An Exploration of Fate in Plato’s Theology: Focusing on the Interpretation of the Timaeus’ Cosmology
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Timaeus’ Literary Form and Character Analysis in Dialogue
2.1. The Timaeus’ Literary Form: Dialogue and Monologue Forms
2.2. Character Analysis in the Timaeus’ Introductory Conversation
2.3. The Purpose of Plato’s Writing of the Timaeus and the Establishment of Corresponding Theories
3. The Hidden Fate in Plato’s Cosmological Theology and the Methodology of “Eikos Logos”
3.1. The Definition of Fate in Plato’s Cosmology
He put intelligence in soul, and soul in body, and so he constructed the cosmos. He wanted to produce a piece of work that would be as excellent and supreme as its nature would allow. This, then, in keeping with our likely account, is how we must say divine providence brought our world into being as a truly living thing, endowed with soul and intelligence.
διὰ δὴ τὸν λογισμὸν τόνδε νοῦν μὲν ἐν ψυχῇ, ψυχὴν δ᾽ ἐν σώματι συνιστὰς τὸ πᾶν συνετεκταίνετο, ὅπως ὅτι κάλλιστον εἴη κατὰ φύσιν ἄριστόν τε ἔργον ἀπειργασμένος. οὕτως οὖν δὴ κατὰ λόγον τὸν εἰκότα δεῖ λέγειν τόνδε τὸν κόσμον ζῷον ἔμψυχον ἔννουν τε τῇ ἀληθείᾳ διὰ τὴν τοῦ θεοῦ γενέσθαι πρόνοιαν(Timaeus, 30b3-c1)5.
He divided the mixture into a number of souls equal to the number of the stars and assigned each soul to a star. He mounted each soul in a carriage, as it were, and showed it the nature of the cosmos. He described to them the laws that had been foreordained: They would all be assigned one and the same initial birth, so that none would be less well treated by him than any other.
συστήσας δὲ τὸ πᾶν διεῖλεν ψυχὰς ἰσαρίθμους τοῖς ἄστροις, ἔνειμέν θ᾽ ἑκάστην πρὸς ἕκαστον, καὶ ἐμβιβάσας ὡς ἐς ὄχημα τὴν τοῦ παντὸς φύσιν ἔδειξεν, νόμους τε τοὺς εἱμαρμένους εἶπεν αὐταῖς, ὅτι γένεσις πρώτη μὲν ἔσοιτο τεταγμένη μία πᾶσιν, ἵνα μήτις ἐλαττοῖτο ὑπ᾽ αὐτοῦ, δέοι δὲ σπαρείσας αὐτὰς εἰς τὰ προσήκοντα ἑκάσταις ἕκαστα ὄργανα χρόνων(Timaeus, 41d4–e3).
3.2. Eikos Logos: The Divine Laws of Fate in Cosmology
4. The Divine Providence of Fate in the Timaeus: Based on the Macroscopic Dimension of the Cosmos
4.1. Divine Providence and Reason: The Laws of the Fate
4.2. The Demiurge’s Divine Laws and Techne of Creating the Cosmos: The Fate of the Cosmic Soul and the Cosmic Body
5. The Fate of Humanity in the Dimension of Determinism: The Combination of Reason and Necessity
5.1. Examining the Essential Relationship Between Humans and the Cosmos: Based on the Divine Laws of Eikos Logos
5.2. The Fate of Human Reincarnation: The Dimension of Determinism
6. The Freedom Dimension of Fate: Breaking Free from Determinism
6.1. The Demiurge’s Freedom: A Critical Dimension of Cosmic Fate
6.2. Potentiality and Actuality: The Free Dimension of Human Fate in the Cosmos
If a person lived a good life throughout his time, he would return to his dwelling place in his companion star to live a life of happiness that agreed with his character. However, if he failed, he would be born a second time as a woman. Moreover, even if he still could not refrain from wickedness, he would be changed again, this time into some wild animal resembling the wicked character he had acquired.
ὧν εἰ μὲν κρατήσοιεν, δίκῃ βιώσοιντο, κρατηθέντες δὲ ἀδικίᾳ. καὶ ὁ μὲν εὖ τὸν προσήκοντα χρόνον βιούς, πάλιν εἰς τὴν τοῦ συννόμου πορευθεὶς οἴκησιν ἄστρου, βίον εὐδαίμονα καὶ συνήθη ἕξοι, σφαλεὶς δὲ τούτων εἰς γυναικὸς φύσιν ἐν τῇ. δευτέρᾳ γενέσει μεταβαλοῖ: μὴ παυόμενός τε ἐν τούτοις ἔτι κακίας, τρόπον ὃν κακύνοιτο, κατὰ τὴν ὁμοιότητα τῆς τοῦ τρόπου γενέσεως εἴς τινα τοιαύτην ἀεὶ μεταβαλοῖ θήρειον φύσιν, ἀλλάττων τε οὐ πρότερον πόνων λήξοι(Timaeus, 42b2-c3).
7. Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Plato discusses the concept of fate in multiple works, such as Crito, 43c1–2, 45c–e, and 46b3–5, Phaedo, 84e2–5, 95b1–5, 113e2–5, and 115a2–4, Cratylus, 398a–b, Theaetutus, 188c–d, Philebus, 23a1–5, Symposium, 193b1–2 and 208a1–3, Phaedrus, 248e3–5 and 255b1–2, Alcibiades, 132a–b, Gorgias, 512e3–4 and 525a4–5, Republic, 365a1–2, 379d–e, 387d3–5, 388d1–2, 399b1–2, 574b1–5, 617b–c, and 620e1–2, and Laws, 799b2–3, 807a–b, 870e2–4, 870e1–5, 873c2–3, 903e1, 918e2–3, 958a1–2, 960c–d, and 982c–d. |
2 | There is controversy in academia regarding the Timaeus’ position in Plato’s dialogues, whether it belongs to the middle or later dialogues. Owen analyzes from the perspectives of rhythm, form, and vocabulary and maintains that the Timaeus should not belong to Plato’s later dialogues but to his middle dialogues (Owen 1953, pp. 79–95). Similarly, scholars represented by Hartmann analyze the Timaeus from a rhetorical perspective (Hartmann 2021, pp. 22–48). Owen also supports his assertion through an ideological analysis of the text. Firstly, the Parmenides criticizes Plato’s concept of “participation” because it leads to infinite regression, so the Timaeus’ creation should be before the Parmenides. The Timaeus still uses the distinction between “eternal being” and “generated being”, but the Theaetetus and the Sophists reject this “two worlds” division, so the Timaeus should be before the Theaetetus and the Sophists. Accordingly, the Timaeus belongs to Plato’s mid-term work, not his later work (Owen 1953, pp. 79–95). Cherniss opposes Owen’s classification method and asserts that the Timaeus cannot be Plato’s mid-term dialogue but must be the later dialogue. Cherniss points out that Owen uses prosody to analyze the Timaeus, which contradicts Plato’s methodology. The concepts of “participation” and “two worlds” cannot serve as criteria for determining the order of Plato’s writings. Therefore, in Cherniss’ perspective, The Parmenides, the Cratylus, and the Theaetetus should be before the Timaeus, and there is no difference in the Timaeus’ later dialogues with Plato (Cherniss 1957, pp. 225–66). |
3 | With Alexander, Scholars represented by Boodin and Hersbell conduct an in-depth analysis of the philosophical origins of cosmology in the Timaeus. In Alexander’s viewpoint, the mathematical methods in the Timaeus are directly derived from Pythagoras, as Plato created the cosmos based on the pattern of mathematics. In addition, the proportion method used in the Timaeus is the method of the demiurge, creating an immortal cosmos and the lesser gods creating mortal humans, which originated from Heraclitus. Plato’s cosmology should also be elucidated in the ethical dimension, and his concern for morality stems from Socrates (Alexander 1918, pp. 1–24). Boodin acknowledges that Anaxagoras influences the Timaeus’ cosmology. Anaxagoras holds that nous is the origin of the cosmos, which profoundly influences the theoretical construction of Plato’s cosmology, as Plato believes that nous is the crucial link in generating the cosmos. Boodin reminds us, however, that Anaxagoras’ nous cannot be wholly equated with the forms the Timaeus hopes to express, as Anaxagoras reduces nous to purely material elements (Boodin 1929, pp. 489–505). Hersbell analyzes explicitly the relationship between Empedocles and Plato. Although Empedocles’ four elements match the components that make up the cosmos in the Timaeus, there are differences in understanding the essence of the four primary bodies. Moreover, Heraclitus’ viewpoint on love and struggle does not directly influence Plato’s cosmology (Hersbell 1974, pp. 145–66). |
