2.4.2. From Contra Eunomium Libri (see Patr. Graec. vol. 45, cols. 248–464; using Gregory of Nyssa, Opera I and II [ed. Jaeger] vol. 1, pp. 3–409; vol. 2. pp. 3–311; and note Clav. Patr. Graec. 3135)
But wise Gregory, his brother, speaks as follows in his Refutation of Eunomius (which begins: To want to help everybody was not, apparently): This, then, is what the imitator of Paul does, having seen that the error of those who teach ‘dissimilarity’ is strengthened through the word ‘ingenerate’ (Syr. ܠܐ ܝܠܝܕܐ) (in the evil, heretical usage of the term). He advised that we should safeguard in our souls the truly religious idea of ‘ingenerate’ but that the word should not be an object of special concern, because it becomes a resource of sin to those who are perishing. For the title of ‘Father’ in one sense is enough to produce for us the sense of ‘ingenerate’. For having heard ‘Father’ we at once understand the one who is the cause of everything’s existence, who, had he owned a cause transcending himself, would not be called ‘Father’ in the full sense of the word, because ‘Father’ (in the full sense) would have been attributed to the cause found to be prior. And similarly in the fifth of his books against impious Eunomius (the beginning goes: Because, he says, the word ‘Lord’ he writes as follows: for the things remain what they are by nature, but the mind, when it handles existing things, reveals its ideas by whatever words it discovers. Just as Peter’s substance was not altered along with the alteration of name, so no other visible object is altered by variations of name. This is the reason we say that the term ‘ingenerate’ was applied by us to the truly primal Father, the cause of all, no damage at all accruing to the meaning of the subject if we indicate it with a different, equivalent word. For it is permissible, instead of saying ‘ingenerate’, to call him ‘First Cause’ or ‘Father of the Only-begotten’ or ‘Causeless Existent (Ibid., p. 70).
Now if he says that these, being what they are, are insufficient to confirm the truth of the statements, let one, who (as he [Gregory] claims) speaks nothing but what the Fathers spoke, bend his ears to this wise teacher, and hear again the kinds of thing he said to impious Eunomius (who had written cognate, blasphemous nonsense) in the fifth book (the beginning goes: Because, he says, the word ‘Lord’): But Peter and Paul, he says, were named by men, and therefore there was a possibility of their names being changed. But what existent is not named by men? I summon you, Eunomius, as a witness to the argument. For if you make changes of name a proof that things have been named by men, you must thereby agree that every name has been imposed on existents by us, because the same names of objects have not prevailed amongst everybody. For just as Paul was once Saul and Peter was Simon [Acts 13:9; Matt 17:18], so land, sky, air, ocean and all the parts of creation are not named alike by everybody, but one way by the Hebrews, another way by us and with different names by each nation. If, then, Eunomius has a valid objection to establish, I mean that Peter and Paul got new names because their names were given them by men, our argument (constructed from similar premisses and stating that everything has been given its name by us) must be confirmed, because the names of everything vary with different nations. Now if everything is of this kind, ‘generate’ and ‘ingenerate’ can be no different. For these also get fresh names. We have an idea about some object and reformulate it as a name. We say what has been thought in different words at different times, not creating the realities but indicating them by the names we call them (Ibid., p.86).
Saint Gregory, his brother, spoke in his book Against Eunomius the impious and witless (its beginning runs: There is a limit to the labours of those who fight in contests) as follows: If, then, the meaning of ‘substance’ is one thing and the term ‘generation’ is established to mean something else, their sophistical tricks have collapsed all of a sudden, like earthenware pots, thrown together and shattering one another. For it will no longer be open to them to carry over the ingenerate-generate distinction to the substance of Father and Son and simultaneously transfer the mutual conflict of the names to the realities. Likewise in the fifth book of the same treatise Against Eunomius (its beginning goes: Because, he says, the word ‘Lord’ he spoke as follows: But if he asserts a difference of substance between generacy and ingeneracy like that between fire and water, and imagines the names as having the same mutual relation as his examples have, the awfulness of his blasphemy will be evident even if we stay silent. For fire and water have mutually destructive natures and when one happens to be in the other it is destroyed by the force of the more powerful. If, therefore, he teaches this sort of remoteness between the Ingenerate’s nature and the Only-begotten’s, he must consequently concede that this destructive contrariety too resides in the difference between the substances; so that their nature must thereby be incompatible and unshared, and one would be consumed by the other or both mutually if they should come together. How, then, can the Son be ‘in the Father’ without being destroyed? How can the Father, while ‘in the Son’, hold out perpetually and remain unconsumed, if (as Eunomius says) the property of the fire in respect to water is also preserved in the relationship of generate to ingenerate? But neither does the argument perceive any communion between earth and air; for earth is firm, stable, hard, with a downward tendency and heavy. Air, though, has a nature founded on the opposites. In the same way white or black are included in colour-contraries and I agree that a circle is not identical with a triangle for each is, by the condition of its shape, what the other is not. I cannot, though, discover what he sees the opposition between God the Father and God the Only-begotten Son to reside in. A single goodness, wisdom, justice, intelligence, power, incorruptibility, and all other terms of sublime meaning are used of each alike. In a certain sense the power of each resides in the other; for the Father effects everything through the Son, and the Only-begotten, being the Father’s power, effects everything in him (Ibid., pp. 160, 162).
Saint Gregory, Bishop of Nyssa, wrote in similar vein in his first book Against Eunomius (its beginning runs: There is a limit to the labours of contestants): But I say we ought to pay close attention to the question whether it is the natural relationship which introduces the employment of these names. For he must be saying this: that affinity of substance enters with affinity of names. For he will not be saying that the mere names on their own, separated from a comprehension of their meanings, have any mutual relationship and affinity; no, we distinguish affinity and alien-ness of appellations by the meanings signified by the words. Therefore, if he acknowledges a natural relationship between Father and Son, let us leave the appellations and scrutinize the force of the things indicated. And again: So if, as Eunomius says, the appellations prove affinity, and the affinity is perceptible in the realities conceived of as individual and not in the mere verbal expressions of the names (if it be not rash so to refer to the Son and the Father) who can deny that the champion of blasphemy too has been drawn over to the advocacy of true religion of his own accord seeing that he demolishes his arguments himself and preaches commonness of substance as divine doctrine? For the argument about this he involuntarily tossed out on the side of truth is no cheat: he would not have been called ‘Son’, if the natural meaning of the terms had not corroborated the appellation (Ibid., pp. 178, 180).
Gregory, Bishop of Nyssa, Basil’s brother is seen to have written in the fifth book Against Eunomius (its beginning is: Because, he says, the word ‘Lord’) as follows’: For when we say ‘this one was begotten’ or ‘was not begotten’, we are stamped with a two-fold conception by the statement: by the demonstrative part of the sentence we look at the substrate; by ‘was begotten’ or ‘was not begotten’ we learn what is viewed as pertaining to the substrate. So that we understand one thing concerning the being but another thing concerning what is viewed as pertaining to the being. Besides, along with each term used of the divine nature (e.g., ‘just’, ‘incorruptible’, ‘immortal’, ‘ingenerate’ and any other expression) ‘is’ has to be understood. Even if the word happens not to accompany the statement, all the same the speaker’s and listener’s minds must complete the term by ‘is’; so that the title lands in a vacuum unless the ‘is’ be supplied. For instance (for it is better to present the argument using an example) when David says: “God the righteous judge, mighty and patient” [Ps 7:11], unless ‘is’ were understood along with each term used, the itemizing of titles unsupported by any substrate would be thought vacuous and baseless. But when ‘is’ is understood along with each term, the expressions altogether gain significance as they are viewed belonging with that which is (Ibid., pp. 206, 208).
