Leibniz and the Proof of God’s Existence from Eternal Truths
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Proof of God from Eternal Truths: Invention, Eclipse, and Reactivation
2.1. Invention and Reception of the Proof: From Augustine to Valerianus Magnus
2.2. Reasons for a Certain Lack of Interest in This Proof
2.3. A Renewal Prepared by Descartes but Achieved by Malebranche
2.4. Diroys and Bossuet
3. Leibniz’s Reinvention of the Proof of God from Eternal Truths
3.1. Leibniz’s Initial Reservation
“This is to say that God did not make these things [the ideas of nine, the square and all things] by willing them, but by understanding them, and he understood them by existing. For if there were no God, all things would simply be impossible, the number nine and the square along with everything else. You see, then, that there are things of which God is the cause not by his will but by his existence”.
3.2. Opposition to Foucher
“Thus the nature of the circle with its properties is something which exists and is eternal, that is, there is some constant cause outside of us which makes everyone who thinks carefully about a circle discover the same thing”.
3.3. The First Explicit Formulations of the Proof (1677)
“since that truth is eternal or necessary, this reality that is in it, independent of our thought, will also be from all eternity. This reality is a certain thing existing in actuality. For this truth always subsists in actuality, objectively (a parte rei). Therefore, there is a necessary being, i.e., in whose essence there is existence”.
3.4. The Defects of the Proof and Its Link with the Ontological Proof
3.5. A Priori Proof by the Reality of Essences
“For the cause is the reason for the thing outside of the thing, i.e., the reason for the production of the thing; but the reason for the thing can be within the thing itself. And this applies in all things that are necessary, such as mathematical truths, which contain their reason within themselves; likewise God, who alone among actual things is the reason for his own existence”.
“[…] it must be the case that eternal truths have their existence in some absolutely or metaphysically necessary subject, that is, in God, through whom these truths, which otherwise would be imaginary, are realized, to use a barbarous but distinctive word”.
“For the divine essence is, as it were, the region of eternal truths, so that by God’s existence truths concerning non-existent possibles are realized, otherwise they would be deprived of subject and support”.
3.6. The Primacy of Reality over Possibility
“In fact, possibility is a (necessary) precondition of the reality of the possible: if, at any rate, the quite plausible assumption is made, first, that something has reality (something exists) only if it is intrinsically, or absolutely, or logically possible to begin with; and, second, that the absolutely impossible has no reality of any kind. In a word: being possible is a (necessary) precondition of possible being”.
“From the fact that eternal truths are ontologically grounded in the divine intellect, it need not at all follow that their truth is, therefore, also grounded (modally, that is) in God’s intellect. Were we to contend, in other words, that, if God did not exist, there would be no (such things as) eternal truths, meaning thereby that the reality of eternal truths is grounded (ontologically, that is) in God, we could hardly be taken to be suggesting, let alone implying, that the truth of eternal truths is also grounded (modally, that is) in God”.
“I agree that the idea of possibles necessarily presupposes the idea of the existence of a being who could produce the possible. But the idea of possibles does not presuppose the very existence of this being, as you seem to hold, Sir, by adding: if there were no such being, nothing would be possible. For it is sufficient for a being who could produce the thing to be possible, in order for the thing to be possible. Generally speaking, for a being to be possible, it is sufficient that its efficient cause be possible; I make an exception of the supreme efficient cause, which must actually exist. But this belongs to another chapter, that nothing would be possible if the necessary being did not exist. This is because the reality of possibles and of eternal truths must be founded upon something real and existent”.
