Divine Simplicity, Divine Relations, and the Problem of Robust Persons
Abstract
:1. The Threeness-Oneness Problem
- (1)
- The Father is God, the Son is God, and the Holy Spirit is God,
- (2)
- The Divine Persons are not each Other,
- (3)
- Yet, there is only one God.
2. Trinitarian Models
2.1. Latin Trinitarianism
2.2. Social Trinitarianism
While the above tenets do capture the essence of some Social Trinitarians, not all defenders of ST would be happy with such a designation, especially since certain models want to affirm something stronger than the persons sharing a generic or abstract kind essence.(ST1) The Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit are “of one essence,” but are not numerically the same substance. Rather, the divine persons are consubstantial only in the sense that they share the divine nature in common. Furthermore, this sharing of a common nature can be understood in a fairly straightforward sense via the “social analogy” in which Peter, James, and John share human nature.(ST2) Properly understood, the central claim of monotheism that there is but one God is to be understood as the claim that there is one divine nature—not as the claim that there is exactly one divine substance.(ST3) The divine persons must each be in full possession of the divine nature and in some particular relation R to one another for Trinitarianism to count as monotheism.
By strong or social trinitarianism, I mean a theory that meets at least the following three conditions: (1) The theory must have Father, Son, and Spirit as distinct centers of knowledge, will, love, and action. Since each of these capacities requires consciousness, it follows that in this sort of theory, Father, Son, and Spirit would be viewed as distinct centers of consciousness or, in short, as persons in some full sense of that term. (2) Any accompanying sub-theory of divine simplicity must be modest enough to be consistent with condition (1), that is, with the real distinctness of trinitarian persons. (3) Father, Son, and Spirit must be regarded as tightly enough related to each other so as to render plausible the judgment that they constitute a particular social unit. In such social monotheism, it will be appropriate to use the designator God to refer to the whole Trinity, where the Trinity is understood to be one thing, even if it is a complex thing consisting of persons, essences, and relations.
3. Aquinas on Simplicity, Persons, and Relations
3.1. Divine Simplicity and Divine Relations
3.2. Divine Persons and Divine Processions
For personal properties are the same as the persons because the abstract and the concrete are the same in God; since they are the subsisting persons themselves, as paternity is the Father Himself, and filiation is the Son, and procession is the Holy Ghost. But the non-personal properties are the same as the persons according to the other reason of identity, whereby whatever is attributed to God is His own essence.
3.3. Difficulties with Thomistic Persons
For any object x and y, if x and y are identical, then for any property P, x has P if and only if y has P.
4. Toward a More Robust Understanding of Person
…these things God has revealed to us through the Spirit. For the Spirit searches everything, even the depths of God. For who knows a person’s thoughts except the spirit of that person, which is in him? So also no one comprehends the thoughts of God except the Spirit of God.(ESV)
And he who searches hearts knows what is the mind of the Spirit, because the Spirit intercedes for the saints according to the will of God.(Rom 8:27, ESV)
Shares the “name” with the Father and the Son (Matt. 28:19; cf. Exod. 23:21);Teaches (Luke 12:12; cf. John 14:26);Testifies or bears witness (John 15:26; cf. Rom. 8:16);Guides (John 16:13; Acts 8:29)Can be lied to and tested (Acts 5:3–4, 9)Speaks (Acts 8:298; cf. 10:19–20; 28:25; 1 Tim. 4:1; Heb. 3:7);Calls to ministry and sends out (Acts 13:2-4);Forbids or allows (Acts 16:6–7);Intercedes (Rom. 8:26–27; cf. 15:16; Titus 3:5);Possesses a “mind” or “mindset” (Rom. 8:27);Reveals, searches, and knows the thoughts of God (1 Cor. 12:11); andCan be “grieved” (Eph. 4:30; cf. Isa 63:10; Heb. 10:29).
5. Two Objections
5.1. Objection 1: The Charge of Tritheism
For ST, Father, Son, and Spirit are three individual cases of deity, three divine substances, as Adam, Eve, and Abel are three human substances. For ST, there are in the Trinity three tropes of deity, not one. In most versions of ST, each Person has his own discrete mind and will, and ‘the will of God’ and ‘the mind of God’ are ambiguous or refer to the vector sum of the Persons’ thoughts and wills. Like three humans, ST’s Persons make up a community.