Gregory too, the wise doctor’s brother, shall confirm that this is so by consideration of God the Father. He wrote as follows in the thirty seventh chapter of the Refutation of Eunomius the impious (its beginning is: To want to help everybody was not, apparently): This, then, is what the imitator of Paul too does: having seen that the error of those who teach dissimilarity through the word ‘ingenerate’ is strengthened by its evil, heretical usage, he advised that we should safeguard in our soul the truly religious idea of ‘ingenerate’, but that the word should not be an object of special concern, because it becomes food for sin to those who are perishing. For the name “Father’ is, by its meaning, enough to produce for us the sense of ‘ingenerate’. For having heard “Father’ we at once understand the one who is the cause of everything’s existence who, had he owned another cause transcending himself, would not be called ‘Father’ in the full sense of the word, because the appellation ‘Father’ (in the full sense) would have been attributed to the cause found to be prior. But if he is the cause of all and “all is from” him, as the Apostle says [cf. Rom 11:36}, obviously nothing can be found to pre-exist his being. And this is ingenerate existence. And again: But we despise this puerile, superficial attack of theirs and will manfully acknowledge what is presented by them as an absurdity: that the name ‘Father’ is identical in meaning with ‘ingenerate’; that ‘ingenerate’ reveals the Father as not being from anything; and that the Father introduces connectedly along with himself, through the relationship, the idea of the Only-begotten (Ibid., p. 216).
Gregory of Nyssa, very cleverly demolished the same mischievous attack by writing as follows in his fifth book Against Eunomius (its beginning goes: Because, he says, the word ‘Lord’): If the Son’s substance is called “Spirit” and God also is called Spirit (for this is also how the Gospel states it [John 4:24]) the Father’s substance must be called Spirit too. But their argument that things with dissimilar names have dissimilar natures has as its logical consequence that things with similar names are not mutually alien in nature either. So because, according to their argument, the substance of Son and Father is termed ‘Spirit’, the fact of there being no difference in substance is hereby given clear proof. And a few lines later: For if God is called ‘Spirit’ in the Gospel and the substance of the Only-begotten is made out by Eunomius to be Spirit, there being no difference between the terms, what are indicated by the terms cannot differ in nature from one another either. And again after other matters: What, then, are the titles of the substances by which he has learned of a difference in nature between Father and Son? He mentions fire and water, air and earth, cold and hot, white and black, triangle and circle. He scores a victory with his examples; he has got much the better of me in the argument. For I will not gainsay the argument that names which have nothing in common disclose along with themselves a difference of natures. But this acute and quick mind of his fails to see just this: that here the Father is termed ‘God’, the Son is termed ‘God’ and ‘just’, ‘incorruptible’ and all the terms belonging to the doctrine of God’ are applied equally to both Father and Son. In which case, if a divergence of titles indicates a difference of natures; commonness of names must disclose commonness of substance. If we must agree that the divine substance is known by means of names, it would be appropriate to apply the lofty, God-befitting words to the nature rather than the terms ‘generate’ and ‘ingenerate’ (Ibid., p. 266).
But let us pass to the wise teaching of his namesake; he [Gregory of Nyssa], too, indeed, impelled by the same grace says: Every name whatsoever you use belongs with the being and is not the being. And again: All the things existing within the creation are considered with the aid of the meaning of names. One who says ‘sky’ has brought the mind of his auditor to the created thing signified by this term, and one who mentions man or any other living thing by name immediately impresses his auditor with the appearance of the living thing. And again: Only the uncreated nature believed in the Father, Son and Holy Ghost transcends every nameable meaning. Therefore, when the Word referred to “the name” in handing over the Faith, he did not add what it was (for how could a name be found for a reality “above every name”?) [Phil 2:9] but gave power so that our mind, being stirred by piety, should be able to discover what the name, revelatory of the transcendent nature, is, which we should attach in like manner to the Father, the Son and the Holy Ghost, whether it be ‘the Good’, or ‘the Incorruptible’, whatever name each man thinks fitting to be taken for the manifesting of the immortal nature (Ibid., p. 344).
For Gregory also who adorned the throne of Nyssa, says this in the second book Against Eunomius the abominable: I ask the readers not to be irritated by the exactitude of the examination which unwillingly extends the discourse to a large size. For it is not on unimportant matters that we are in jeopardy, so that, if we pass by things that need more studied contemplation, we should suffer little damage, but we are endangered on the chief article of our hope. For it is set before us either we should be Christians, not deluded by heretical perdition, or that we should be utterly swept away into Jewish and pagan opinions. And at the beginning of the third book of the same treatise he says as follows: But it is now time to examine more studiously what was said by Eunomius himself and by our father in connexion with the Apostle Peter’s words. But if a careful contemplation lengthens the discourse to a large extent, the right-thinking listener will completely pardon the fact, not blaming us but the one who caused it (Ibid., p. 362).
For we find our teachers did this too, and, out of many, we show wise Gregory of Nyssa who in the fourth chapter of his Refutation of Eunomius (which begins: It is not possible, it seems, to want to help everybody) says as follows: I omit all such as being an empty multitude of things which introduce nothing useful. But if any defence of heretical opinion is made by him, towards this I consider it would be as well for me to devote more effort. For this is how the leader of divine doctrines acted in his own discourse, he who, though there were many points capable of broadening the argument, runs through only the essentials and shortens most of the subject-matter, selecting from all the statements in that book of impiety, the main points of the blasphemies (CD vol. 32, p. 66).
Saint Gregory teaches us this again in the second chapter of the Refutation just mentioned, writing as follows: It has occurred to me to say these things on considering one who shared his good things unsparingly, with everybody, Basil, I mean, the man of God, the mouth of blessing, who often in the abundance of spiritual treasures pours out the grace of wisdom without investigation even on souls who devise evil, even on Eunomius ungrateful to those who have taken pains to benefit him. For he, because of his soul’s immeasurable disease with which it sickened as regards the faith, was considered pitiable by all participants in the Church (for who is so lacking in compassion as not to pity the perishing?) but him alone did he move to undertake the cure, him alone who in the abundance of his philanthropy ventures upon an impossible cure; who, pained by the loss of the man, due to his natural sympathy towards those in misery, devised, as an antidote to the evil, lethal poisons, a refutation of heresy having as its aim to save and restore him thereby to the Church. But he, as if mentally distraught by madness, rages against the physician, fights and battles with, and counts an enemy him who battles to draw him from the gulf of evil. And he babbles in this way not simply casually before just anyone, but he has erected a written monument to his own madness, and having obtained in a long period, as much leisure as he desired, he travailed with the discourse longer than the large, big-bodied animals, in all the intervening time (Ibid., pp. 68, 70).
Wise Gregory, who occupied with sanctity the throne of Nyssa, is seen to have said as follows in the 29th chapter of the Refutation of Eunomius (whose beginning is: To want to help everybody was not, apparently): If, therefore, the concept of the energy indicates the substance, one nature of the two will be seen, energy and substance being found in the same equal marks and properties. If, however, the concepts of substance and energy are not the same but the meaning of each is different, how can proofs of the points in question be given by things alien ad foreign? It is just as if, when the substance of manhood is being inquired into and it is being discussed whether man is a laughing animal or an animal capable of grammar, someone should take, as proof of the former subject, the construction of a house or ship which a builder or shipwright has effected (Ibid., p. 146).