4. Conclusion
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Letter to Electress Sophie, August 1696, Grua p. 379; Leibniz and the Two Sophies (2011), p. 123. |
2 | Proofs of God in Early Modern Europe 2018, p. xiii. |
3 | |
4 | See Monadology, § 45. |
5 | See Principles of Nature and Grace, § 8; Monadology, § 36–39. |
6 | See Monadology §§ 51–52, § 59. See also Considérations sur les principes de vie, et sur les natures plastiques, GP VI, pp. 541, 544; Éclaircissement sur les natures plastiques et les principes de vie et de mouvement, GP VI, p. 555. |
7 | See Principles of Nature and Grace, § 11. |
8 | See On Free Will, II, 6, 14; (Augustine of Hippo 2010, pp. 42–43). |
9 | See On Free Will, II, 7, 16; II, 8, 20; (Augustine of Hippo 2010, pp. 43–44, 46). |
10 | Ibid. |
11 | On Free Will, II, 8, 21; (Augustine of Hippo, pp. 46–47). On the non-sensible origin of the knowledge of numbers, see On Free Will, II, 8, 22; (Augustine of Hippo 2010, pp. 47–48). |
12 | See On Free Will, II, 10, 28–29; (Augustine of Hippo 2010, pp. 53–54). |
13 | On Free Will, II, 10, 29. |
14 | Ibid., II, 12, 33; (Augustine of Hippo 2010, p. 56). |
15 | “For our minds sometimes see more of the truth and sometimes less. And for this reason, they acknowledge themselves to be changeable. The truth, remaining in itself, neither increases when we see more of it nor decreases when we see less […]” (On Free Will, II, 12, 34; (Augustine of Hippo 2010, p. 57)). |
16 | On Free Will, II, 14, 38; (Augustine of Hippo 2010, p. 60). |
17 | On Free Will, II, 13, 36; (Augustine of Hippo 2010, p. 59). |
18 | See On Free Will, II, 15, 39; (Augustine of Hippo 2010, pp. 60–61). |
19 | In On true Religion (XXX–XXXI), Augustine repeats that the mind does not derive from itself the law by which it judges and reasons, but that it judges and reasons on the basis of an immutable law that is superior to it (the law of equality, resemblance, propriety). This immutable law or truth, which governs our reason but which our reason cannot judge, is identified with God himself. See also Confessions, XII, 25, 35; On christian Doctrine, I, 8. |
20 | See Soliloquies, I, 1, 3: “I call upon Thee, O God the Truth, in whom and by whom and through whom all those things are true which are true” (Augustine of Hippo 1948, p. 345). |
21 | See On Free Will, II, 13, 36. Note that the comparison of truth with sunlight is questionable, since divine truth is not only that which makes truths true, i.e., makes them truths, just as sunlight is that which makes external objects visible, it is also that which contains within itself all these truths—which cannot apply in the case of sunlight, which does not contain within itself the objects it illuminates. |
22 | On the Trinity, IX, 6, 9. |
23 | Ibid., IX, 7, 12; (Augustine of Hippo 2002, p. 34). |
24 | Soliloquies, II, 2, 2; (Augustine of Hippo 1948, p. 385). |
25 | See Monologion, ch. 18; On Truth, c. 1. |
26 | See On Truth, c. X and c. XIII. |
27 | Quaestiones in Genesim cum accurata textus explicatione, Paris, 1623, c. I, quaest. I, art. II, ratio IV, p. 35. |
28 | Itinerarium mentis in Deum, II, p. 9, in Works of Saint Bonaventure 1956, vol. II, p. 57 (translation modified). |
29 | Ibid. |
30 | Ibid. |
31 | Ibid.; Works of Saint Bonaventure 1956, vol. II, pp. 57–59 (translation modified) |
32 | See Itinerarium mentis in Deum, III, p. 4; Works of Saint Bonaventure 1956, vol. II, p. 69. |
33 | See Itinerarium mentis in Deum, III, p. 3; Works of Saint Bonaventure 1956, vol. II, p. 67. |
34 | See ibid. |
35 | De luce mentium, et ejus imagine, Antwerp, 1643, c. XVIII, p. 91. |
36 | Ibid., c. XIX, p. 97. |
37 | See ibid., c. XVIII, p. 92. |
38 | The existence of God can be proved by motion, by efficient cause, by the possible and the necessary, by “the gradation to be found in things “ and by consideration of “the governance of the world” (Summa Theologica, Ia, qu. 2, art. 3 co.; Aquinas 1911, pp. 24–27). |
39 | Thomas Aquinas probably comes closest to this in his Summa contra Gentiles, II, 84, n. 4. |
40 | See respectively Metaphysicae systema methodicum […]. Steinfurt, 1604, lib. IV, cap. II, quest. II, pp. 390–92; Tractatus theologicus de Deo […]. Steinfurt, 1610, Disp. I, pp. 3–7; Theologia naturalis. Frankfurt, 1615, Pars I, cap. II; L’athéisme convaincu: traité démontrant par raisons naturelles qu’il y a un Dieu. Orange, 1659, and Disputatio theologica, de existentia Dei. Geneva, 1661. |
