Leibniz and the Religion of the Mohammadans
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. What Did Leibniz Know of the Qur’an?
His encounters with the Islamic Orient were strictly textual. His knowledge of Islam was filtered through a European language. As far as we know, he never even met a Muslim. Nevertheless, he did comment on Islam (and the Arabic sources available in Europe at the time) and displayed a growing interest in it.
The book of Father Maracci, confessor of the late Pope Innocent XI, on the Alcoran, has just now appeared. This Father, who is of an order other than the Jesuits, has extensively read the Arab commentators on the Alcoran, and his goal is to teach us the true sense of this book that our Christian authors often take wrongly.(A I 8, 373)
I had already learned that in Padua they had prepared an edition of the alcoran in 2 volumes, in folio, and that the edition was made with the support of Cardinal Barbarigo. The diversity of manuscripts will not teach us anything, since never was a text less altered than this one, because the respect Musulmans had for their Law was greater than the Christians had for theirs, or because deception and animosity had from all times been attached to the purest belief.(Larroque to Leibniz, A I 9, 614)
There has been published in Rome, not the Koran itself, but Maracci’s observations on the Koran;5 he is a learned man, one versed in reading the Arabs, and his observations are taken not so much from the prejudices of the Christians as from the commentaries of the Muslims themselves. Ultimately I would like the entire Koran to appear with an accurate translation along with notes suitable for elucidating the meaning. But there are, I suppose, few people among us who are able to do such a thing. And I think that the Arabism of most is mediocre, although one-eyed people are rightly valued among the blind. For me there is no access to these studies because the occasion [to study them] was lacking in my youth.(Leibniz to Johann Reiske, 1693, A I 9, 426, cited in (Cook 2008, p. 179))
It is the fifth reading I have made of the Alcoran, and I do not find it as contemptible as does Mr Bochart;7 when one enters in the spirit, in the morals, and in the teaching of this people and of this century, one finds there a rather consistent system of morals and Theology, even though its foundations are vicious.(Nov. 1696. A II 3B, 239–40)
I am assured that Pope Innocent XI has blocked the edition of the good father Maracci, although he was his confessor, because he regarded his remarks as a kind of apology for the Alcoran, in which he showed that the commentators very often gave it a reasonable sense. The Arabs have had philosophers whose sentiments on divinity have been as elevated as the most sublime Christian philosophers could be. This can be known by the excellent book of the self-taught philosopher that M. Pococke has published in Arabic.(Leibniz to Claude Nicaise, March 1697, A II 3B, 274)
To know well the life of Mahomet, author of the religion of the Saracens, it will be necessary to consult the Arab Manuscripts, otherwise one runs the risk of being mistaken.
3. On Idolatry, the Trinity, and the Incarnation
we find Leibniz lamenting how the early church’s prohibition of images was overturned by the second Council of Nicaea. If the abuse of image-worship had been checked early on, remarks Leibniz, ‘Christianity would not have become reproachable [meprisable] in the Orient, and Mohammed would never have prevailed’.13
To come down to detail, there are some who, while teaching the Holy Trinity, go to Tritheism, by conceiving three completely distinct infinite substances, which have only a perfect agreement between them. But this is to lay oneself open to the Jews and to the Mohammedans and to overthrow natural religion, which teaches us that what makes and fills all cannot be three, and that the perfect substance, the source of beings, the ultimate reason of things, is unique. Everything beyond that is impossible and superfluous, and if there are three perfect and absolute substances, nothing stops there being an infinity of them. The Holy Trinity should be conceived as three principles in one and the same substance, which have an essential relation between them, without it being possible that there be more of them, and it should be compared with power, knowledge, and will: three principles of actions in a single intelligent substance which has to be able, to know, and to will; even though this comparison taken from our conceptions cannot be entirely accurate when it is related to God.
For neither the dogma of the Trinity nor that of the Incarnation greatly changes worship, because it is certain that we worship one God, the creator of heaven and earth, by himself and with principal latria.