Led by the same Spirit, wise Gregory of Nyssa, too, wrote in the first book Against Eunomius (whose beginning runs: There is a limit to him who “strives lawfully” [1 Tim 2:5b]): But I say, we ought to pay close attention to the question whether it is the natural relationship which introduces the employment of these names. For he must be saying this: that affinity of substance enters along with affinity of names. For he is not saying that mere names on their own, separated from the meaning of the objects indicated have any mutual relationship and affinity; no, we distinguish affinity and alien-ness of appellations by the meanings signified by the words. Therefore, if he acknowledges a natural relationship between Father and Son, let us leave the appellations and scrutinize the force of the things indicated. And in the second book Against Eunomius: In the same way here too (when offspring and creature are mentioned together) in passing from the expressions to the meanings we do not envisage each of the names as containing the same understanding. And again in the book Against the same wicked Eunomius’ Statements (whose beginning runs: The faith of Christians): For one who says ‘sky’ has brought the minds of his auditor to the created thing signified by this term, and one who mentions man or any other living thing by name immediately impresses his auditor with the appearance of the living thing. All the other things, too, are likewise depicted, through the names imposed on them, in the heart of one who has received through the ear the appellation imposed on the reality (Ibid., pp. 208, 210).
For wise Gregory of Nyssa answered Eunomius, who made similar thoughtless pronouncements: Every argument, so long as it is asserted by authority without proof, is old wives’ prattle, having no power to prove thereby the point at issue when no support for the statements made is introduced either from the divine words or from human reasonings (Ibid., pp. 234, 236).
Gregory, too, Basil’s brother, taught these sacred doctrines and taking up the same contests against Eunomius the intoxicated, wrote in his fifth book (its beginning runs, Because, he says, the word ‘Lord’), as follows: Anyone, then, undertaking to give a definition of the existence of the one who is good and is ingenerate, would be useless if he spoke of the things viewed in him and said nothing of the substance itself which he had undertaken to explain with a definition. For existing ingenerately is one of the things viewed in “Him who is” [Exod 3:11], whereas the concept of existing is one thing and that of how it exists, another (Ibid., p. 492).
Here we shall move the examination on to words akin to those divinely inspired words of Saint Basil. For the wise instructor, his brother Gregory, wrote in the first book Against Eunomius as follows: I will take up and repeat the sentence of his which I set down at the beginning. ‘we do not refuse’, he says, ‘also to call the Son, since he is begotten, “offspring”, the begotten substance itself and the title “Son” laying claim to such a relationship of terms’. So now let the critical hearer of these words remember this: by using ‘begotten substance’ of the Only- begotten he grants, by logical sequence, that we should use ‘unbegotten substance’ of the Father, so that, therefore, neither ingeneracy nor generacy will be understood as substance; but substance, on the one hand, and the fact that it was begotten or not begotten, on the other hand, are to be considered individually by means of the properties viewed in the substance. But let us consider the reasoning on this point more studiously. He says that a substance has been begotten, and that the name of the substance which has been begotten is ‘Son’. However, here the argument from our side rebuts the opposing argument on two grounds: first, for the impudence of its knavery; secondly for the feebleness of its attack on us. For he is acting with malicious deceit in speaking of the generacy of the substance, in order to procure the mutual opposition of the substances sundered by generacy and ingeneracy into a difference of natures. The feebleness of the attempt is rebutted by the very means whereby the plot is set up. For one who says the substance has been begotten clearly defines generacy as being something other than substance, so as not to permit the meaning of generacy to be adapted to the concept of substance. For he has not done in this part the very thing he designed in many passages so that he could say that generacy is the substance itself; but here he acknowledges that the substance has been begotten, so that the hearers have a distinct idea of each word. For different ideas are created for the hearer of ‘has been begotten’ and by the term ‘substance’. The argument will become clearer to us by illustrations. The Lord said in the Gospel that when her labour is at hand a woman is in pain but afterwards rejoices in her happiness “that a man has been born into the world” (John 16:21). So, just as in this passage we have learned from the Gospel two distinct ideas: first, we have understood a generation by birth; secondly, the one who has come into existence by generation (for a man is not generation but by generation the man exists); so also here; since Eunomius has acknowledged that the substance was begotten, we have learned by the word ‘begotten’ the fact of being derived from something and by the word ‘substance’ we have understood a substrate possessing a derived hypostasis. If, then, the meaning of ‘substance’ is one thing and the term ‘generation’ is established to mean something else, their sophistical tricks have collapsed all of a sudden, like earthenware pots thrown together and shattering one another. For it will no longer be open to them to carry over the ingenerate-generate distinction to the substance of Father and Son and simultaneously transfer the mutual conflict of the names to the realities. For with Eunomius having agreed that the substance was begotten (as the Gospel illustration too explains this sort of notion, an illustration by which, on learning that a man has been begotten we do not understand man and generation as meaning the same thing but have received the notion proper to each term) the heresy which teaches the otherness of substances through such words absolutely has no longer any room (Ibid., pp. 508, 510, 512).
So they then acted corruptly in that document and produced a proof-text from Gregory (the one time sainted bishop of Nyssa, who illuminated the whole world under the Sun with the radiance of his words) when he caught Eunomius the impious in the toils of his arguments in the third book he wrote against that wicked man, as follows: ‘So just as in this passage we have learned from the Gospel two distinct ideas: first, we have understood a generation by birth; secondly, the one who has come into existence by generation (for a man is not generation but by generation the man exists); so also here; since Eunomius has acknowledged that the substance was begotten, we have learned by the word ‘begotten’ the fact of being derived from something and by the word “substance” we have understood a substrate possessing a derived hypostasis. And again: ‘For with Eunomius having agreed that the substance was begotten (as the Gospel illustration too explains this sort of notion, an illustration by which, on learning that a man has been begotten we do not understand man and generation as meaning the same thing but have received the notion proper to each term) the heresy which teaches the otherness of substances through such words absolutely has no longer any room’ (Ibid., p. 518).
For on such things too we have the same wise Gregory who instructs us by his defence of his brother, Basil the great, against Eunomius, the master and teacher of this writer and says as follows in the eighth chapter of his Refutation of Eunomius the impious (its beginning runs: To want to help everybody was not, apparently): Therefore, the sequence of insulting and abusing is prevented from its further courses by patience. So that if anybody pays back insult with insult and abuse with abuse, he must increase the outrage by nourishing it with things similar. Therefore, leaving aside all the intervening argument, which consists of insults, mockery, abuse and cavils, I shall hurry the discussion on to the examination of doctrines. But if anyone says I am refraining from abuse owing to a lack of requital in kind, let him observe himself how much proneness there is towards evil, slipping without occasion into sin of its own accord. And a few lines later: But I recollect that divine utterance which spoke prophetically those prophetic things about him, where he compares him with abusive women who load the modest with their own obscenities (Ibid, pp. 520, 522).
And so, when he [Gregory] begins the second of that pair earlier pair, he says: The first things in the contests with Eunomius have indeed already been accomplished sufficiently with God’s help in the previous labours; whereas near the beginning of the first of those ten he wrote: So because Eunomius, though already twice overthrown in the previous discussion, does not yet permit truth to have its victory over falsehood but again struggles by literary production in the accustomed wrestling-booth of falsehood for a third time against true religion, strengthening himself for contests on behalf of error, the word of truth must now stand up through us for the overthrow of falsehood (Ibid., pp. 538, 540).