41 | See respectively Institutionum metaphysicarum. Leiden, 1640, II, c. IV; Meletemata philosophica, maximam partem Metaphysica. Leiden, 1654, Disp. III, th. I. |
42 | See Theologia naturalis. Sive Entis increati et creati intra supremam abstractionem ex naturae lumine investigatio. Lyon, 1622. |
43 | See Section 2.4 below. |
44 | See Summa contra Gentiles, III, 47, n. 4–5. |
45 | Exodus, 33, 20. |
46 | Summa contra Gentiles, III, 47, n. 6; (Aquinas 1956, p. 160). |
47 | Summa contra Gentiles, III, 47, n. 6; (Aquinas 1956, p. 161). |
48 | “For it is because the actual thing exists or does not exist that the statement is said to be true or false, not because it is able itself to receive contraries” (Categories V, 4b 8–10). See (Picon 2014, p. 135). |
49 | This is the objection raised by Jakob Thomasius, who was Leibniz’s teacher in Leipzig, in Dilucidationes Stahlianae, in partem priorum Regularum Philosophicarum Danieli Stahlii. Leipzig, 1676, I, 6, p. 37. See (Picon 2014, p. 141). |
50 | See Section 3.5. |
51 | Pascal briefly mentions it in the Pensées, but only to note its uselessness without Jesus Christ. See Lafuma 449: «Though a man should be convinced that numerical proportions are immaterial truths, eternal and dependent on a first truth, in which they subsist, and which is called God, I should not think him far advanced towards his own salvation» (Pensées. The Provincial Letters (1941), p. 182). |
52 | See Meditations, III, AT VII, p. 45. |
53 | The proof by means of “simple view”, which assumes that God is immediately known without the intermediary of an idea, is expounded in Search after Truth starting from the consideration of the infinite (see III, II, VI; III, II, VII, § 2; VI, II, VI). |
54 | See Search after Truth, III, II, VI, p. 344; (Malebranche 1997, p. 234). |
55 | Search after Truth, III, II, VI, p. 342; (Malebranche 1997, p. 233. Translation modified). |
56 | Christian Conversations, I, p. 1134. |
57 | See Search after Truth, III, II, VI, p. 345; (Malebranche 1997, pp. 234–35). |
58 | Critique of the Search after Truth. Paris, 1675, p. 26. |
59 | Ibid. |
60 | Ibid. |
61 | See ibid., pp. 27–28, 30. |
62 | Ibid., p. 32. |
63 | Tenth Elucidation, p. 902; (Malebranche 1997, p. 613). |
64 | Tenth Elucidation, p. 903; (Malebranche 1997, p. 614). From now on, moral principles are not separated from eternal speculative truths. |
65 | See Tenth Elucidation, pp. 903–4; (Malebranche 1997, p. 614). |
66 | Tenth Elucidation, p. 904; (Malebranche 1997, p. 614). See also Dialogues on Metaphysics and Religion, VIII, art. XII. |
67 | Tenth Elucidation, p. 904; (Malebranche 1997, p. 614). |
68 | Thus “truths which are necessary by their nature, such as that 2 and 2 make 4, do not need a will from God to make them so” (preface to volume 2 of the Search after Truth (1675), in Œuvres II, Paris, Vrin, 1963, p. 489). |
69 | Ibid. pp. 486–87. |
70 | See Proofs and Prejudices (Preuves et préjugés pour la religion chrétienne et catholique, contre les fausses religions et l’athéisme). Paris, 1683, livre I, ch. VIII, p. 20; Proofs of God in Early Modern Europe (2018), p. 268. |
71 | In his 1675 preface, Malebranche criticizes Foucher for “confusing beings with truths”. We must bear this in mind: “Man is capable of reason and feeling; a ball can be cut into two hemispheres. Man and the ball are subject to change; but these truths are immutable” (Œuvres II, p. 490). |
72 | God is described as the “model” and, as it were, “original” of all things (see Proofs and Prejudices, p. 21; Proofs of God in Early Modern Europe (2018), p. 269). |
73 | Proofs and Prejudices, p. 21; Proofs of God in Early Modern Europe (2018), p. 269. |
74 | In Paris, under the title Introduction à la philosophie, ou de la connaissance de Dieu et de soi-même. |
75 | See Treatise on the Knowledge of God and of the Oneself (Traité de la connaissance de Dieu et de soi-même). Paris, 1856, pp. 147–50; Proofs of God in Early Modern Europe (2018), pp. 251–54. |
76 | “[…] it is not our knowledge which makes its objects, it rather supposes them”. (Treatise on the Knowledge of God and of the Oneself, p. 148; Proofs of God in Early Modern Europe (2018), p. 252). |
77 | Treatise on the Knowledge of God and of the Oneself, p. 147; Proofs of God in Early Modern Europe (2018), p. 251. |
