Unity in Reason: Mendelssohn on the Conflict between Common Sense and Speculation
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Common Sense and Wakefulness
Truthfully, this rule also tends to serve me as the right guide when I am awake. Whenever my speculation seems to lead me too far from the main street of common sense, I stand still and seek to orient myself. I look at the point from which I started out and try to compare my two guides. Experience has taught me that in most cases common sense tends to be right and reason must speak very decisively for speculation if I am to leave common sense and follow speculation […].
3. Speculative Reason and the Step into Existence
If we could be persuaded that the supreme intellect exhibited to itself the things outside of us as actual objects, then our assurance of their existence would have attained the highest degree of evidence and there would be no further increase that it might undergo […] If we shall have convinced ourselves of the existence of the supreme being and its properties, then a way will also present itself of making for ourselves some concept of the infinity of the supreme being’s knowledge and from this truth, along with several others, perhaps in a scientific, demonstrative manner, of refuting the pretensions of the idealists and of proving irrefutably the actual existence of a sensory world outside us.
4. Approval-Drive and Logic of Creation
The aim of the power of approving is to bring forth the object, to strive to bring the object of the representation to actuality, in keeping with the standard of the ideal. The power of the self-sufficient being will thus bring forth these limited degrees of its perfection and their best possible combination, not in himself since they are not compatible with his properties but outside himself as limited substances, subsisting for themselves, each with that alteration in place and space, by means of which they are the best in relation to the whole. God is the creator and sustainer of the best universe. One sees here the transition from God’s intellect to his property as creator and sustainer of things outside him. Representation, combined with approval or participation, is vital knowledge and vital knowledge in the highest degree is the spur to activity, the striving to bring forth, to express power.
The same combination of things in which the matter as an object of representation is actually on hand must be necessarily more perfect than one in which the [represented] sensory make-ups have externally no object. In the latter there is merely harmony in thinking beings’ representations insofar as they are depictions and contain truth; in the former, by contrast, the thinking beings’ representations agree not only among themselves but also with an object that is actually to be found outside them, an object that is the prototype for their pictorial representations. In the former case, depiction agrees only with depiction; in the latter, by contrast, copy also agrees with prototype. Greater agreement is greater perfection; a world in which matter is to be encountered outside minds is more perfect than one that consists merely of minds. Since then God brings only the most perfect to actuality, the world that he has created will not be merely ideal but will also actually contain matter, just as the greatest harmony demands.
5. Concluding Remarks
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Hereafter, I will refer to Mendelssohn (1971) whenever I quote Morning Hours, accompanied by the usual abbreviation JubA 3.2 and the pagination. |
2 | |
3 | For a critique of the interpretation that Mendelssohn’s favoring of common sense arose from a gradual disenchantment with metaphysical speculation, see Freudenthal (2012). |
4 | |
5 | Freudenthal (2012, p. 31) aptly speaks of “refinement” and “systematization”. |
6 | The rule reappears in An die Freunde Lessings (Mendelssohn 1971, JubA 3.2, p. 198). |
7 | Among these “deniers of God”, Mendelssohn mentions Epicurus and Lucretius among the ancients, and Helvétius and Hume among the moderns (Mendelssohn 1983, p. 95). |
