermeneutics of Religion. Indiana Series in the Philosophy of Religion; Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kosky, Jeffrey L. 2004. Philosophy of Religion and Return to Phenomenology in Jean-Luc Marion: From God without Being to Being Given. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 78: 629–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lacoste, Jean-Yves. 2018. The Appearing of God. Translated by Oliver O’Donovan. Oxford: Oxford University Press, vol. 1. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Leung, King-Ho. 2022. Sartre and Marion on Intentionality and Phenomenality. Theory, Culture & Society 39: 41–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Llewelyn, John. 2009. Approaches to (Quasi)Theology Via Appresentation. Research in Phenomenology 39: 224–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Manoussakis, John Panteleimon. 2006. After God. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Marion, Jean-Luc. 1988. Aspekte Der Religionsphanomenologie: Grund, Horizont Und Offenbarung. In Religionsphilosophie Heute. Edited by Alois Halder and Joseph Moller. Translated by Rudolf Funk. Patmos: Dilsseldorf, pp. 84–103. [Google Scholar]
- Marion, Jean-Luc. 1989. A Dieu, Rien d’impossible. Revue Catholique Internationale Communio 14: 43–58. [Google Scholar]
- Marion, Jean-Luc. 1992. Le Possible et la Revelation. In Eros and Eris: Contributions to a Hermeneutical Phenomenology: Liber Amicorum for Adriaan Peperzak. Edited by Adriaan Theodoor Peperzak and Paul van Tongeren. Phaenomenologica 127. Boston: Kluwer Academic, pp. 217–32. [Google Scholar]
- Marion, Jean-Luc. 2000. The Saturated Phenomenon. In Phenomenology and the “Theological Turn” The French Debate. Edited by Dominique Janicaud. Perspectives in Continental Philosophy. New York: Fordham University Press, pp. 176–216. [Google Scholar]
- Marion, Jean-Luc. 2002. Being Given: Toward a Phenomenology of Givenness. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Marion, Jean-Luc. 2007. The Impossible for Man-God. In Transcendence and Beyond. Edited by John D. Caputo and Michael J. Scanlon. Translated by Anne Davenport. The Indiana Series in the Philosophy of Religion; Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Marion, Jean-Luc. 2008. The Visible and the Revealed, 1st ed. Perspectives in Continental Philosophy. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Marion, Jean-Luc. 2015. The Impossible, or What Is Proper to God. In Negative Certainties. Translated by Stephen E. Lewis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 51–82. [Google Scholar]
- Marion, Jean-Luc. 2017. Nothing Is Impossible for God. In Believing in Order to See: On the Rationality of Revelation and the Irrationality of Some Believers. New York: Fordham University Press, pp. 87–101. [Google Scholar]
- Marion, Jean-Luc. 2024. Revelation Comes from Elsewhere. Translated by Stephen E. Lewis, and Stephanie Rumpza. Cultural Memory in the Present. Standford: Standford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Marion, Jean-Luc, and Dan Arbib. 2017. The Rigor of Things: Conversations with Dan Arbib, 1st ed. Translated by Christina M. Gschwandtner. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Marion, Jean-Luc, and Thomas A. Carlson. 2001. Translator’s Introduction. In The Idol and Distance: Five Studies. New York: Fordham University Press, pp. xi–xxxi. [Google Scholar]
- Ricoeur, Paul. 1992. Oneself as Another. Translated by Kathleen Blamey. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schrijvers, Joeri. 2011. Ontotheological Turnings? The Decentering of the Modern Subject in Recent French Phenomenology. SUNY Series in Theology and Continental Thought; Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Simmons, J. Aaron. 2011. God and the Other: Ethics and Politics After the Theological Turn. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Simmons, J. Aaron, and Bruce Ellis Benson. 2013. The New Phenomenology: A Philosophical Introduction. New York: Bloomsbury. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, James K. A. 1999. Liberating Religion from Theology: Marion and Heidegger on the Possibility of a Phenomenology of Religion. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 46: 17–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tóth, Beáta. 2024. Christian Revelation as a Phenomenon: Jean-Luc Marion’s Phenomenological ‘Theology’ and Its Balthasarian Roots. Religions 15: 216. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zahavi, Dan. 2019. Mind, Meaning, and Metaphysics: Another Look. In Normativity, Meaning, and the Promise of Phenomenology, 1st ed. Edited by Matthew Burch, Jack Marsh and Irene McMullin. New York: Routledge, pp. 47–61. [Google Scholar]
- Zarader, Marlène. 2003. Phenomenality and Transcendence. In Transcendence in Philosophy and Religion. Edited by James E. Faulconer. Indiana Series in the Philosophy of Religion; Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 106–19. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Kish, O.A. Transcendence in Jean-Luc Marion: Negotiating Theology and Phenomenology. Religions 2025, 16, 523. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040523
Kish OA. Transcendence in Jean-Luc Marion: Negotiating Theology and Phenomenology. Religions. 2025; 16(4):523. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040523
Chicago/Turabian StyleKish, Otniel A. 2025. "Transcendence in Jean-Luc Marion: Negotiating Theology and Phenomenology" Religions 16, no. 4: 523. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040523
APA StyleKish, O. A. (2025). Transcendence in Jean-Luc Marion: Negotiating Theology and Phenomenology. Religions, 16(4), 523. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040523