4. Trinitarianism, Socianism, and Usury
I have read with pleasure and profit your Treatise, which draws a parallel between Mohammedans and Socinians, wherein you have shown a great deal of erudition and zeal. I am not surprised by the great progress of Mohammedanism. It is a kind of Deism, joined to the belief in some facts [faits], and to the observation of some practices, which Mohammed and his followers have added, sometimes quite inappropriately, to natural religion. We are obliged to that sect for the destruction of paganism in many parts of the world, and that would be one step to lead people towards the more sublime religion of Christianity, if ours was preached as it ought to be, and if the ill-founded prejudices of the Mohammedans did not put a great obstacle in the way.
As far as usury, condemned by the Mahometans, one could say that it is permitted to distribute profits among those to whom one lends in order to make a profit; but it is not at all just to burden miserable and poor persons who must borrow in order to live.
5. Engagement with Islamic Commentators
5.1. Leibniz’s Notes on Maimonides’ Guide to the Perplexed
According to this doctrine it is possible that a person be afflicted without having previously committed any sin, in order that his future reward may be increased; a view which is held by the Mu’tazilites, but is not supported by any Scriptural text.
5.2. Averroism: The Immortality of the Active Intellect and the Twofold Truth
- The human species is eternal (common assumption).
- Suppose the individual soul is immortal.
- Therefore,
- Individual souls must transmigrate (rejected by Aristotle)
- Or, if individual souls must be continually generated anew, and since the species is eternal, then there must be an actual infinity of souls (rejected by Aristotle).
- The rational part of the individual soul has two parts: passive intellect and active intellect (Aristotle).
- c.
- The passive intellect dies with the body of which it is the form (Aristotle).
- d.
- The active intellect becomes part of the universal soul (Averroist assumption).
- Therefore, the passive intellect is mortal while the active intellect is immortal.
6. Engagements with Islamic Theodicies
As Eric Ormsby has shown, every major strategy for reconciling reason with faith in the matter of evil was first introduced by the medieval Islamic theologians, whose discussion of the problem is, until Leibniz’s time, unsurpassed in thoroughness and detail.
6.1. Theodicy and Turkish Fate
The false conception of necessity, being applied in practice, has given rise to what I call Fatum Mahometanum, fate after the Turkish fashion, because it is said of the Turks that they do not shun danger or even abandon places infected with plague, owing to their use of such reasoning as that just recorded.
ended in a decision to do nothing: for (people would say) if what I ask is to happen it will happen even though I should do nothing; and if it is not to happen it will never happen, no matter what trouble I take to achieve it.
Do your duty and be content with that which shall come of it, not only because you cannot resist divine providence, or the nature of things (which may suffice for tranquility, but not for contentment), but also because you have to do with a good master.
The philosopher from Hanover probably ignored when giving that illustration that he was actually repeating a truncated oral narrative which is presented in different versions among which the most consistent is the following account of what happened once when the second caliph of Islam, Umar, was on an expedition in Syria: ‘On hearing that plague was raging in a particular town of Syria, Umar decided not to visit that place. In reply to abu Ubaydah ibn al-Jarrah, who had objected to his fleeing from a divinely ordained destiny, he said that Abd al-Rahman ibn Awf had told him that the holy Prophet had said; ‘If plague breaks out in a place, do not enter it, if you are not already inside it, but if you are, do not leave it’.
The school of theology known as the Mutazila was famously born out of the rationalist view that God’s Justice could only make sense if human beings have absolute free will. They were opposed by the partisans of predestination who emphasized God’s omnipotence and omniscience. This question of the true meaning of God’s decree and sentence has been ceaselessly debated before it simply amounted, at a period of decadence in Islamic thought, to the popular notion of مكتوب, ‘what is [already] written’ which conveyed resignation and irresponsibility.