8 | See An die Freunde Lessings (Mendelssohn 1971, JubA 3.2, p. 197): “Zwar bin ich ein großer Verehrer der Demonstrationen in der Metaphysik, und fest überzeugt, daß die Hauptwahrheiten der natürlichen Religion so apodiktisch erweislich sind, als irgend ein Satz in der Größenlehre. Gleichwohl aber hängt selbst meine Ueberzeugung von Religionswahrheiten nicht so schlechterdings von metaphysischen Argumentationen ab, daß sie mit denselben sehen und fallen müßte. Man kann mir wider meine Argumente Zweifel erregen, mir in denselben Schlußfehler zeigen, und meine Ueberzeugung bleibt dennoch unerschütterlich.” |
9 | In his Rêveries du promeneur solitaire, written between 1776 and 1778, Rousseau similarly argues against those who, with subtle arguments, question his certainty of God’s existence and of the soul’s immortality—pristine certainties firmly rooted in our hearts (Rousseau 2012, pp. 66–67): “Elles m’ont inquiété quelquefois mais ells ne m’ont jamais ébranlé. Je me suis toujours dit: tout cela ne sont que des arguties et des subtilités métaphysiques qui ne sont d’aucun poids auprès des principes fondamentaux adoptés para ma raison, confirmés par mon cœur, et qui tous portent le sceau de l’assentiment intérieur dans le silence des passions […] Non, de vaines argumentations ne détruiront jamais la convenance que j’aperçois entre ma nature immortelle et la constitution de ce monde et l’ordre physique que j’y vois régner.” |
10 | |
11 | A concise summary of Strauss’ position on this matter can be found in Arkush (1994, pp. 86–88). |
12 | See, for instance, Mendelssohn (1971, JubA 3.2, p. 79; 2011, p. 57): “Metaphysicians do not shy from denying those things which the sound human understanding would never dream of doubting. The idealist denies the actual existence of a material world. The egoist, if there has ever been one, denies the existence of all substances except himself and the Spinozist says that the himself is no being that subsists for itself, but a mere thought in God. Finally, the skeptic finds all of this still uncertain and subject to doubt. I cannot believe that any of these absurdities has ever been seriously maintained.” It should be noted that Mendelssohn’s notion of “idealism” is peculiar and does not correspond to the common usage. As the text itself indicates, Mendelssohn understands idealism as the denial of the existence of a material world—with the consequent affirmation of the exclusively mental nature of the actually existing world—a notion he shares with Wolff and Baumgarten. I am grateful to an anyonymous reviewer for highlighting this aspect to me. |
13 | Regarding Mendelssohn’s conception of truth as agreement (Übereinstimmung), see Gottlieb (2011, pp. 87–91). |
14 | In Morning Hours (Mendelssohn 1971, JubA 3.2, p. 53), Mendelssohn erroneously attributes the sentence to Democritus, while in Über Wahrheit und Schein (JubA 3.1, p. 278), he correctly attributes it to Heraclitus. |
15 | ὁ Ἡράκλειτός φησι τοῖς ἐγρηγορόσιν ἕνα καὶ κοινὸν κόσμον εἶναι τῶν δὲ κοιμωμένων ἕκαστον εἰς ἴδιον ἀποστρέφεσθαι. Translation by Kahn (1979, p. 104). |
16 | See Über Wahrheit und Schein (Mendelssohn 1971, JubA 3.1, p. 278): “Heraklit behauptete, daß wir alle nur so lange, als wir wachen, eine einzige gemeinschaftliche Welt hätten, und daß ein jeder im Schlaf und Traum gleichsam in seiner eignen Welt verkehre (Plut. VI. 634. Reiske); ferner, daß nur das wahr sei, was mit der allgemeinen Vernfunft, und worin alle Menschen übereinstimmen, und das falsch, was nur dem Verstande einzelner Menschen wahr scheine. Dies kommt mit meinen Begriffen so ziemlich überein”. |
17 | As evidence of this, consider the diversity of positions in metaphysical speculation and the lack of unanimity among them, indicating that they do not grasp a common and unitary reality. We could reasonably distinguish degrees of “philosophical” delirium according to Mendelssohn. The idealist is not as delusional as the solipsist (“if there has ever been one”). Spinozism can be interpreted in a reasonable and “purified” version, as Chapter 14 of Morning Hours shows. Skepticism and enthusiasm are perhaps the most delusional positions according to Mendelssohn. |
18 | The following passage from Jerusalem clearly shows that speculation fails to discern the adequate from the inadequate (Mendelssohn 1983, p. 95; italics mine): “But as soon as an Epicurus or a Lucretius, a Helvétius or a Hume criticizes the inadequacy of this mode of conceiving things and (which is to be charged to human weakness) strays too far in the other direction, and wants to carry a deceptive game with the word nature, Providence again raises up other men among the people who separate prejudice from truth, correct the exaggerations on both sides, and show that truth can endure even if prejudice is rejected.” |