4 | The debate between literalist and metaphorist interpretations in academia is a key issue in studying Plato’s cosmology. Scholars such as Finkelberg, Dillon, and Carone assert the crucial significance of resolving this controversy to understand Plato’s cosmology. Finkelberg harbors the attitude that the debate between two interpretations has a long history in academia, with Aristotle representing the literalist interpretation and the Academy representing the metaphorical interpretation. Specifically, Finkelberg analyzes Plato’s cosmology using mathematical methods and the differences between temporality and non-temporality (Finkelberg 1996, pp. 391–409). Dillon maintains that there are numerous misinterpretations in the Timaeus’ commentaries, both intentionally and unintentionally, by ancient scholars. Starting from the debate between literalist and metaphorist interpretations, Dillon conducts a detailed textual revision of the Timaeus (Dillon 1989, pp. 50–72). Carone holds that both literalist and metaphorist interpretations are reasonable. Therefore, he proposes a compromise assertion, which explains the process of the demiurge’s creation from a literalist perspective and regards the demiurge’s creation as an ongoing process (Carone 2004, pp. 211–26). |
5 | The citations of the Timaeus in this article are from Zeyl’s English translation (Plato 2000). |
6 | Johansen explains the essence of truth from the myth of Atlantis. On the one hand, Johansen agrees that Atlantis is indeed a fabricated story, as it is impossible to verify whether the story of Atlantis has ever occurred in history. On the other hand, the so-called “real story” cannot be demonstrated as simple fiction. It should be understood as “another kind of truth.” The so-called truth aims to demonstrate how the demiurge acts, so it is important for us to clarify the significance of the demiurge’s actions (Johansen 2005, pp. 28, 67). |
7 | Plato makes two distinctions in the Timaeus, the first between eternal and generated beings. Eternal beings are invisible and intangible, belonging to things that can be attained through reason. Generated beings are visible and tangible and belong to beings that the sense-organs can perceive. The second is the distinction between the different ways of account, that is, the difference between the account of eternal beings and the account of generated beings. The description of eternal beings remains unchanged, while the account of generated beings follows the method of eikos logos (Timaeus, 28b–29b). |
8 | There is a conflict in the texts of the Timaeus and Theaetetus regarding the complete four elements and the flux of element traces: According to Theaetetus, all things are in the process of flux and, therefore, cannot be spoken of. Although the Timaeus acknowledges the flux state of element traces, Plato believes that element traces can be spoken of through “this such.” Gill criticizes Owen’s viewpoint; Owen holds that on the condition that the Timaeus’ creation time comes first, the contradiction between different texts regarding the conception of flux can be resolved. However, Gill thinks that this is not an appropriate solution (Gill 1987, pp. 34–53). |
9 | In Plato’s perspective, the standard of cosmos’ perfection requires that there must be mortal living bodies in the cosmos, such as humans, beasts, and plants. However, imperfect mortal beings in the cosmos cannot be created by the demiurge. Otherwise, it will destroy the demiurge’s goodness and lack of jealousy and lead to the equality of mortal humans and immortal gods in the hierarchy. This is unacceptable, as it would undermine the overall goodness of the cosmos, so the lesser gods accept the task given to them by the demiurge to create mortal beings. Once the demiurge entrusts the task of creating mortal beings to the lesser gods, he is not responsible for any evil in the cosmos. |
10 | Johansen provides a subtle explanation of the demiurge’s free will. According to Johansen’s opinion, in Plato’s cosmology, the demiurge can choose to use either the perfect or imperfect model; the latter belongs to the category of generated beings. From the generated cosmos, it can be inferred that the demiurge should choose the perfect model to create the cosmos, the eternal eidos. The eternal model has the characteristic of beauty, while the generated model lacks beauty compared to the former, so the generated being is created by imitating eidos (Johansen 2014, pp. 297–20). |
11 | Plato focuses on the discussion of fate and freedom in the Politicus. Although the Politicus and the Timaeus have different contexts, the Politicus still have important reference value for the Timaeus. Please refer to the Politicus 272e: τοῦ παντὸς ὁ μὲν κυβερνήτης͵ οἷον πηδαλίων οἴακος ἀφέμενος͵ εἰς τὴν αὑτοῦ περιωπὴν ἀπέστη͵ τὸν δὲ δὴ κόσμον πάλιν ἀνέστρεφεν εἱμαρμένη τε καὶ σύμφυτος ἐπιθυμία; 273b: τὸν εἰωθότα δρόμον τὸν ἑαυτοῦ κατακοσμούμενος ᾔει͵ ἐπιμέλειαν καὶ κράτος ἔχων αὐτὸς τῶν ἐν αὑτῷ τε καὶ ἑαυτοῦ͵ τὴν τοῦ δημιουργοῦ καὶ πατρὸς ἀπομνημονεύων διδαχὴν εἰς δύναμιν; 273d: προϊόντος δὲ τοῦ χρόνου καὶ λήθης ἐγγιγνομένης ἐν αὐτῷ μᾶλλον καὶ δυναστεύει τὸ τῆς παλαιᾶς ἀναρμοστίας πάθος; 273e: ἵνα μὴ χειμασθεὶς ὑπὸ ταραχῆς διαλυθεὶς εἰς τὸν τῆς ἀνομοιότητος ἄπειρον ὄντα πόντον δύῃ; 273e: κοσμεῖ τε καὶ ἐπανορθῶν ἀθάνατον αὐτὸν καὶ ἀγήρων ἀπεργάζεται. |