Pure time is an organic whole in which the past is not left behind, but is moving along with, and operating in, the present. And the future is given to it not as lying before (my emphasis), yet to be traversed; it is given only in the sense that it is present in its nature as an open possibility. It is time regarded as an organic whole that the Qur’an describes as تقدیر, or the destiny—a word that has been so much misunderstood both in and outside the world of Islam.(Diagne 2010, p. 81, quoted from Iqbal 1986, p. 40)
6.2. Theodicy: Al-Razi and the Preponderance of Evil over Good
6.3. Theodicy: Al-Ghazali and the Best Possible World
- The perfect rightness of the actual: This follows from God’s wisdom. All that is actual has been decreed by God, and since God is most wise, the actual must be right and just. Notably, al-Ghazali does not say that this world is the best, but rather that it is ‘most wonderful’. As Ormsby says, ‘’most wonderful’ and ‘optimal’ are not equivalent. God may create, and does create, the less than perfect, but this is itself most wonderful’ (Ormsby 1984, p. 238). Nor is ‘most wonderful’ equivalent to perfect, since, for example, blindness in a human, normally a privation or an evil, is still most wonderful since, ‘divine wisdom requires it, be it perfect or imperfect’ (Ormsby 1984, p. 143). We do not know why God has decreed it, but we do know that since God has decreed it, it is most wise. We should not mistake this view to mean that God’s decree makes something most wise. Al-Ghazali is not a voluntarist but is enough of a rationalist to hold that God’s decrees are issued just because they are most wise. On possibility, as opposed to actuality, al-Ghazali says that possibility cannot be more wonderful (abda) than actuality, that is, more wonderful than ‘the form of this world or more excellent in arrangement or more complete in construction’ (Ormsby 1984, p. 35). With this aesthetic notion of ‘wonderful’, al-Ghazali may have wanted to ‘emphasize the startling and admirable artistry of the world order’ in distinction from the Mutazila’s conception of the optimum (al-aslah) as beneficial. In sum, we can say that the actual is perfect because it is wonderful.
- The radical contingency of the world: The world could have been completely different than it is. Every individual, action, and event could have been otherwise than it is. However, the way of the world is also necessary. That is, given God’s decree, which is a contingent choice for God, everything follows necessarily (unavoidably, but not geometrically) from that decree. But God does not simply issue arbitrary decrees—His decrees are always most wise, and we can know this because the actual world is a sure sign that it is superior to any possible world, just because it is actual rather than possible. But what does the divine wisdom aim for? Why did God decree such a world? The answer may be clarified by the third principle.
- The contribution of imperfection: Even though the world contains disease, destruction, vice, and whatever suffering, these evils and imperfections contribute to this most wonderful world by enabling us to perceive distinctions among phenomena, enabling us to have knowledge of phenomena. It also enables us to perceive perfection, most importantly God’s perfection, so that we may become more perfect ourselves. In the end, since God willed imperfection, it must be most wise. To deny this is to impugn God’s wisdom. In sum, we can say that God aims to produce a most wonderful world by means of including imperfection.
- Regarding the perfect rightness of the actual, Leibniz would say that the actual world is the best possible world. However, this is not equivalent to saying this world is unqualifiedly perfect, for Leibniz admits there is evil and that God permits it, although humans are responsible for moral evil. Nevertheless, Leibniz denies that a world containing less evil, sin, and suffering would be better (Leibniz [1710] 2007, p. 131). The best possible world is that combination of individuals that together comprise the most reality, despite their inherent imperfections.44 Imperfection is to be controlled and mitigated through the free exercise of moral virtue. Leibniz also says that God designs the world like a most efficient craftsman employing a single rule of perfection: the simplest means productive of the richest effects (Leibniz 2023, §5). In this, Leibniz and al-Ghazali have in common a rationalist viewpoint: the rules of wisdom morally necessitate the optimal, or best possible, world. In addition, both philosophers include a metaphysics of imperfection compatible with, if not ameliorative of, the best (or most wonderful) world.
- Leibniz would find al-Ghazali’s ‘radical contingency’ quite similar to his own conception of ‘hypothetical necessity’. Like al-Ghazali, Leibniz wants to avoid the strong necessitarian consequence in which God has no agency or freedom. Hypothetical necessity means that the series of events in the world are contingent in themselves, and theoretically could have been otherwise; but they are necessary (will not be otherwise) because they stem from God’s decree, which is itself contingent. But how can a decree be both contingent and necessary? The sense of necessity Leibniz employs in ‘hypothetical necessity’ is not geometric, in which God cannot choose another world without contradiction; or the ‘blind necessity’ of Spinoza, in which God has no intellect to choose which world to actualize.45 This necessity is, rather, a moral necessity, according to which God chooses the best possible world, even though God could have chosen to actualize a lesser world. While it would contradict God’s good nature not to actualize the best possible world, it would not be a logical contradiction. It is a choice that a supremely rational and good mind would certainly make, precisely because it is rational and good.