19 | Gottlieb aptly terms this knowledge, based on the agreement between finite minds, “finite truth” (Gottlieb 2011, p. 91). |
20 | |
21 | The interweaving of epistemology and theology within the rationalistic tradition has been aptly described by Cassirer in the following terms (Cassirer 1932, p. 211): “Für Descartes und Malebranche, für Spinoza und Leibniz gibt es keine Lösung des Wahrheitsproblems außer durch die Vermittlung des Gottesproblems: die Erkenntnis des göttlichen Seins bildet das oberste Prinzip der Erkenntnis, aus dem alle anderen abgeleiteten Gewißheiten herfließen.” |
22 | I deliberately use the term “hypothesize,” for the reasoning presented by Mendelssohn is—contrary to his claim—far from being “apodictic.” Indeed, Mendelssohn can only reasonably assume that God possesses an impulse of approval similar to that of the human mind, but he cannot conclusively demonstrate this. Regarding the reasons in favor of his assumption, the argument could be framed as follows. Unlike the human intellect, the divine intellect is not affected by imperfections and limitations of any kind. In the human intellect we find not only an impulse of truth but also an impulse of approval, which does not seem to be due to a limitation or imperfection of the human mind. Rather, the approval-drive appears to be a capacity or power. Therefore, since the divine intellect is without limits, it is reasonable to suppose that it also possesses this approval-drive. Furthermore, if we attribute to God—as is commonly done—a certain “productivity” or “efficacy,” this assumption becomes even more plausible. |
23 | See also §49 from Sache Gottes oder die gerettete Vorsehung (Mendelssohn 1971, JubA 3.2). |
24 | Mendelssohn’s emphasis on the ontological “richness” as a fundamental aspect of the world’s perfection also encompasses a significant aesthetic dimension, which can be traced back to Baumgarten’s notion of “aesthetic wealth” (ubertas). For a detailed examination of this concept in Baumargten’s aesthetics and its influence on Mendelssohn, see Guyer (2011). For an exploration of the notions of perfection and imperfection in Mendelssohn’s thought, see Atlas (2019). The metaphysical focus on diversity also underlies Mendelssohn’s defense of religious plurality; see Gottlieb (2016). |
25 | We find similar argumentation in §437 of Baumgarten’s Metaphysics (Baumgarten 2014, p. 183): “If the most perfect world is posited, the supreme perfection that is possible in a world is posited (§436). Hence, the most perfect world is also the best of all possible worlds (§187). Now, the parts of the world are actual (§354), and there are either simultaneous or successive (§306). Therefore, the most perfect world embraces as many (1) simultaneous, (2) successive, and (3) as great beings as are compossible in the best world; i.e., it is (1) extensively, (2) protensively, and (3) intensively the best and greatest of the worlds (§436, 368).” |
26 | It could certainly be objected that—contrary to what Mendelssohn seems to assume—it is far from obvious that an ontologically “profuse” world is better than ontologically “austere” or “parsimonious” one. In defense of Mendelssohn, one might argue that an ontologically abundant world manifests more clearly the unlimited power and “fecundity” of the divine intellect. This assumption is shared by Wolff, who invokes precisely this argument to refute idealism (see Wolff 1744, pp. 339–40): the existence of bodies is consistent with God’s purpose in creating the world, which is precisely to manifest His unlimited power and “glory.” Baumgarten refutes in a similar manner solipsism (“egoism”) and idealism (Baumgarten 2014, p. 183; the terms written in uppercase are from Baumgarten’s text): “Even if only two contingent beings that are posited outside of each other in a world are compossible, either as simultaneous or as successive, one of whose perfection either subtracts nothing form the perfection of the other, or does not subtract from the perfection of the other so much as it adds to the perfection of the whole, then EGOTISTICAL WORLD, such as an egoist posits, is not the most perfect. And even if there is only one non-intellectual monad possible in itself that is compossible with spirits in the world, whose perfection either subtracts nothing from the perfection of the spirits, or does not subtract from the perfection of the spirits so much as it adds to the perfection of the whole, then the IDEALISTIC WORLD, such as is posited by the idealist, is not the most perfect”. It must be emphasized that all these approaches, including the “logic of creation” developed by Mendelssohn and analyzed here, are indebted to Leibniz and his doctrine of the best of all possible worlds. |