78 | Treatise on the Knowledge of God and of the Oneself, p. 148; Proofs of God in Early Modern Europe (2018), p. 252. See also Bossuet, Logic, I, chap. XXXVI: “[…] as it is not the understanding that gives being to truth, but that, supposing it to be such, it only turns to it in order to perceive it, it follows that, were all created understanding destroyed, these truths would subsist immutably” (Traités de logique et de morale, Paris, 1858, p. 49). Fénelon, who was familiar with these texts by Bossuet, develops a very similar argument in his Demonstration of the Existence of God, I, II, § 52, Œuvres II, 1997, pp. 556–57. See also ibid., II, c. 4, § 49: “Even if I were no longer to think about the essences of things, their truth would not cease to be. It would still be true that nothingness does not think, that the same thing cannot both be and not be, that it is more perfect to be by oneself than to be by another. These general objects are immutable, and always exposed to anyone who has eyes. They may well lack spectators. But whether they are seen or not, they are always equally visible. These truths, always present to any eye open to see them, are therefore not that vile multitude of singular and changeable beings, which have not always been, and which only begin to be in order to be no more in some moments” (pp. 632–33). The first part of Fénelon’s Demonstration was probably written between 1701 and 1712, the second around 1687–1688 (see Gouhier 1977, pp. 130–31). |
79 | Treatise on the Knowledge of God and of the Oneself, p. 148; Proofs of God in Early Modern Europe (2018), p. 252. Emphasis added. |
80 | Ibid. Fénelon similarly declares that our ideas “subsist very really”. “One must therefore find in nature something existing and real that is my ideas, something that is within me and not me, that is superior to me, that is in me even when I don’t think about it, with whom I believe I am alone, as if I were only with myself, and finally, that is more present and more intimate than my own fund. This je ne sais quoi, so admirable, so familiar and so unknown, can only be God” (Demonstration of the Existence of God, II, c. 4, § 50, p. 633). See also John Norris, A metaphysical Essay toward the Demonstration of a God, from the Steddy and Immutable nature of Truth, in A Collection of Miscellanies, Oxford, 1687, especially sections V and VI, pp. 201–3. |
81 | Treatise on the Knowledge of God and of the Oneself, p. 150; Proofs of God in Early Modern Europe (2018), p. 253. |
82 | Conspectus demonstrationum catholicarum (1668–1669?), A VI, 1, p. 494; Leibniz on God and Religion (2016), pp. 22–23. |
83 | See A II, 1, p. 393. |
84 | De Religione Magnorum Virorum (early 1686-late 1687), A VI, 4-C, p. 2460. |
85 | On proof by movement and proof by creation, see (Rateau 2016, 2021). |
86 | Disputatio metaphysica de principio individui (1663), A VI, 1, p. 19: “Essentiae rerum non sunt aeternae nisi ut sunt in Deo”. |
87 | De Arte combinatoria (1666), § 83, A VI, 1, p. 199. |
88 | See Marii Nizolii de veris principiis et vera ratione philosophandi libri IV, Dissertatio praeliminaris, A VI, 2, p. 431; Philosophical Papers and Letters (1969), p. 129. |
89 | See Specimina juris III (1669), chap. I, Theoremata (4), A VI, 1, p. 373, where Leibniz explicitly refers to the controversies of the “Summulists” on the constancy of the subject. |
90 | Letter to Magnus Wedderkopf, May 1671, A II, 1, p. 186; Leibniz 2005, p. 3 (translation modified). |
91 | On this ambiguity that runs through Leibniz’s work, see (Newlands 2013, p. 171, note 43). |
92 | A VI, 3, p. 122; (Leibniz 2005, p. 43 (translation modified)). |
93 | See Section 3.6. |
94 | See Confession of a Philosopher (Confessio Philosophi), A VI, 3, p. 131; (Leibniz 2005, p. 65). |
95 | A II, 1, p. 186; (Leibniz 2005, p. 3 (translation modified)). |
96 | |
97 | See Von der Allmacht, § 10, A VI, 1, p. 540 (my translation). See also De Demonstratione possibilitatis Mysteriorum Eucharistiae (1671?), A VI, 1, p. 515: “[…] possible, i.e., clearly and distinctly intelligible”. |
98 | A VI, 2, p. 306. |
99 | Confession of a Philosopher, A VI, 3, p. 127; (Leibniz 2005, p. 55). |