- On the contribution of imperfection: as already seen, Leibniz similarly permits imperfections, as they are built-in to the nature of created substances, but considers imperfections as compensated by a whole that is overall more perfect.
So, the limitation or original imperfection of creatures brings it about that even the best plan of the universe cannot admit more good, and cannot be exempted from certain evils, these, however, being only of such a kind as may tend towards a greater good. There are some disorders in the parts which wonderfully enhance the beauty of the whole, just as certain dissonances, appropriately used, render harmony more beautiful.
7. Conclusions
Later also Mahomet showed no divergence from the great dogmas of natural theology: his followers spread them abroad even among the most remote races of Asia and of Africa, whither Christianity had not been carried; and they abolished in many countries heathen superstitions which were contrary to the true doctrine of the unity of God and the immortality of souls.
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | (Almond 2006; Cook 1993, 2008; Strickland 2016). Translations in this paper belong to whomever is referenced. For the Academy edition (A), where no reference is given, the translation is mine. |
2 | In a letter to Wilhelm Ernst Tentzel, Leibniz expresses his wish ‘to enjoy the mysteries of the Arabs, despite being uninitiated in Arabic literature’ (1694, A I 11, 125). Cited in (Cook 2008, fn. 58). |
3 | For example, in the Justa Dissertatio (1672), Leibniz passingly refers to ‘the nonsense of the Alcoran’ (A IV 1, 335), but primarily for rhetorical effect, since he wrote the ‘Just Proposal’ to convince Louis XIV to invade Egypt as a strategy to undermine the Turkish Empire. See (Strickland 2016). |
4 | ‘I am not of those who believe that the Jews have corrupted the Hebrew text by malice and by design to foil the Christians. However, it may have been altered for other reasons’ (Leibniz to Larroque, June 1693, A I 9, 486). |
5 | In fact, Maracci’s edition, which appeared in 1698, included a Latin translation. |
6 | |
7 | Samuel Bochart, Huet’s teacher, died in 1667 without having completed his Latin translation of the Qur’an (A II 3B, 239, fn. on line 22). |
8 | The Academy provides bibliographic information on the two editions mentioned by Huet: A II 3B, 239. |
9 | Academy’s note to line 8 of the letter. Ibn Tufayl, d. 1185, Grenada, Spain. Tuyfal’s novel, Hayy ibn Yaqzan, (or translated from the Latin translation: The self-taught Philosopher, or the Epistle of Hayy ibn Yaqzan, in which it is shown how human reason can ascend from the lower to the higher) was well-known. Pococke gave Leibniz the Latin translation. In a letter to Albert Von Holten in 1672 Leibniz wrote approvingly of the novel for its depiction of an isolated man obtaining knowledge of all things through reason and experience rather than from the learned (see A II 1A, 325). |
10 | ‘De Cultu Sanctorum’, A IV 6, 673–681, unpublished translation by Lloyd Strickland, forthcoming 2026. |
11 | ‘Indeed, Allah does not forgive associating others with Him in worship, but forgives anything else of whoever He wills. And whoever associates others with Allah has indeed committed a grave sin’ (Surah An-Nisa, 4: 48). ‘Associating’ is another word for idolizing. Prohibitions against idolatry are also found in Sura Al-An’am, 6: 121, and in the Hadith 7:732:838. |
12 | For example, the second (or first) of the Ten Commandments: ‘thou shalt not make unto thee any graven image’ (Exodus 20: 3). New Testament: ‘Claiming to be wise, they became fools, and exchanged the glory of the immortal God for images resembling mortal man and birds and animals and creeping things’ (Romans 1: 22–23). |
13 | Cited in (Almond 2006, p. 475): Leibniz to Bossuet, March 1693, A I 9, 85–86. |
14 | Cited in (Almond 2006, p. 475): Leibniz to de Brinon, February 1695, A I 11, 295. |
15 | Also, ‘O People of the Book! Do not go to extremes regarding your faith; say nothing about Allah except the truth. The Messiah, Jesus, son of Mary, was no more than a messenger of Allah and the fulfilment of His Word through Mary and a spirit created by a command from Him. So believe in Allah and His messengers and do not say, ‘Trinity’. Stop!—for your own good. Allah is only One God. Glory be to Him! He is far above having a son!’ (Quran 2024, 4: 171). |