References
- Alexander, Hartley. 1918. Plato’s Conception of the Cosmos. The Monist 28: 1–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Boodin, John Elof. 1929. Cosmology in Plato’s Thought (I.). Mind 38: 489–505. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Boys-Stones, George. 2017. Cornutus und sein philosophisches Umfeld: Der Antiplatonismus der Epidrome. In Die Griechischen Götter: Cornutus-Ein Überblick über Namen, Bilder und Deutungen. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck Gmbh and Co. KG, pp. 1–24. [Google Scholar]
- Brisson, Luc. 2021. How to Make a Soul in the Timaeus. In Proceedings of the Tenth Symposium Platonicum Pragense. Leiden: Brill, pp. 70–91. [Google Scholar]
- Broadie, Sarah. 2008. Theological Sidelights From Plato’s Timaeus. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 1–17. [Google Scholar]
- Broadie, Sarah. 2012. Nature and Divinity in Plato’s Timaeus. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Burnyeat, Myles. 2005. Eikos Muthos. Rhizai II: 143–65. [Google Scholar]
- Carone, Gabriela. 2004. Creation in the “Timaeus”: The Middle Way. Apeiron 37: 211–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Carone, Gabriela. 2005. Plato’s Cosmology and its Ethical Dimensions. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Charbit, Yves, and Arundhati Virmani. 2002. The Platonic City: History and Utopia. Population 57: 207–35. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cherniss, Harold. 1957. The Relation of the Timaeus to Plato’s Later Dialogues. The American Journal of Philology 78: 225–66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cornford, Francis. 1935. Plato’s Cosmology: The Timaeus of Plato. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Dillon, John. 1989. Tampering with the Timaeus: Ideological Emendations in Plato, with Special Reference to the Timaeus. The American Journal of Philology 110: 50–72. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Finkelberg, Aryeh. 1996. Plato’s Method in the Timaeus. American Journal of Philology 117: 391–409. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fronterotta, Francesco. 2021. Panteles Zōion e Pantelōs on: Vita, Anima e Movimento Intellegibile nel Timeo (e nel Sofista). In Proceedings of the Tenth Symposium Platonicum Pragense. Leiden: Brill, pp. 49–69. [Google Scholar]
- Gill, Mary. 1987. Matter and Flux in Plato’s “Timaeus”. Phronesis 32: 34–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gkatzaras, Thanassis. 2018. The Form of the Good in Plato’s Timaeus. Plato: The Internet Journal of the International Plato Society 17: 71–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Glenn, S. 2011. Proportion and Mathematics in Plato’s Timaeus. Hermathena 190: 11–27. [Google Scholar]
- Gregory, Andrew. 2008. Introduction. In Plato: Timaeus and Critias. Translated by Robin Waterfield. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Griffin, Svetela. 2005. “A Feast of Speeches”: Form and Content in Plato’s “Timaeus”. Hermes 133: 312–27. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hartmann, Lucius. 2021. Die Grosse Rede des Timaios–ein Beispiel Wahrer Rhetorik? In Proceedings of the Tenth Symposium Platonicum Pragense. Leiden: Brill, pp. 22–48. [Google Scholar]
- Hersbell, Jackson. 1974. Empedoclean Influences on the Timaeus. Phoenix 28: 145–66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ilievski, Viktor. 2013. Soul, Causation and Evil: Is Plato’s ψυχή indeed κινήσεως ἁπάσης αἰτία and τῶν πάντωναἰτία? Hermathena 195: 31–54. [Google Scholar]
- Johansen, Thomas. 2005. Plato’s Natural Philosophy: A Study of the Timaeus-Critias. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Johansen, Thomas. 2014. Why the Cosmos Needs a Craftsman. Phronesis 59: 297–320. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Johansen, Thomas. 2021. Crafting the Cosmos: Plato on the Limitations of Divine Craftsmanship. In Productive Knowledge in Ancient Philosophy. Edited by Thomas Johansen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 86–108. [Google Scholar]