For the same Saint Gregory of Nyssa, whom we are presently discussing, said, in the seventh chapter of his Refutation of Eunomius (whose beginning goes: To want to help everybody was not, apparently): But I will reserve the discussion of doctrines to its due time. But now for the present let us observe what truth the man, who makes the accusation at the beginning that he is hated by unbelievers for speaking the truth, uses. For it will not perhaps be beside the point to learn through his extra-doctrinal discussions his attitude to truth and use this as an example in dealing with the doctrinal also. “For he who is faithful in little will also be faithful in much, and he who is unrighteous in little will also be unrighteous in much” (Luke 16:10) (Ibid., pp. 544, 546).
Gregory, wise in things divine, brother of Basil the Great and bishop of Nyssa, will confirm this in the second book Against Eunomius: ‘Therefore he indicates by the word the fearful manifestations of the judge at the end of the ages, when He will be seen no longer in “the form of the slave” but seated in grandeur on the throne of empire, worshipped by all the angels round him (Phil 2:7, 10). For this reason, He who came once for all into the world and was made “first born of the dead” (Col 1:15) of his “brothers” and “of all Creation” (Col. 1:15, 18; Rom 8:29) when he comes again into the world, He who (as prophecy says) “will judge the world in righteousness” (Acts 17:31) does not reject the title “first-born” which he accepted once for all on our behalf’ (Ibid, p. 534).
The point will become clearer if the father’s proof-text itself comes forward in evidence. He says, then: Similarly, he [Gregory] says these things also, expressing them in almost the same words, in the third book Against Eunomius (whose beginning goes: ‘But concerning the statement of the Apostle Peter, it is time to examine more studiously what was said’): ‘So that these things seem not to exist in the two on their own with any division; but by juncture with the Godhead, the temporal nature, being re-formed in accordance with the stronger nature, receives the Godhead’s power, as one might say that the mixture makes into sea a drop of vinegar mingled with the ocean, so that the natural operation of the latter mixture moisture no longer remains in the boundlessness of what contains it’ (Ibid., p.528).
Likewise Severus says, indeed, at the beginning of the tenth chapter of the same third book: But Gregory of Nyssa, wise in things divine, will confirm that he recognizes the immortal and uncreated nature, God the Father’s eternal and Only-begotten Word, as unchangeable and immutable in the same divine substance, and that he voluntarily took on the change involved in the passibility of the flesh which he united to him hypostatically. For he [Gregory] wrote in the fourth book Against Eunomius the impious: ‘So believing the immortal, impassible and uncreated nature to have been made in the passibility of the Creation and therein understanding change, how can we be condemned for saying that “he emptied himself” (Phil 2:8) by those who noise abroad their own argument in opposition to our doctrines?’ (Ibid., pp. 528, 530).
Listen to the same wise Gregory, who speaks as follows in the first book Against Eunomius the impious and explains the point to us: But let us consider the reasoning on this point more studiously. He says that a substance has been begotten, and that the name of the substance which has been begotten is ‘Son’ (CD vol. 35, p. 12).
Did not the doctor very wisely and very opportunely use the example for the clear demonstration of the point at issue, and consider it? Because, in combating Eunomius, he [Gregory] says, as follows, in the first book: For he has not done in this part the very thing he designed in many passages so that he could say that generacy (Syr. ܝܠܝܕܘܬܐ) is the substance itself; but here he acknowledges that the substance has been begotten, so that the hearers have a distinct idea of each word. For different ideas are created for the hearer of ‘generation’ and by the term ‘substance’. The argument will become clearer to us by illustrations. The Lord said in the Gospel that when her labour is at hand a woman is in pain but afterwards rejoices “in her happiness that a man has been born into the world” [John 16:21]. So, just as in this passage we have learned from the Gospel two distinct ideas: first, we have understood a generation by birth; secondly, the one who has come into existence by generation (for a man is not generation but by generation the man exists); so also here; since Eunomius has acknowledged that the substance was begotten, we have learned by the word ‘begotten’ the fact of being derived from something and by the word ‘substance’ we have understood a substrate possessing a derived hypostasis (Ibid., pp. 18, 20).
For we recollect wise Gregory of Nyssa who, in the 30th chapter of the refutation Against Eunomius (whose beginning is: It seems that the wish to benefit all) explains this point for us and defines it as no small danger neglectfully to abandon truth slandered by the evil-minded. He says: So if some impiety we should shun has become immediately obvious to everybody from what is said, and besides the impiety the baselessness of its design, it might be thought superfluous to make a detailed stand against each point. But because many, having adhered without examination to what has been said, “ere they perceive the thorns of the word” (to speak like the Psalmist) “have been swallowed up by wrath” (Job 5:5; 6:3; cf. Matt 13:15, 22, with Psalm 21:9), meaning that they would not have been swept away so much, as by a flood, into this depth of impiety, unless they had thought something in these arguments invincible and irresistible), it is wholly necessary that we should not surrender the truth through any negligence even though we need to rebut the argument by many words. So let us take up each point again (Ibid., p. 44).
Look at what wise Gregory, bishop of Nyssa, says on this point in the Refutation of Eunomius (its beginning is: To want to help everybody was not, apparently): For though the Church teaches us not to divide out faith into a plurality of substances but to believe there is no difference in the three prosōpa or hypostases qua being (Syr. ܫܘܚܠܦܐ ܒܗܿܝ ܕܐܝܬܘܗܝ ܢܗܿܝܡܢ ܒܬܠܬܐ ܦܖ̈ܨܘܦܐ ܘܩܢܘܡ̈ܐ ܘܠܐ ܕܝܢ ܚܕ), whereas our opponents posit difference and dissimilarity in the substances themselves, this fellow confidently decrees the unproved and unprovable by any argument, as if the ground for it had been prepared; perhaps, without so much as addressing attentive ears, otherwise he would have learned from intelligent listeners, that every argument which issues unproven by authority is old wives’ prattle, because it has no power to prove thereby the point at issue when no support for the statements made is introduced from the divine words or from human reasonings (Ibid., p. 108).
Therefore, let him listen to what wise Gregory, head of the see of Nyssa, said to Eunomius, a similar slanderer, in the Refutation (whose beginning is: To want to help everybody was not, apparently) as follows: For who would be so crazy or so out of his mind as to say ‘Father’ and ‘Son’, and again to suppose two ingenerates, and then think that the one had been begotten by the other? But what is the necessity thrusting his teachings into these suppositions? From what words of his has this been constructed so that the absurdity should be forced to crop up? For if he were alleging anything professed by us and then was bringing forward, whether by sophistry or with some sort of force, a proof for such a cavill, he might perhaps have had occasion for alleging such a thing for the slandering of our doctrines. But if there are not and will not be in the Church any such words, and none is convicted of saying them, none is proved to have heard them, and no necessity constructing this absurdity by way of some consequence is to be found. I do not understand what purpose this shadow-battle of his has (Ibid., pp. 124, 126).
Listen to wise Gregory of Nyssa, saying in the 20th chapter of his refutation Against Eunomius (whose beginning is: To want to help everybody was not, apparently) that this is a complete absurdity, as follows: But if, escaping from these absurdities he should call the activity, whose completion defines the Son, a non-subsistent thing, let him tell us again how what does not exist can follow “Him who is” [Exod 3:11; Rev 1:8], how, indeed, what does not subsist can effect what subsists. For it will be found that what do not exist will thereby follow God, indeed that what do not exist will be the causes of those that exist and that what do not subsist by their own nature will bound the nature of what subsists and that the power completing and making all Creation will be bounded by what does not, according to its own principle, exist. Such are the doctrines of the new theologian! (Ibid., p. 138).