27 | If we incorporate this proof of God’s existence into the argument developed thus far, the resulting overall reasoning would be—in very broad strokes—as follows. God is fundamentally an infinite intellect, unaffected by the limitations and imperfections that characterize the finite human intellect. In the human intellect we find, in addition to a truth-drive, an approval-drive that accounts for its creative impetus. We can reasonably assume that the divine intellect also possesses this approval-drive, as it does not constitute an imperfection or limitation. God, understood as an infinite intellect, exists (proof of Chapter 16 of Morning Hours). Therefore, we can reasonably hold that the actually existing world ultimately exists because a faculty of approval in God has endorsed its transition to existence. As for the proof of God’s existence itself presented by Mendelssohn—which is notably intricate and obscure—the most detailed examination has been provided by Gideon Freudenthal (2018). Other analyses include those by Jakob (1786), Beck (1969), Altmann (1973, 1982), and Dyck (2011). |
28 | Mendelssohn’s discussion and defense of the ontological proof in the final chapter of Morning Hours clearly show that he was well acquainted with Kant’s critique of the proof and its central aspects (despite claiming in the preface to be unfamiliar with Kant’s philosophy). Furthermore, his defense of the proof can even be seen as a critique of Kant’s critique. See Rovira (2017). |
References
- Altmann, Alexander. 1973. Moses Mendelssohn: A Biographical Study. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. [Google Scholar]
- Altmann, Alexander. 1982. Moses Mendelssohn’s Proofs for the Existence of God. In Die Trostvolle Aufklärung. Studien zur Metaphysik und Politischen Theorie Moses Mendelssohns. Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog, pp. 135–51. [Google Scholar]
- Arkush, Allan. 1994. Moses Mendelssohn and the Enlightenment. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Atlas, Dustin Noah. 2019. What God Does Not Possess: Moses Mendelssohn’s Philosophy of Imperfection. Journal of Jewish Thought & Philosophy 27: 26–59. [Google Scholar]
- Baumgarten, Alexander. 2014. Metaphysics. A Critical Translation with Kant’s Elucidations, Selected Notes and Related Materials. Translated and edited with an introduction by Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers. London and New York: Bloomsbury. [Google Scholar]
- Beck, Lewis White. 1969. Early German Philosophy: Kant and His Predecessors. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Beiser, Frederick C. 1987. The Fate of Reason. German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Cassirer, Ernst. 1932. Philosophie der Aufklärung. Tübingen: Mohr-Paul Siebeck. [Google Scholar]
- Dahlstrom, Daniel O. 2019. Truth, Knowledge, and “the Pretentions of Idealism”: A Critical Commentary on the First Part of Mendelssohn’s Morning Hours. Kant-Studien 109: 329–51. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dyck, Corey W. 2011. Turning the Game Against the Idealist: Mendelssohn’s Refutation of Idealism in the Morgenstunden and Kant’s Replies. In Moses Mendelssohn’s Metaphysics and Aesthetics. Edited by Reinier Munk. Dordrecht, Heidelberg, London and New York: Brill, pp. 159–82. [Google Scholar]
- Fogel, Jeremy. 2015. Scepticism of Scepticism: On Mendelssohn’s Philosophy of Common Sense. Melilah: Manchester Journal of Jewish Studies 12: 53–69. [Google Scholar]
- Franks, Paul. 2011. Divided by Common Sense: Mendelssohn and Jacobi on Reason and Inferential Justification. In Moses Mendelssohn’s Metaphysics and Aesthetics. Edited by Reinier Munk. Dordrecht, Heidelberg, London and New York: Brill, pp. 203–15. [Google Scholar]
- Freudenthal, Gideon. 2012. No Religion without Idolatry. Mendelssohn’s Jewish Enlightenment. Notre Dame Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press. [Google Scholar]