- Kahn, Charles. 1987. Plato’s Theory of Desire. Review of Metaphysics 41: 77–103. [Google Scholar]
- Krell, David. 1975. Female Parts in “Timaeus”. A Journal of Humanities and Classics 2: 400–21. [Google Scholar]
- Lampert, Laurence, and Christopher Planeaux. 1998. Who’s Who in “Timaeus-Critias and Why”. The Review of Metaphysics 52: 87–125. [Google Scholar]
- Matskiv, Vasyl Василий Мацькив. 2021. The Expression of Plato’s Philosophical Position Thorough the Dialogue Form: Chance or Necessity? ДИАЛОГИЧЕСКАЯ ФОРМА КАК ВЫРАЗИТЕЛЬ ФИЛОСОФСКОЙ ПОЗИЦИИ ПЛАТОНА: СЛУЧАЙНОСТЬ ИЛИ НЕОБХОДИМОСТЬ? Δόξα/Дoкса 35: 141–51. [Google Scholar]
- McCoy, Marina. 2017. Perspectivism and the Philosophical Rhetoric of the Dialogue Form. Plato: The Internet journal of the International Plato Society 16: 45–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McHugh, Mary. 2019. Plato’s Timaeus and Time. In Plato at Syracuse: Essays on Plato in Western Greece with a New Translation of the Seventh Letter by Jonah Redding. Iowa: Parnassos Press, pp. 167–84. [Google Scholar]
- Mohr, Richard. 1985. Plato’s Theology Reconsidered: What the Demiurge Does. History of Philosophy Quarterly 2: 131–44. [Google Scholar]
- Morrow, Glenn. 1950. Necessity and Persuasion in Plato’s Timaeus. The Philosophical Review 59: 147–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Owen, Gwilym. 1953. The Place of the Timaeus in Plato’s Dialogues. The Classical Quarterly 3: 79–95. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Patterson, Richard. 1981. The Unique Worlds of the “Timaeus”. Phoenix 35: 105–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pears, Colin. 2015. Congruency and Evil in Plato’s “Timaeus”. The Review of Metaphysics 69: 93–113. [Google Scholar]
- Pearson, Lionel. 1986. The Speeches in the Timaeus’ History. The American Journal of Philology 107: 350–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Plato. 2000. Timaeus. Translated by Donald Zeyl. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Prince, Brian. 2014. The Metaphysics of Bodily Health and Disease in Plato’s Timaeus. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 22: 908–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Robinson, Richard. 1990. The Tripartite Soul in the “Timaeus”. Phronesis 35: 103–10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rosen, Stanley. 1979. Plato’s Myth of the Reserved Cosmos. The Review of Metaphysics 33: 59–85. [Google Scholar]
- Steel, Carlos. 2001. The Moral Purpose of the Human Body: A Reading of the Timaeus 69–72. Phronesis 46: 105–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tarán, Leonardo. 1971. The Creation Myth in Plato’s Timaeus. In Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy. Edited by John P. Anton and George Kustas. Albany: State University of New York Press, pp. 372–407. [Google Scholar]
- Vlastos, Gregory. 1965. Creation in the Timaeus: Is it a Fiction? In Studies in Plato’s Metaphysics. Edited by Reginald Allen. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, pp. 401–19. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfsdorf, David. 2014. Timaeus’ Explanation of Sense-Perceptual Pleasure. The Journal of Hellenic Studies 134: 120–35. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Zhao, Q. An Exploration of Fate in Plato’s Theology: Focusing on the Interpretation of the Timaeus’ Cosmology. Religions 2025, 16, 495. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040495
Zhao Q. An Exploration of Fate in Plato’s Theology: Focusing on the Interpretation of the Timaeus’ Cosmology. Religions. 2025; 16(4):495. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040495
Chicago/Turabian StyleZhao, Qi. 2025. "An Exploration of Fate in Plato’s Theology: Focusing on the Interpretation of the Timaeus’ Cosmology" Religions 16, no. 4: 495. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040495
APA StyleZhao, Q. (2025). An Exploration of Fate in Plato’s Theology: Focusing on the Interpretation of the Timaeus’ Cosmology. Religions, 16(4), 495. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16040495