Listen to the master of mysteries himself, who clearly explains these things to us through his plain words. For he [Gregory] says about Eunomius in the first book Against Eunomius (whose beginning is: There is a limit to him who “strives lawfully” [cf. Tim 2:5]): I will take up and repeat the sentence of his which I set down at the beginning. ‘We do not refuse’, he says, ‘also to call the Son, since he is begotten, “offspring”, the begotten substance itself and the title “Son” laying claim to such a relationship of terms’. So now let the critical hearer of these words remember this: by using ‘begotten substance’ of the Only-begotten he grants, by logical sequence, that we should use ‘unbegotten substance’ of the Father, so that, therefore, neither ingeneracy nor generacy will be understood as substance; but substance, on the one hand, and the fact that it was begotten or not begotten, on the other hand, are to be considered individually by means of the properties viewed in the substance (Ibid., pp. 194, 196).
For the same master of mysteries says, a little after the words set down earlier, as follows: for he is acting with malicious deceit in speaking of the generacy of the substance, in order to procure the mutual opposition of the substances sundered by generacy and ingeneracy into a difference of natures. The feebleness of the attempt is rebutted by the very means whereby the plot is set up. For one who says the substance has been begotten clearly defines generacy as being something other than substance, so as not to permit the meaning of generacy to be adapted to the concept of substance. For he has not done in this part the very thing he designed in many passages so that he could say that generacy is the substance itself; but here he acknowledges that the substance has been begotten, so that the hearers have a distinct idea of each word. For different ideas are created for the hearer of ‘has been begotten’ and by the term ‘substance’. The argument will become clearer to us by illustrations. The Lord said in the Gospel that when her labour is at hand a woman is in pain but afterwards rejoices in “her happiness that a man has been born into the world” [John 16:21]. So, just as in this passage we have learned from the Gospel two distinct ideas: first, we have understood a generation by birth; secondly, the one who has come into existence by generation (for a man is not generation but by generation the man exists); so also here, since Eunomius has acknowledged that the substance was begotten, we have learned by the word ‘begotten’ the fact of being derived from something and by the word ‘substance’ we have understood a substrate possessing a derived hypostasis (Ibid., pp. 204, 206).
But let us, please, look at the harshness of the noble and truth-loving writer’s grand criticisms of us. He wrote, then, immediately after his words just examined, about wise Gregory, as follows: For he says, “in between those words quoted by these admirable accusers, some which the agents of sacrilege have disregarded with a pricking conscience: ‘If, then, the meaning of “substance” is one thing and the term “generation” is established to mean something else, their sophistical tricks have collapsed all of a sudden, like earthenware pots thrown together and shattering one another. For it will no longer be open to them to carry over the ingenerate-generate distinction to the substance of Son and Father and simultaneously transfer the mutual conflict of the names to the realities”. …. For as the same wise father says of Eunomius: “The caviller’s trivial accusation becomes important advocacy of the defendant’s superiority” (Ibid., pp. 226, 228).
He [Damian] said, then: These words, which rebut their insanity and free the doctor [Gregory] from their calumny, they have left out. The doctor to explain them to us in a different way, teaches again a little later: ‘But because the substance of Adam and of Abel is characterized by the same properties, we must necessarily profess that there is one substance in the two but that those viewed in the same nature are different. For Adam and Abel, the two of them, are one in the concept of nature but have a mutual, unconfused distinction in the properties viewed in each of them’ (Ibid., pp. 248, 250).
But please let us examine ‘generation’ and see the real opinion of the doctor on the divine generation. He [Gregory] says, then, a little after the words we set down previously, as follows: ‘But because, amongst men, the term “father” has various conjoined meanings, to which the immortal nature is a stranger, we must leave aside all the material ideas entering in beside the corporeal meaning of “father” and have the impress of a God-befitting thought which signifies only genuine relationship with God the Father. So, because along with human fatherhood one always conceives not only of all that the flesh gives to be apprehended in the notion of a human father, but also a temporal idea, it would be as well to rid divine generation of the temporal idea as well as of the corporeal taint; so that with the material property being everywhere cleansed away, the transcendent generation may be pure not only of any idea of passion but also of any of temporality’ (Ibid., p. 250).
Therefore he [Gregory] writes in the first book Against Eunomius, after the words just now examined, as follows: So what we have been guided to learn of human nature (the same thing which has been proved by a train of argument) this, I think, is what ought to be taken as our guide to the exalted conception of divine doctrines as well. For having shaken off every carnal and material conception from the divine and exalted doctrines we shall have, through the conception that remains, secure guidance to the exalted and unapproachable, when that conception is purified of such things (Ibid., p. 264).
Taking up these words and pouring scorn upon them, the doctor, after a few lines, says: He repudiates a commonness of substance by a twofold argument and says: either there are two parallel ingenerate first principles, one of which we name ‘Father’ and the other ‘Son’, saying that “He who” is has been begotten by “Him who is” [Exod 3:11; Rev 1:8]; or, one and the same substance is understood as belonging to both, a substance which receives the names in turn, and is Father and becomes Son, being produced from itself by generation. And again: He says we conceive of two ingenerate substances. How can someone who accuses us of merging and muddling everything by professing a single substance, say this (Ibid., pp. 360, 362)?
What will he who affirms that a hypostasis is a collection of properties and indicative marks, and not the substrate they are collected to belong with, devise against these words? For we have now heard the doctor [Gregory] saying: for one who says ‘man’ has effected a vague understanding in the ear by the indefiniteness of the meaning, so that the nature is signified by the term whereas the reality itself, which subsists and is signified properly, is not indicated by the term. But one who says ‘Paul’ has shown that the nature subsists in the reality which is signified by the name. This then is the hypostasis: not the indefinite thought of the substance, which as a result of the generality of the object indicated, obtains no stability; but that thought which presents and delimits the common and unbounded in some reality, by means of the properties appearing on it. And again: For our mind must rest upon some substrate and have the impress of its clear marks and thus have imagination of the one loved. For if we had not conceived of the fatherhood or considered the one for whom this property was set aside, how could we have taken in the idea of God the Father (Ibid., pp. 376, 378)?
Gregory, his brother, wrote similar things to this in the fifth book of the treatise Against Eunomius (its beginning is: But because, he says, the word ‘Lord’) as follows: For when we say ‘this one was begotten’ or ‘was not begotten’, we are stamped with a twofold conception by the statement: by the demonstrative part of the sentence we look at the substrate; by ‘was begotten’ or ‘was not begotten’ we learn what is viewed as pertaining to the substrate. So that we understand one thing concerning the being, but another thing concerning what is viewed as pertaining to the being. Besides, along with each term used of the divine nature (e.g., ‘just’, ‘incorruptible’, ‘immortal’, ‘ingenerate’ and any other expression) ‘is’ has to be understood. Even if the word happens not to accompany the statement, all the same the speaker’s and the listener’s minds must complete the term by ‘is’; so that the title lands in a vacuum unless the ‘is’ be supplied. For instance (for it is better to present the argument using an example) when David says: “God the righteous judge, mighty and patient” [Ps 7:11], unless ‘is’ were understood along with each term used, the itemizing of titles unsupported by any substrate would be thought vacuous and baseless. But when ‘is’ is understood along with each term, the expressions altogether gain significance as they are viewed belonging with that which is. So just as by saying ‘he is judge’ we have conceived of as belonging with him a certain activity by means of judgement, yet we have cast our mind on the substrate by ‘is’, clearly being taught hereby not to suppose the concept of being the same as the activity; so also, as a result of saying ‘is generate’ or ‘is ingenerate’ we divide our understanding into a twofold conception, by ‘is’ conceiving of the substrate, but by ‘generate’ or ‘ingenerate’ apprehending either what belongs or does not belong to the substrate (Ibid., pp. 378, 380).