100 | See, for example, Elements of True Piety (Elementa verae pietatis), A VI, 4-B, p. 1363 (Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 195); Dialogue between Theophilus and Polidore (1679), A VI, 4-C, p. 2232 (Leibniz on God and Religion (2016), pp. 130–31); A VI, 4-B, p. 1443 (Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), pp. 29–30); On the Radical Origin of Things (De rerum originatione radicali) (November 23, 1697), GP VII, p. 303 (Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 32). |
101 | A VI, 3, p. 312. |
102 | Letter to Foucher (1675), A II, 1, p. 387; Philosophical Papers and Letters (1969), p. 151. |
103 | Letter to Foucher (1675), A II, 1, p. 387; Philosophical Papers and Letters (1969), p. 151. |
104 | A VI, 3, p. 312. |
105 | See A VI, 3, p. 313. |
106 | A VI, 3, p. 312. |
107 | Ibid. |
108 | Ibid., p. 313. |
109 | Letter to Foucher (1675), A II, 1, pp. 387–88; Philosophical Papers and Letters (1969), p. 152. |
110 | Letter to Foucher (1675), A II, 1, p. 388; Philosophical Papers and Letters (1969), p. 152. |
111 | Mathematical objects–lines, surfaces, figures, etc.—which Foucher equated with fictions of the mind, are indeed “something real” (A VI, 3, p. 312). |
112 | See A VI, 4-A, pp. 17–19; Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), pp. 181–83. |
113 | A VI, 4-A, p. 17; Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 182 (translation modified). |
114 | A VI, 4-A, p. 17; Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 182. |
115 | See ibid. and A VI, 4-A, p. 19; Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 182. |
116 | A VI, 4-A, p. 17; Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 183. |
117 | A parte rei means “from the point of view of the thing”, i.e., “objectively”. |
118 | A VI, 4-A, p. 17; Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 183 (translation modified). |
119 | A VI, 4-A, p. 18; Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 181. |
120 | A VI, 4-A, p. 18; Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 181 (translation modified). Essences or natures, from which truths derive, are “some kind of always-existing realities” (A VI, 4-A, p. 19); Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 182. |
121 | Since the mid-1670s: see A VI, 3, pp. 462–63, 511, 579. |
122 | A II, 1, p. 588; Leibniz on God and Religion (2016), p. 56. |
123 | For detailed evidence, see A II, 1, pp. 588–89; Leibniz on God and Religion (2016), pp. 56–58. |
124 | In the New Essays on Human Understanding (IV, 11, § 13, A VI, 6, pp. 446–47), Leibniz argues that eternal truths are conditional rather than hypothetical. The difference lies in the fact that, in hypothetical propositions, the antecedent (if a figure has three sides…) and the consequent (… its angles are equal to two rights) do not have the same subject, whereas in conditional propositions the subject is identical (as in the proposition: any figure that has three sides will have three angles). From a strictly metaphysical point of view, however, this distinction is of little importance. |
125 | See A II, 1, p. 590. |
126 | Ibid.; Leibniz on God and Religion (2016), p. 59 (translation modified). |
127 | New Essays on Human Understanding, IV, 11, § 13, A VI, 6, p. 447. |
128 | See Remarks on the letter from Mr Arnauld (June 1686): “[…] there is no reason to doubt that God can form such a concept of him [sc. Adam], or rather that he finds it fully formed in the land (pays) of possibles, that is to say in his understanding” (A II, 2, p. 49; The Leibniz-Arnauld Correspondence (2016), p. 67). God’s mind is “the very region of ideas or truths” (A Specimen of Discoveries of the Admirable Secrets of Nature in General (Specimen inventorum de admirandis naturae generalis arcanis), 1688, A VI, 4-B, p. 1618). |
129 | See letter to Arnauld, July 14, 1686 (A II, 2, p. 78). |
130 | Wagner considers “metaphysical possibility” to be a “pure fiction” that can only exist in thought (conceptu) but “not in actuality or really”. Leibniz replies: “Metaphysical possibility, or of essences, would be a fiction if it were not founded in something really existing, namely in the first substance or monad, namely God”; “Essence is not a concept, nor always in relation to existing things” (A II, 3, p. 688). |
131 | “In every positive term, we conceive a subject, i.e., a thing, and an attribute, i.e., a mode of the thing” (A VI, 4-A, p. 388). Leibniz posits the equivalence between reality, positivity, essence and perfection (see, for example, A VI, 4-A, p. 556; A VI, 4-B, pp. 1429–1430; GP VII, p. 304; Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 33). |