16 | ‘One has to be very reckless and extravagant to treat as spurious those passages of the Koran which speak honourably of Jesus Christ’ (Leibniz 2016, p. 342). |
17 | For details on Leibniz’s trinitarianism see (Antognazza 2001). |
18 | Leibniz’s letter, printed in La Croze’s Dissertations historiques sur divers sujets pp. 164–81, is titled ‘Letter of Mister Leibniz to the author of the Reflections on the Origin of Mahometism’. The letter is translated in (Leibniz 2016, pp. 337–44). |
19 | Socinianism was a Protestant Reformation movement of the 16–17th centuries, founded by Lelio Sozzi and his nephew Fausto Sozzi, which rejected a number of mainstream theological doctrines such as the Trinity, the pre-existence of Christ, the Incarnation, original sin, and pre-destination. |
20 | For reference: (Quran 2024, 2: 275): ‘Those who consume interest will stand on Judgment Day like those driven to madness by Satan’s touch. That is because they say, ‘trade is no different than interest’. But Allah has permitted trading and forbidden interest’. |
21 | Leibniz had already set down a similar version of this law in his Elementa Juris Naturalis of 1669–71: ‘The just is my advantage not connected with the disadvantage of another. Unjust is my advantage connected with the disadvantage of another’ (Justum est lucrum meum cum non lucro alieno and Inustum est lucrum meum cum damno alieno) (A VI 1, 433). |
22 | For example, (Quran 2024, 25: 2): ‘[Allah] has created everything, ordaining it precisely’. 37: 96–7: ‘How can you worship what you carve with your own hands, when it is Allah Who created you and whatever you do?’ |
23 | Cook 2008, 174. Maimonides composed the Guide c. 1185–1190 in Classical Arabic but using Hebrew script. |
24 | Leibniz’s notes are based on John Buxtorf’s 1629 Latin translation of the Guide. The Akademie dates Leibniz’s notes as 1677 to 1716 (A VI 4, No. 424). Strickland argues that Leibniz probably did not read the Guide until after 1707 (Strickland 2023, p. 361). |
25 | (Leibniz 2023, §23). Just as the idea of ‘greatest’ contradicts the idea of ‘number’, the idea of greatest contradicts the idea of ‘speed’. |
26 | As noted above in Suras 25:2 and 37:96–7. |
27 | Leibniz’s Latin is ‘legis nostrae’. |
28 | (Hilliger 2022, p. 154), but thanks to Lloyd Strickland for help with the Latin. |
29 | Also known as Ibn Rush, 1126–1198. |
30 | ‘For it is memory, or the knowledge of this me, which renders it subject to punishment and reward. Thus the immortality that one expects in morals and religion consists not merely in this perpetual subsistence, common to all substances; for without the memory of what one has been, it would have nothing to desire’ (Leibniz 2023, §34). |
31 | In ‘The Decisive Treatise’ Averroes (Ibn Rushd) says that ‘demonstrative truth and scriptural truth cannot conflict’ (McGinnis and Reisman 2007, p. 313). However, it is not the case that both must be taken to be true; rather, ‘If the apparent meaning of Scripture conflicts with demonstrative conclusions it must be interpreted allegorically, that is, metaphorically’ (McGinnis and Reisman 2007, p. 313). This may imply that what cannot be in conflict is the demonstrative truth and the allegorical meaning or significance. For background on the Averroists and the two-fold truth, see (Brown 2010). |
32 | In ‘Preliminary Dissertation on the Conformity of Faith and Reason’. |
33 | Timaeus, 29a-30, perhaps especially: ‘God desired that all things should be good and nothing bad, so far as this was attainable’ (Plato 1961, line 30a). |
34 | In (Leibniz 2023, §4), Leibniz refers to this argument as the ‘lazy reason’ (logon ergon) sophism. |
35 | Cicero gives Chrysippus’ version of the ‘lazy argument’ as well as Chrysippus’ rejection of it based on ‘co-fated events’ (Long and Sedley 1987, pp. 339–40). But Carneades rejects the lazy argument entirely and Chrysippus’ rejection implicitly by maintaining it is false that there is nothing in our power (Long and Sedley 1987, p. 464). |
36 | This argument reflects the ‘problem of future contingents’ which originated with Aristotle in On Interpretation Ch. 9. |