Only Eunomius, it would seem, who wrote this sort of riddle and concealed his mischief in a morass of darkness, could understand the obscurity of these phrases, Eunomius of whom wise Gregory of Nyssa says the following in the 23rd chapter of the Refutation of him (which begins: To want to help everybody was not, apparently): I suppose, then, that not even the writer himself would be able to say in simple terms what he meant when he wrote this. The meaning of what is said is so befouled in the mire of the diction that no one can easily recognize the intention for the mud of the explanation. For one would suppose that ‘come out to as great a difference as the works come out to’ belongs to a pagan word-twister, who talks nonsense to deceive the audience (Ibid., pp. 398, 400).
For wise Gregory of Nyssa wrote in the second book Against Eunomius the profane (its beginning is: But it is time that the explanation of the offspring’s nature): But let us leave this aside and, so far as possible, let care for the prior issues mollify our hearts which leap up with faith’s zeal against these great blasphemers. For how can we not be moved to hot indignation, when our God, our Lord, our Life-giver and our Saviour, is insulted by these little men? For had he been abusing my fleshly father or been at enmity with a benefactor of mine, could I have calmly borne his rage against my loved-ones? But if the Lord of my soul who caused it to subsist when it did not exist, and redeemed it when it was in bondage, who caused it to taste the present, and prepared for it a future life; who invites us into the kingdom, and counsels how we may flee the condemnation of Hell (to speak thus far of small things and not of things befitting the glory of our common Lord); who is worshipped by all the Creation of heavenly, earthly and sub-terrestrial beings; before whom stand numberless myriads of ministers in Heaven, and before whom bows whatever is governed by understanding and has a yearning for good; if he is exposed to abuse by men for whom it is not enough to make the lot of the Rebel only their own but who account it loss not to cast others too into the same pit with themselves through their writing, so that their descendants may not lack guides to destruction: will anyone censure anger at that (CD vol. 54, pp. 6, 8)?
See how Gregory, brother to the God-clad father Basil expounds this when he says the following in the 39th chapter of his Refutation of Eunomius (its beginning is: To want to help everybody was not apparently): But we ourselves shall in charity correct the error of his opinion by saying what we know of the matter. Names mean various things with us, Eunomius, and yield a different meaning in application to the transcendent power. For in all else, too, divine, is parted from human, nature by a large interval and experience discloses no such thing here as great as that which is thought on in similitudes and suppositions. Likewise also, even if there be a homonymity of things human with the eternal in what is signified by the names, nevertheless what are meant by the names are parted in proportion to the remoteness of the natures (Ibid., p. 30).
For by ‘concept’, as has been said, they are characterizing the nature, as Gregory of Nyssa has shown by saying ‘for the concept of “man” characterizes a man and that of “horse” a horse (Ibid., p. 52).
Wise Gregory too, Basil’s brother, taught us similar (indeed, to speak more truly, the very same) things in his book Against Eunomius (whose beginning is: There is a limit to the labours of those who “strive lawfully” in contests) writing as follows: So now let the critical hearer of those words remember this: by using ‘begotten substance’ of the Only-begotten he grants, by logical sequence, that we should use ‘unbegotten substance’ of the Father, so that, therefore, neither ingeneracy nor generacy will be understood as substance; but substance, on the one hand, and the fact it was begotten or not begotten, on the other hand, are to be considered individually by means of the properties viewed in the substance. And later: For one who says the substance has been begotten clearly defines generacy as being something other than substance, so as not to permit the meaning of generacy to be adapted to the concept of substance. For he has not done in this part the very thing he designed in many passages so that he could say that generacy is the substance itself; but here he acknowledges that the substance has been begotten so that the hearers have a distinct idea of each word. For different ideas are created for the hearer of ‘has been begotten’ and by the term ‘substance’. And again: If, then, the meaning of ‘substance’ is one thing and the term ‘generation’ is established to mean something else, their sophistical tricks have collapsed all of a sudden, like earthenware pots thrown together and shattering one another. For it will no longer be open to them to carry over the ingenerate-generate distinction to the substance of Son and Father and simultaneously transfer the mutual conflict of the names to the realities (Ibid., pp. 122, 124).
Similarly also in the second book (whose beginning is: But it is time that the explanation of the offspring’s nature) he [Gregory] rebuts the miscreant out of his own words, proving that generacy is not a substance and saying as follows: What does he mean when he says these things? For having distinguished the two terms from each other and made a corresponding verbal division in what they signify, he sets down each of them on its own and properly: one term ‘generation’; the other term ‘substance’. ‘The substance’, he says, ‘clearly being something other than generation, admits of generation’. For if generation were a substance (which is what he always rules so that the two terms may be mutually equivalent in meaning), he would not have said, ‘the substance admits of generation’; for that would have been the same as saying, ‘the substance admits of substance’ or ‘the generation admits of generation’, if substance were generation. Therefore, he understands generation as one thing and the substance admitting of generation as another; for what is received is not the same as the recipient (Ibid., pp. 124, 126).
Let us investigate again also his [Gregory’s] very wise words on this point in the 35th chapter of his Refutation of the same Eunomius (whose beginning is: To want to help everybody was not apparently), where he explains the issue more clearly and says as follows: For let us grant that it is allowable, according to the argument of our opponents, that ingeneracy is a substance and, again, likewise, admissible that generacy is a substance. In that case if anyone adheres to the meaning of the words, precisely the Manichean doctrine will be constructed by this path, because it pleased the Manichees to teach, by an opposition of natures, an opposition between evil and good, light and darkness, and all such things. And, I think, anyone who has not traversed the exposition in a superficial way will readily agree that what I am saying is true. But let us examine the point as follows. In each of the subjects are seen fitting indications whereby the property of the underlying nature is recognized, whether you are studying the differences between animals or anything else; for a tree and an animal are not characterized by the same things, nor are man’s signifying marks common to animals as against irrational nature; nor again, indeed, do the same things indicate life and death, but, as has been said, in all, generally, there is a pure and simple separation of subjects, unconfused, as it is, by any sharing of the indication appearing on them. This is the arrangement, by reference to which the argument of our opponents will be examined. They call ingeneracy a substance and likewise make generacy a substance. Now just as the indications of man and stone are different and not the same (for you would not give the same definition when defining what each of them is), so they will necessarily concede that the ingenerate God is recognized by certain marks whereas the generate God by different ones. In which case let us observe all the properties of ingenerate God which we have learned from divine Scripture to say about him and understand devoutly. What, then, are they? No Christian man, I think, is unaware that God is good, kindly, holy, just, pure, invisible, immortal, incapable of corruption change and alteration, powerful, wise, benefactor, Lord and judge, and all such things. Why, indeed, should we prolong discussion by dwelling on these undisputed matters? If, then, we perceive these things in the ingenerate nature, but ‘being generate’ is opposite in conception to ‘not being generate’, those who define ingeneracy and generacy as being ‘substance’ must, of necessity, assert that, according to the contrariety obtaining between ‘ingeneracy’ and ‘generacy’, the indicative marks of the begotten substance will also be contrary to those seen in the ingenerate nature. For if they say they are the same owing to the sameness in what appear on them, the otherness of the nature of the subjects will no longer be preserved; for we must necessarily suppose that the indications of things which are different are also different, whereas things which are alike in concept of substance are, it is clear, characterized by the same marks (Ibid., pp. 126, 128, 130).