132 | A VI, 4-B, p. 1635 (text dated between March and August 1689); Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 31. |
133 | A VI, 4-B, p. 1363; Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 195. |
134 | See On the Radical Origin of Things (1697), GP VII, p. 304; Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 33. |
135 | A Specimen of Discoveries of the Admirable Secrets of Nature in General, A VI, 4-B, p. 1618. See also A VI, 4-C, p. 1635. |
136 | See Stefano Di Bella, “Causa Sive Ratio. Univocity of Reason and Plurality of Causes in Leibniz” in M. Dascal (ed.), Leibniz: What Kind of Rationalist? Logic, Epistemology, and The Unity of Science, (Di Bella 2008, pp. 495–509). |
137 | A VI, 4-B, p. 1360; Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 192 (translation modified). |
138 | A VI, 4-C, p. 1635 (text dated between March and August 1689); Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 31 (translation modified). |
139 | On the Radical Origin of Things, GP VII, p. 305; Shorter Leibniz Texts (2006), p. 34. |
140 | GM III, p. 586. |
141 | “The reason for truths lies in the ideas of things, which are enveloped in the divine essence itself” (A Specimen of Discoveries of the Admirable Secrets of Nature in General, A VI, 4-B, p. 1618). |
142 | A II, 4, p. 352; Leibniz and the Two Sophies (2011), p. 337. Emphasis added. |
143 | GP VI, p. 226. |
144 | GP VI, p. 229. |
145 | See Theodicy, § 184, GP VI, p. 226. |
146 | See Grotius, De jure belli ac pacis, Paris, 1625, Proleg. XI. |
147 | See Theodicy, § 190. |
148 | “[…] this regard or relation of an existing substance to mere possibilities, cannot be anything other than the understanding which has the ideas of it” (Theodicy, § 7, GP VI, p. 106); eternal truths are said to constitute the internal object of the divine understanding, as if they were distinct from it (see also Theodicy, § 20 and GP III, p. 33). |
149 | |
150 | Gabriel Wagner argues that the other possible series of things are only in the mind and not in nature, and therefore that possibility is fictitious. Leibniz responds on the contrary that they are to be found in the divine mind “which is prior to nature (rerum natura)” (see A II, 3, p. 688). |
151 | Leibniz sometimes seems to distinguish God’s wisdom from his understanding, insofar as his wisdom does not simply embrace all the possible (contained in the understanding), but considers them individually and apart, evaluates and compares them, and then makes infinite combinations of them, i.e., worlds (see Theodicy, § 225). |
152 | See Critical Remarks concerning the General Part of Descartes’ Principles (Animadversiones in partem generalem Principiorum Cartesianorum), on article 7, GP IV, p. 357. |
153 | “The most general Partition of Truth is into Truth of the Thing and Truth of the understanding, or (according to the language of the Schools) Truth of the Object and Truth of the Subject” (Norris, A metaphysical Essay toward the Demonstration of a God, section II, p. 195). |
154 | See Monadology, § 45. It is even announced before the ontological proof. |
155 | Monadology, § 43. See also Theodicy, § 184; Causa Dei, § 8, GP VI, p. 440. |
156 | “It is true that an atheist can be a geometer. But if there were no God, there would be no object of Geometry” (Theodicy, § 184). |
157 | Dutens IV, 3, § 13, p. 273: “Interim uti atheus potest esse Geometra, ita atheus Jureconsultus esse posset, nec absurde statuit Grotius, intelligi jus naturae, etsi fingatur Deus non esse”. |
158 | |
159 | |
160 | Ibid., p. 208. |
161 | GP III, p. 572. |
162 | “It must be answered that eternal reasons are in the divine understanding, and therefore nothing is prior to God, but only that the divine intellection is, by nature, prior to the divine will” (letter to Bierling, 20 June 1712, GP VII, p. 507). |
163 | “Knowledge of reasons perfects us because it teaches us universal and eternal truths, which express the perfect Being” (Grua p. 580). |
164 | Grua p. 355. |
165 | I would like to express my gratitude to Lloyd Strickland, Justin Smith, François Duchesneau and the two reviewers of this paper for their helpful comments and suggestions. |
References
Primary Sources