37 | ‘These philosophers were not far removed from the teaching of our Lord, who deprecates these anxieties in regard to the morrow, comparing them with the needless trouble a man would give himself in labouring to increase his stature’ (Leibniz [1710] 2007, Preface, p. 56). Leibniz is likely referring to: ‘Take therefore no thought for the morrow: for the morrow shall take thought for the things of itself. Sufficient unto the day is the evil thereof’ (Matthew 6:34). |
38 | 1877–1938, doctorate in Philosophy from Cambridge, thesis on The Development of Metaphysics in Persia. |
39 | Strickland (Hilliger 2022, p. 8) points out that in Theodicy Leibniz is not quoting Maimonides from the Guide itself, but rather from the second edition, 1702, of Bayle’s Dictionary. |
40 | Abu Bakr Muhammad ibn Zakariya al-Razi, alternatively ‘ar-Razi’ (865–925 CE) Persian physician and philosopher, whose work, Sepher Elohuth, or Theosophy, Maimonides cites in (Maimonides 2002, p. 267). Leibniz does not appear to know anything about al-Razi other than what he read in the Guide. |
41 | Born in Tus, Iran in 1058; died there in 1111. |
42 | This paragraph is based on Ormsby’s introduction. |
43 | According to (Ormsby 1984, pp. 259–61), except where noted. |
44 | ‘As soon as God has decreed to create something there is a struggle between all the possibles, all of them laying claim to existence, and that those which, being united, produce most reality, most perfection, most significance carry the day. It is true that all this struggle can only be ideal, that is to say, it can only be a conflict of reasons in the most perfect understanding, which cannot fail to act in the most perfect way, and consequently to choose the best. Yet God is bound by a moral necessity, to make things in such a manner that there can be nothing better’ (Leibniz [1710] 2007, p. 256). |
45 | ‘And this [absolute] deduction holds among the eternal truths such as those of Geometry; the other is necessary only ex hypothesi, and so to speak by accident, but it is contingent in itself, when the contrary does not imply [contradiction]’ (Leibniz 2023, §13). |
References
- Acevedo, Gabriel. 2008. Islamic Fatalism and the Clash of Civilizations: An Appraisal of a Contentious and Dubious Theory. Social Forces 86: 1711–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Almond, Ian. 2006. Leibniz, Historicism, and the ‘Plague of Islam’. Eighteenth-Century Studies 39: 463–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Antognazza, Maria Rosa. 2001. Leibniz de Deo Trino: Philosophical Aspects of Leibniz’s conception of the Trinity. Religious Studies 37: 1–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Antognazza, Maria Rosa. 2007. Leibniz on the Trinity and the Incarnation. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Brown, Stuart. 2010. Christian Averroism, Fideism, and the “Two-fold” Truth. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 25: 207–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cook, Daniel J. 1993. Leibniz’s use and abuse of Judaism and Islam. In Leibniz and Adam. Edited by Marcelo Dascal and Elhanan Yakira. Tel Aviv: University Publishing Projects Ltd., pp. 283–97. [Google Scholar]
- Cook, Daniel J. 2008. Leibniz and Orientalism. Studia Leibnitiana 40: 168–90. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cornell, Vincent J. 1999. Fruit of the Tree of Knowledge: The Relationship Between Faith and Practice in Islam. In The Oxford History of Islam. Edited by John L. Esposito. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 63–105. [Google Scholar]
- Cunningham, William. 1863. The Works of William Cunningham, D.D. Vol. 3; Historical Theology. London: Hamilton, Adams & Co. [Google Scholar]
- Diagne, Souleymane Bachir. 2010. De fato mahometano: Leibniz and Muhammad Iqbal on Islamic fatalism. Diogenes 226: 75–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gerhardt, Carl Immanuel. 1875–1890. Die Philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. 7 vols. Berlin: Weidmann, Cited by volume and page. [Google Scholar]
- Hilliger, Walter. 2022. Leibniz’s Anthology of Maimonides’ Guide. Translated and Annotated by Walter Hilliger. New York: Shehakol Inc. [Google Scholar]