It is this that wise Gregory of Nyssa teaches us when he subtly exposed Eunomius’ hidden, satanic and blasphemous abuse in the 15th chapter of his Refutation of the impious fellow (its beginning is: To want to help everybody was not apparently), as follows: But it will not perhaps be inopportune to investigate each of these by argument, to see what he means when he attributes to the Father’s substance alone the ‘highest and fullest sense’, not permitting the substance of Son or Holy Ghost to be high or in the full sense. For I think this is a device for totally denying the Only-begotten’s and the Spirit’s substance, by covertly contriving this verbal trick to make them seem to exist only in name, and the true acknowledgement of their subsistence to be negated by such a contrivance. And one can without difficulty discern that this is so, if one spends a little more time on the argument. It is not the part of one who thinks that the Only-begotten and the Holy Ghost truly exist in their own hypostases, to be over-particular about the acknowledgement of the names whereby he thinks he should honour the God over all; otherwise, it would be most insane, having assented to the reality, to be over-particular about the words. But as it is, by having attributed to the Father’s substance alone the ‘highest and fullest sense’, he has conceded, by silence over the others, that he thinks they do not subsist in the full sense. For how could he say that anything to which ‘being in the full sense’, is not attributed, truly exists? For in the case of what do not have ‘in the full sense’ attributed to them, we must necessarily assent to their contraries; for what does not ‘exist’ in the full sense, is entirely non-existent, in which case the claim of ‘not being in the full sense’ is proof of total non-existence. And after other things: but there is no doubt of this argument’s being advocacy of Jewish teaching professed by those who make only the Father’s substance subsist. It alone they affirm exists in the full sense, whereas they reckon that of Son and Spirit among the non-existent. For anything which does not exist in the full sense is spoken of as ‘existing’ only by a linguistic custom, just as someone seen in a portrait is named ‘a man’ whereas the one called ‘a man’ in the full sense is not the likeness but the archetype of the likeness; and the picture is ‘a man’ only in name, and therefore cannot be called in the full sense what it is called, because it is not by nature that which is named. And hence, then, if only the father’s substance is called ‘substance’ in the full sense, whereas that of Son and Spirit is not called that at all, what else is this but a clear denial of the saving message? Therefore, let them run from the Church to the Jewish synagogues, because they will not grant that the Son exists in the full sense and claim that he does not exist at all; for what is ‘not in the full sense’ is equivalent to ‘what does not exist’. And again: But if he professes the Son as subsisting as a substantial force in some way or other (for we will not still dispute over this), why does he again tear up what he has conceded, by claiming that he who is acknowledged as existing does not exist in the full sense, which is equivalent (as we have said) to his not existing at all? For just as someone to whom the name does not fully apply cannot be a man, and in the absence of a man’s properties the whole concept of his substance is negated as well, so too in the case of any reality, which does not have existence attributed to it completely and in the full sense, a partial admission of its being is no proof of its existence. However, this claim about its ‘not existing in the full sense’ is a device for the total abolition of its basis (Ibid., pp. 184, 186, 188, 190).
As wise Gregory, Basil the Great’s brother, instructs us in the 37th chapter of his Refutation of Eunomius (its beginning is: To want to help everybody was not apparently) by saying: For having heard ‘Father’ we at once understand the one who is the cause of everything’s existence, who, had he owned another cause transcending himself, would not be called ‘Father’ in the full sense of the word, because the appellation ‘Father’ (in the full sense) would have been attributed to the cause found to be prior. But if he is the cause of all and “all is from Him” [Rom 11:36]. as the Apostle says, obviously nothing can be found to pre-exist his being. And again, in the 38th chapter: And, here then, if there is another Father, conceived of in thought as prior to the Lord’s Father, those who pride themselves upon their inexpressible wisdom must demonstrate the point and then we shall agree that the idea of the ingenerate cannot be understood from the title ‘Father’. But if the primal Father has no prior cause underlying his subsistence, and the Only-begotten’s hypostasis is always also understood immediately ‘Father’ is heard, why do they terrify us with these technical tangles of sophisms (Ibid., pp. 200, 202)?
Therefore, on his having made these so wretched and irrational charges, he may be very justly and opportunely answered in the words wise Gregory wrote in reply to Eunomius, our author’s stay and mentor (and like him a misrepresenter and accuser of the fathers) in the 34th chapter of his Refutation (whose beginning is: To want to help everybody): But what is the necessity thrusting his teaching into such suppositions? From what words of his has this been constructed so that the absurdity should be forced to crop up? For if he were alleging anything professed by us and then there were forthcoming, whether by sophistry or with some sort of force, a proof for such a cavil, he might perhaps have had occasion for alleging such a thing for the slandering of our doctrines. But if there are not and will not be in the Church any such words, and none is convicted of saying them, none is proved to have heard them, and no necessity constructing this absurdity by way of some consequence is to be found. I do not understand what purpose this shadow-battle of his has. It is as if a mentally sick lunatic without a combatant were to fancy that someone was wrestling with him, and then, having made the effort to fling himself down, thinks that he has beaten his opponent. The clever writer has suffered some such fate, fabricating fancies unknown to us, and fighting the shadows he has formed with the imprint of his own notions (Ibid., pp. 276, 278).
For Gregory of Nyssa, as has been said, clearly testified that the property, or prosōpon, is one thing in its own concept, and the substance another thing, in the Discourses against Eunomius, when he said: ‘Clearly the teaching of true religion will be confirmed by the opponents’ claim, because they do not think ingeneracy is the same as substance but that it is viewed on the substrate, whereas the substrate is, in its own concept, something other than they’ (Ibid., p. 290).
What a torpor this is, says wise Gregory of Nyssa to Eunomius, what a stupor this is, that these tipsy topers suppose the ceiling is turning into the floor and that they have the ground over their heads! They cry out in protest that even the ground is unsteady, that the walls have run away, that the whole world is revolving and that nothing they can see is still! Perhaps, then, the author was writing with his soul in such turmoil that we ought to pity him for what he wrote rather than despise him (Ibid., pp. 292, 294).