Alsted, Johann Heinrich. 1615. Theologia Naturalis Exhibens Augustissimam Naturae Scholam. Franckfurt: Hummius.Anselm of Canterbury. 1946. Opera Omnia. Vol. I. Edited by Franciscus Salesius Schmitt. Edinburgh: Thomas Nelson and Sons.Augustine of Hippo. Opera omnia. Available online: www.augustinus.it/latino/index.htm (accessed on 5 January 2025).Augustine of Hippo. 1948. The Happy Life, Answer to Skeptics, Divine Providence and the Problem of Evil, Soliloquies. Writings of Saint Augustine, vol. 1. Translated by Ludwig Schopp, Denis J. Kavanagh, Robert P. Russell and Thomas F. Gilligan. New York: CIMA Publishing Co.Augustine of Hippo. 2002. On the Trinity. Books 8–15. Edited by Gareth B. Matthews. Translated by Stephen McKenna. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Augustine of Hippo. 2010. On the Free Choice of the Will, On Grace and Free Choice, and Other Writings. Edited and Translated by Peter King. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Bonaventure. 1956. Itinerarium Mentis in Deum. Works of Saint Bonaventure, vol. II. Translated by Philotheous Boehner. Saint Bonaventure: The Franciscan Institute Saint Bonaventure University.Bossuet, Jacques-Bénigne. 1856. Traité de la Connaissance de Dieu et de Soi-même. Edited by Émile Lefranc. Paris: Imprimerie et librairie classiques de J. Delalain.Bossuet, Jacques-Bénigne. 1858. Traités de Logique et de Morale. Paris: J. Lecoffre et Cie.Burgersdijk, Franco. 1640. Institutionum Metaphysicarum. Leiden: H. de Vogel.Derodon, David. 1659. L’athéisme Convaincu: Traité Démontrant par Raisons Naturelles qu’il y a un Dieu. Orange: O. de Varennes.Derodon, David. 1661. Disputatio Theologica, de Existentia Dei. Geneva: P. Chouët.Descartes, René. 1897–1913. Œuvres. 12 vols. Edited by Ch. Adam et P. Tannery. Paris: L. Cerf.Diroys, François. 1683. Preuves et Préjugés pour la Religion Chrétienne et Catholique, Contre les Fausses Religions et L’athéisme. Paris: E. Michallet.Fénelon, François de Salignac de La Mothe. 1997. Œuvres. Vol. 2. Paris: Gallimard, Bibliothèque de la Pléiade.Foucher, Simon. 1675. Critique de la Recherche de la Vérité, où L’on Examine en Même Temps une Partie des Principes de Mr Descartes. Paris: M. Coustelier.Grotius, Hugo. 1625. De Jure Belli ac Pacis. Paris: N. Buon.Heereboord, Adriaan. 1654. Meletemata Philosophica, Maximam Partem Metaphysica. Leiden: F. Moyard.Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 2005. Confessio Philosophi. Papers Concerning the Problem of Evil, 1671–1678. Edited and Translated by Robert C. Sleigh, Jr. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 2006. The Shorter Leibniz Texts. A Collection of New Translations. Edited and Translated by Lloyd Strickland. London and New York: Continuum International Publishing Group Ltd.Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 2016. Leibniz on God and Religion. A Reader. Translated and Edited by Lloyd Strickland. London and New York: Bloomsbury Academic.2011. Leibniz and the Two Sophies: The Philosophical Correspondence, Edited and Translated by Lloyd Strickland. New York and Toronto: Iter Press.2016. The Leibniz-Arnauld Correspondance. With Selections from the Correspondance with Ernst, Landgrave of Hessen-Rheinfels. Edited and Translated by Stephen Voss, New Haven and London: Yale University Press.Malebranche, Nicolas. 1958–1970. Œuvres Complètes. 21 vols. Edited by André Robinet. Paris: Vrin.Malebranche, Nicolas. 1979 and 1992. Œuvres. 2 vols. Edited by Geneviève Rodis-Lewis. Paris: Gallimard, Bibliothèque de la Pléiade.Malebranche, Nicolas. 1997. The Search after Truth. Edited and Translated by Thomas M. Lennon and Paul J. Olscamp. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Magnus Valerianus. 1643. De luce mentium, et Ejus Imagine. Antwerp: H. Verdussius.Mersenne, Marin. 1623. Quaestiones celeberrimae in Genesim cum Accurata Textus Explicatione. Paris: S. Cramoisy.Norris, John. 1687. A Collection of Miscellanies: Consisting of Poems, Essays, Discourses, and Letters. Oxford: J. Crosley.Pascal, Blaise. 1963. Œuvres Complètes. Edited by Louis Lafuma. Paris: Éditions du Seuil.Pascal, Blaise. 1941. Pensées. The Provincial Letters. Translated by William F. Trotter and Thomas M’Crie. New York: Random House, The Modern Library.Raynaud, Théophile. 1622. Theologia naturalis. Sive Entis Increati et Creati Intra Supremam Abstractionem ex Naturae Lumine Investigatio. Lyon: Sumpt. C. Landri.Thomas Aquinas. Opera omnia. Available online: www.corpusthomisticum.org/iopera.html (accessed on 5 January 2025).Thomas Aquinas. 