- Iqbal, Muhammad. 1986. The Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam. Edited by Saeed Sheikh. Lahore: Institute of Islamic Culture. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, Gottfried. 1996. New Essays on Human Understanding. Translated and Edited by Peter Remnant and Jonathan Bennett. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. First published 1765. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, Gottfried. 2023. Leibniz’s Discourse on Metaphysics, a New Translation and Commentary. Translated and Edited by Christopher Johns. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1923. Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe. Edited by Berlin-Brandenburgische Akademie der Wissenschaften. 8 Series, Each Divided into Multiple Volumes. Berlin: Akademie Verlag, Cited by A, series, volume, page number. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 2007. Theodicy: Essays on the Goodness of God, the Freedom of Man and the Origin of Evil. Translated and edited by E. M. Huggard. Charleston: BiblioBazaar. First published 1710. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 2011. Leibniz and the Two Sophies: The Philosophical Correspondence. Edited and Translated by Lloyd Strickland. Toronto: Iter Inc. Center for Reformation and Renaissance Studies. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 2016. Leibniz: On God and Religion: A Reader. Edited and Translated by Lloyd Strickland. London: Bloomsbury. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 2026. On the Worship of Saints. In Religion and Theology 1677–1686. Edited by Lloyd Strickland. Oxford: Oxford University Press, (forthcoming). [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, and Samuel Clarke. 2000. G. W. Leibniz and Samuel Clarke: Correspondence. Edited and Translated by Roger Ariew. Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Long, Anthony A., and David N. Sedley. 1987. The Hellenistic Philosophers. Edited by Anthony Arthur Long and David Sedley. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Maimonides, Moses. 2002. Guide for the Perplexed, 2nd ed. Translated by M. Friedländer. Skokie: Varda Books. [Google Scholar]
- McGinnis, John, and David C. Reisman, ed. and trans. 2007. Classical Arabic Philosophy: An Anthology of Sources. Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Ormsby, Eric Linn. 1984. Theodicy in Islamic Thought: The Dispute over Al-Ghazali’s Best of All Possible Worlds. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. 1961. The Collected Dialogues of Plato. Edited by Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns. Timaeus. Translated by Benjamin Jowett. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Quran. 2024. Available online: https://quran.com (accessed on 15 July 2024).
- Strickland, Lloyd. 2016. Leibniz’s Egypt Plan (1671–1672): From holy war to ecumenism. Intellectual History Review 26: 461–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Strickland, Lloyd. 2023. When did Leibniz Read Maimonides? Paper presented at Vorträge des XI Internationalen Leibniz Kongresses, Hannover, Germany, July 31–August 4; Herausgegeben von Wenchao Li, Charlotte Wahl, Sven Erdner, Bianca Carina Schwartz, und Yue Dan. Band 3. pp. 361–67. [Google Scholar]
- Varani, Giovanna. 2008. Leibniz und der Islam: Die Betrachtung des Korans als erster Ansatz zu einer Kulturbegegnung im 17. und 18. Jahrhundert. Studia Leibnitiana 40: 48–71. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wilson, Catherine. 1989. Leibniz’s Metaphysics: A Historical and Comparative Study. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Johns, C. Leibniz and the Religion of the Mohammadans. Religions 2024, 15, 1087. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15091087
Johns C. Leibniz and the Religion of the Mohammadans. Religions. 2024; 15(9):1087. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15091087
Chicago/Turabian StyleJohns, Christopher. 2024. "Leibniz and the Religion of the Mohammadans" Religions 15, no. 9: 1087. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15091087
APA StyleJohns, C. (2024). Leibniz and the Religion of the Mohammadans. Religions, 15(9), 1087. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15091087