For the doctor [Gregory], opposing thoroughly impious Eunomius, quoted a little phrase of Eunomius’ in the eighth book (whose beginning is: But let us hold on to the previously established points) and wrote: ‘Generation’, he says, ‘is separate from the ingenerate but joined to the Son’s substance’. Does this not suffice to prove the ignorance of the author’s mind? Who does not know that what can be separated from something and joined to something is first conceived of on its own, and in this way is joined to something else or separated from what it is joined to, for ‘joining’ is not predicated of a single item on its own. So because he called generation ‘separate from’ the Father ‘but joined to the son’s substance’, it is wholly necessary that what can be separated and joined should be seen entirely properly and on its own, for what does not exist and does not subsist is neither separated from anything nor joined to anything. But because he says ‘generation is joined to the Son’s substance’, he must view each of them on its own; for if he supposed the one was the same as the other, he would not have termed the identity ‘joining’, it being clear to everybody that the signification of ‘joining’ is not observable in the single item on its own but that the term indicates relationship with something else. In which case the substance seen on its own is one thing and the generation which is joined to this substance but separate, according to what he says, from the Father’s, is something other than it. But if generation is seen on its own by our opponents, it will be acknowledged, even by our adversaries, that the Only-begotten’s substance is something other than it. For what is joined to something is not the same as what it is joined to, and what is not the same must be other. So, if the concept of substance and that of generation are different, the heresy will be cancelled by the very things he says. For then the Only-begotten’s substance will not vary from the Father’s substance through the difference between ingeneracy and generacy, for it has been proved by our opponents themselves that generation is something other than substance, so that there will be no necessity for a relationship to exist between what are viewed in the substance and the one joined with it; but if generation exists on its own and again substance is understood on its own, an unique concept, with no participation with the other, will apply to each of them. For were someone to follow Eunomius in the examination of the thought now proposed by him, and return the attack, it would be possible for an equivalent argument to be applied to the Father too. For it will be legitimate to imitate his express words, as follows: by ingeneracy’s being separate from the Son but joined to the Father’s substance, the Son does indeed exist by generation and owes his being to the ingenerate, for he is begotten; for ingeneracy is not prior to the Father’s subsistence nor is the Father prior to his own ingeneracy, for he who does not have his existence by being begotten has existed without being begotten. Equally then, if, when someone says ‘ingeneracy is joined to the Father’s substance’, the argument follows in terms like those he has inferred of the Son, clearly the teaching of true religion will be confirmed by the opponents’ claim: because they do not think ingeneracy or generacy is the same as substance but that they are viewed on the substrate, whereas the substrate is, in its own concept, something other than they; since no difference is found there (because the difference between generacy and ingeneracy is separate from the substance), it will, of entire necessity, turn out that they can profess no variation of substance in the two. Let us, again, examine in addition to what has been said, this too: what it is that he means when he says that generation is separate from the Father. Does he understand it as being a substance or an activity? Now if he thinks it an ‘activity’, it must be connected equally with what is effected and what acts, just as in the case of every effect it is possible to see, both in regard to what is brought into existence and to the agent, the activity unseparated from the craftsman and viewed in the making of the products. But if he calls it a ‘substance’ separate from the Father’s substance, by professing the Lord as owing his existence to it he obviously regards it as occupying the place of Father to the Only-begotten, so that two Fathers are to be thought of for the Son: one who only bears the name, whom he also calls ‘ingenerate’, but who does not participate in generation; and one who effects in the Only-begotten what it belongs to the Father to effect: what he calls ‘generation’. And this will be rebutted more by Eunomius’ very own words than by ours. For he says in the subsequent words: ‘God by existing without generation is also prior to the begotten’; and a little later, ‘for he who owes his existence to generation did not exist before he was begotten’. Therefore, if generation is separate from the Father, whereas the Son owes his existence to his having been begotten, the Father himself will be inactive with regard to the Only-begotten’s hypostasis and separate from the generation to which the son owes his existence. So if the Father is alienated from the Son’s generation, either they are fabricating another Father of the Son by the term ‘generation’, or the clever fellows are, by their words, declaring the Son a self-begotten Son (Ibid., pp. 300, 302, 304, 306).
For Saint Gregory too, when he said: ingeneracy or generacy is not the same as substance but they are viewed on the substrate, whereas the substrate is, in its own concept, something other than they, did not say this on the ground that he recognized ingeneracy or generacy as in any way substance or substrate (Syr. ܐܘ ܗܿܘ ܕܣܝܡ ܝܠܝܕܘܬܐ ܐܘ ܠܝܠܝܕܘܬܐ ܠܐ ܐܘܣܝܐ) (Ibid., p. 326).
His namesake, wise Gregory who occupied the throne of Nyssa, wrote similar things to this in his second book Against Eunomius (its beginning is: But it is time that the explanation of the offspring’s nature) as follows: First let him rebut these words as false and then he will be believed when he speaks about those that follow, but, so long as the first point is unproven, it will be idle chatter to dwell upon secondary matters. And nobody is to retort to me that what we say should be confirmed by an argument, for the tradition coming to us from the fathers as a heritage by succession from the Apostles through the saints after them is sufficient proof of our case. But those who change doctrines by innovation need a good deal of help from their ratiocinations if they are going to persuade, not men blown about like dust but, people who are settled and constant in their minds (Ibid., pp. 388, 390).
Besides this, the wise words of the other Gregory (I mean of Nyssa) will teach us reverence and awe over divine doctrines, for when contending against detestable Eunomius and seeing him brazenly aspire to things not to be ventured upon, he said in the 30th chapter of his Refutation of Eunomius ( its beginning is: To want to help everybody was not, apparently) the following, after first setting down the blasphemer’s words, ‘The kind of similarity to be sought’, he says: by whom does he say it is be sought? What command, what scriptural law has made the search necessary? Does not wisdom clearly forbid search into matters too profound and enquiry into matters too difficult and being wise in inessentials? Paul says and testifies in the Lord to everybody who is on our side that we should “not think things higher than we ought to think” [cf. Rom 3:12], not because he despised wisdom but because he rejects our over-much extending ourselves through contemplating an enquiry into things incomprehensible. Isiah, more clearly than the rest, proclaims the impossibility of such an investigation, by calling his generation ineffable. Indeed, all the words of the divinely inspired Scripture which figuratively teach us “the mystery of godliness”, [1 Tim 3:16] lay down the law that we ought not to enquire about things incomprehensible. For what the divine teaching says is, as it were, a limit of our duties. So, by what necessity has he sought ‘the kind of similarity’, there being no saint who has counselled any concern for such things? For had it occurred to the prophets or patriarchs or the Lord’s disciples to give any consideration to these matters, it would not have been absurd for us too to be zealous for the same things in a like search for a similitude; although even so it would have been superfluous to search again into what has been searched into already, and we should have been right to stick by what was known before. But if the object of their concern seemed beyond even their comprehension and thus the search itself vain (their incapacity for the object of their search indicating its incomprehensibility), solicitude, therefore, in these matters is superfluous and useless in both cases, whether the object desired was sought by saints or unsought. For if anything useful had come about from this search, the saints, who exhort us to “enquire even into the deep things of God through the Spirit” [cf. 1 Cor 2:10], would not have disregarded these essentials. To whom after them, then, will be revealed what is too high for prophetic revelation and knowledge by the apostles? But I do know the necessity which constrains them to ask after such things. For, in my judgement, there is no other cause for such an investigation except their desire to convert the contentious to them by the outlandishness of their teaching. For had they held to the wonted doctrines of the fathers, in accordance with the teachings of the Gospel and the Apostles, they would have had no occasion for being known more than other people (Ibid., pp. 418, 420, 422).
For the same doctor [Gregory] taught this too, when he wrote as follows, in the first book Against Eunomius (its beginning is: There is a limit to the labours of those who “strive lawfully” [2 Tim 2:5b]): But if anybody were to demand an explanation and description of the divine substance, we should not deny that we are ignoramuses in such wisdom, and profess only so much: that it is impossible for the infinite in nature to be comprehended by any design of words, for prophecy calls out that there is no limit to divine grandeur, clearly proclaiming: “There is no bound to the glory of his greatness” [cf. Ephes 3:19]. But if the things belonging with him are infinite, much more is what he himself is in substance uncomprehended by boundary in any part. So, if an explanation by names and words limits the subject in meaning and the infinite cannot be limited, nobody can rightly find fault with our ignorance in not attempting what cannot be ventured upon. For by what name shall I comprehend the incomprehensible? What word shall I use to express the ineffable? So since God is too exalted and too sublime for signification by names, we have learned to honour what is beyond speech and understanding by silence, even if someone, thinking beyond what he ought to think, waxes hot against this soberness of speech, ridiculing this ignorance of ours with regard to things incomprehensible (I mean the absence of configuration, the infinity, the absence of size and volume in Father, Son and Holy Ghost), and recognizes difference by way of dissimilarity and produces this in rebuttal of our ignorance. And again: And therefore, we fix in ourselves the doctrine which has been made a laughing-stock, professing that we are too inferior in knowledge for things which transcend knowledge, and saying that we truly “worship what we know” [John 44:22]. Yet we do know the sublimity of the glory of him we worship, reckoning the incomparability of the grandeur by our incapacity to comprehend it by our reasonings (Ibid., pp. 424, 426).