- Freudenthal, Gideon. 2018. Between Rationalism and Romanticism: Moses Mendelssohn’s Proof of the Existence of God (Hebr). In A Tribute to Hannah. Jubilee Book in Honor of Hannah Kasher. Edited by Avi Elqayam and Ariel Malachi. Tel-Aviv: Idra Publishing, pp. 507–42. [Google Scholar]
- Funkenstein, Amos. 1986. Theology and the Scientific Imagination. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gottlieb, Michah. 2011. Faith and Freedom. Moses Mendelssohn’s Theological-Political Thought. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gottlieb, Michah. 2016. Mendelssohn’s Metaphysical Defense of Religious Pluralism. The Journal of Religion 86: 205–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Guyer, Paul. 2011. Mendelssohn’s Theory of Mixed Sentiments. In Moses Mendelssohn’s Metaphysics and Aesthetics. Edited by Reinier Munk. Dordrecht, Heidelberg, London and New York: Brill, pp. 259–78. [Google Scholar]
- Jakob, Ludwig Heinrich. 1786. Prüfung der Mendelssohnschen “Morgenstunden”. Leipzig: Bey Johann Samuel Heinsius. [Google Scholar]
- Kahn, Charles H. 1979. The Art and Thought of Heraclitus. An Edition of the Fragments with Translation and Commentary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kuehn, Manfred. 1987. Scottish Common Sense in Germany, 1786–1800: A Contribution to the History of Critical Philosophy. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Maydell, Alexander von, and Reiner Wiehl. 1974. Gemeinsinn. In Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie. Edited by Joachim Ritter and Karlfried Gründer. Basel: Schwabe Verlag, vol. 3, pp. 243–47. [Google Scholar]
- Mendelssohn, Moses. 1971. (JubA). Gesammelte Schriften: Jubiläumsausgabe. Edited by Ismar Elbogen, Fritz Bamberger, Julius Guttmann, Eugen Mittwoch, Haim Bar-Dayan and Simon Rawidowicz. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog, 24 vols. [Google Scholar]
- Mendelssohn, Moses. 1983. Jerusalem, or on Religious Power and Judaism. Translated by Allan Arkush. Introduction and commentary by Alexander Altmann. Hannover, NH: Brandeis University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mendelssohn, Moses. 1997. On Evidence in Metaphysical Sciences. In Moses Mendelssohn, Philosophical Writings. Translated and Edited by Daniel O. Dahlstrom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mendelssohn, Moses. 2011. Morning Hours: Lectures on God’s Existence. Translated by Daniel O. Dahlstrom, and Corey Dyck. Edited by Reinier Munk. Studies in German Idealism. Dordrecht: Springer, vol. 12. [Google Scholar]
- Munk, Reinier. 2011. “What Is the Bond?” The Discussion of Mendelssohn and Kant 1785–1787. In Moses Mendelssohn’s Metaphysics and Aesthetics. Edited by Reinier Munk. Dordrecht, Heidelberg, London and New York: Brill, pp. 183–202. [Google Scholar]
- Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 2012. Les Rêveries du promeneur solitaire. Edited by Érik Leborgne. Paris: Flammarion. [Google Scholar]
- Rovira, Rogelio. 2017. Mendelssohn’s Refutation of Kant’s Critique of the Ontological Proof. Kant-Studien 108: 401–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vogt, Wolfgang. 2005. Moses Mendelssohns Beschreibung der Wirklichkeit menschlichen Erkennens. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann. [Google Scholar]
- Wizenmann, Thomas. 1786. Die Resultate der Jacobischen und Mendelssohnschen Philosophie: Kritisch untersucht von einem Freywilligen. Leipzig: Göschen. [Google Scholar]
- Wolff, Christian. 1744. Natürliche Gottesgelahrtheit, II. Frankfurt: Renger. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Sánchez de León Serrano, J.M. Unity in Reason: Mendelssohn on the Conflict between Common Sense and Speculation. Religions 2024, 15, 971. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15080971
Sánchez de León Serrano JM. Unity in Reason: Mendelssohn on the Conflict between Common Sense and Speculation. Religions. 2024; 15(8):971. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15080971
Chicago/Turabian StyleSánchez de León Serrano, José María. 2024. "Unity in Reason: Mendelssohn on the Conflict between Common Sense and Speculation" Religions 15, no. 8: 971. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15080971
APA StyleSánchez de León Serrano, J. M. (2024). Unity in Reason: Mendelssohn on the Conflict between Common Sense and Speculation. Religions, 15(8), 971. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15080971