1911. The “Summa Theologica” of St. Thomas Aquinas. Part I. Translated by Fathers of the English Dominican Province. London: R. & T. Washbourne Ltd.Thomas Aquinas. 1956. Summa Contra Gentiles. Book Three: Providence Part I. Translated by Vernon J. Bourke. New York: Image Books.Thomasius, Jakob. 1676. Dilucidationes Stahlianae, in Partem Priorum Regularum Philosophicarum Danieli Stahlii. Leipzig: G. H. Frommann.Timpler, Clemens. 1604. Metaphysicae Systema Methodicum […]. Steinfurt: T. Caesar.Vorstius, Conrad. 1610. Tractatus theologicus de Deo, Sive de Natura & Attributis Dei […]. Steinfurt: T. Caesar.Strickland, Lloyd. 2018. Proofs of God in Early Modern Europe. An Anthology. Waco: Baylor University Press.Secondary Sources
- Adams, Robert Merrihew. 1999. Leibniz: Determinist, Theist, Idealist. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Blumenfeld, David. 1995. Leibniz’s ontological and cosmological arguments. In The Cambridge Companion to Leibniz. Edited by Nicholas Jolley. Cambridge, New York and Melbourne: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Di Bella, Stefano. 2008. Causa Sive Ratio. Univocity of Reason and Plurality of Causes in Leibniz. In Leibniz: What Kind of Rationalist? Edited by Marcelo Dascal. Logic, Epistemology, and The Unity of Science 13. Dordrecht: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Gouhier, Henri. 1977. Fénelon Philosophe. Paris: Vrin. [Google Scholar]
- Jalabert, Jacques. 1960. Le Dieu de Leibniz. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. [Google Scholar]
- Lascano, Marcy P. 2018. Arguments for the existence of God. In The Routledge Companion to Seventeenth Century Philosophy. Edited by Daniel Kaufman. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Look, Brandon C. 2018. Arguments for the Existence of God. In The Oxford Handbook of Leibniz. Edited by Maria Rosa Antognazza. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Marion, Jean-Luc. 1985. De la création des vérités éternelles au principe de raison. Remarques sur l’anti-cartésianisme de Spinoza, Malebranche, Leibniz. Dix-Septième Siècle, 147. [Google Scholar]
- Mondadori, Fabrizio. 2014. ‘Il ne Faut Point dire avec Quelques Scotistes’: Leibniz on the Reality and the Possibility of the Possible. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, Studia Leibnitiana, vol. 46. [Google Scholar]
- Mormino, Gianfranco. 2005. La limitation originaire des créatures chez Leibniz. In La Monadologie de Leibniz: Genèse et Contexte. Edited by Pasini Enrico. Paris and Milano: Mimesis. [Google Scholar]
- Newlands, Samuel. 2013. Leibniz and the grounding of possibility. Philosophical Review 122: 155–87. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Picon, Marine. 2014. The ‘summulists’ disputes de constantia subjecti: The young Leibniz and his teachers on eternal truths and existence. Intellectual History Review 24: 135–51. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rateau, Paul. 2016. Les preuves leibniziennes de l’existence de Dieu: La “voie” du mouvement. Les Études Philosophiques PUF 118: 357–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rateau, Paul. 2019. Leibniz on the Problem of Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rateau, Paul. 2021. Démontrer Dieu: Leibniz et l’argument de la création continuée. Archives de Philosophie 84: 115–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Savage, Reginald Osburn. 1998. Real Alternatives: Leibniz’s Metaphysics of Choice. Dordrecht, Boston and London: Kluwer Academic Publishers. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Rateau, P. Leibniz and the Proof of God’s Existence from Eternal Truths. Religions 2025, 16, 123. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020123
Rateau P. Leibniz and the Proof of God’s Existence from Eternal Truths. Religions. 2025; 16(2):123. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020123
Chicago/Turabian StyleRateau, Paul. 2025. "Leibniz and the Proof of God’s Existence from Eternal Truths" Religions 16, no. 2: 123. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020123
APA StyleRateau, P. (2025). Leibniz and the Proof of God’s Existence from Eternal Truths. Religions, 16(2), 123. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020123