Either the Trinity is a fourth case of the divine nature, in addition to the Persons, or it is not. If it is, we have too many cases of deity for orthodoxy. If it is not, and yet is divine, there are two ways to be divine—by being a case of deity and by being a Trinity of such cases. If there is more than one way to be divine, Trinity monotheism becomes Platingian Arianism. But if there is in fact only one way to be divine, then there are two alternatives. One is that only the Trinity is God, and God is composed of non-divine Persons. The other is that the sum of all divine Persons is somehow not divine. To accept this last claim would be to give up Trinity monotheism altogether.
A group mind, if there were one, would be a mind composed of other minds. If the other minds were significantly simpler than the mind they composed, we might refer to the composing minds as ‘sub-minds’ and the composed item simply as a mind, but the composed item would be a group mind all the same. In group mind ST, the Trinity has or is a divine mind composed of the Persons’ minds. There is one God in the sense that there is just one ‘minded’ being composed of all divine minds.
The collective would be causeless and so (in my sense), unlike the members, ontologically necessary, not dependent for its existence on anything outside itself. It is they, however, rather than it, who, to speak strictly, would have the divine properties of omnipotence, omniscience, etc.; though clearly there is a ready and natural sense in which the collective can be said to have them as well.
But since the Father had no option but to cause the Son, and Father and Son had no option but to cause the Spirit, and all exist eternally, the dependence of Son on Father, and of Spirit on Father and Son, does not diminish greatness. Each could not exist but as eternally causing or permitting the other or others to exist.
5.1.1. Craig and Moreland’s Trinitarian Monotheism
It now becomes clear that the reason that the Trinity is not a fourth instance of the divine nature is that there are no other instances of the divine nature. The Father, Son, and Holy Spirit are not instances of the divine nature, and that is why there are not three Gods. The Trinity is the sole instance of the divine nature, and therefore there is but one God. So while the statement “The Trinity is God” is an identity statement, statements about the persons like “The Father is God” are not identity statements. Rather, they perform other functions, such as ascribing a title or office to a person (like “Belshazzar is king,” which is not incompatible with there being coregents) or ascribing a property to a person (a way of saying, “The Father is divine,” as one might say, “Belshazzar is regal”).
Protestants bring all doctrinal statements, even conciliar creeds, especially creeds of nonecumenical councils, before the bar of Scripture. Nothing in Scripture warrants us in thinking that God is simple and that each person of the Trinity is identical to the whole Trinity. Nothing in Scripture prohibits us from maintaining that the three persons of the Godhead stand in some sort of part-whole relation to the Trinity. Therefore, Trinity monotheism cannot be condemned as unorthodox in the biblical sense.
5.1.2. Davis’s Perichoretic Monotheism
(1) Each of the Persons equally possesses the divine essence in its totality. (2) The three necessarily share a marvelous unity of purpose, will, and action; that is, it is not possible for them to disagree or to be in conflict. (3) They exist in perichoresis (circumincession, co-inherence, permeation). That is, each is ‘in’ the others; each ontologically embraces the others; to be a divine Person is by nature to be in relation to the other two; the boundaries between them are transparent; their love for and communion with each other is such that they can be said to ‘interpenetrate’ each other.
- God is like a community.
- Each of the three Persons equally possess the divine essence.
- The three Persons are all equally and essentially divine, metaphysically necessary, eternal (or everlasting), uncreated, omnipotent, omniscient, and perfectly good.
- In the immanent Trinity (i.e., the Trinity as it is in itself), the logical basis of all differentiation among Father, Son, and Holy Spirit is their relations to each other.
- All three Persons are involved in all extra-Trintarian acts.
- The Persons are related to each other by perichoresis. (Davis 2016, pp. 69–72)
The Godhead ‘is God’ in the sense of strict numerical identity. The Godhead (which consists of Father, Son, and Holy Spirit, as we might say, exhausts God. Here the word ‘God’ in the predicate ‘… is God’ refers to an individual. But when we say that the Father ‘is God’ the Son ‘is God’, and the Holy Spirit ‘is God’, we are not talking about strict numerical identity; it would be false to say that ‘the Father exhausts God.’ Here the predicate ‘… is God’ does not refer to an individual but is a property meaning something close to ‘is divine’.
5.2. Objection #2: How Do the Persons Work Together?
6. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | As Pavel Butakov (2022) has argued, there is not just one model of divine relations. Patristic and medieval theologians put forth various understandings of the divine relations, leading to differing and often incompatible Trinitarian models. |
2 | |
3 | Here, I am not sure that I’d cash out the different properties as Moreland and Craig do. For our intent and purposes, it is enough to recognize that personal properties are more than mere relations. |
4 | Michael Jones brought this objection to may attention. Jones, Michael. 2022. Evangelical Philosophical Society, Denver, CO, USA. Personal communication. |
5 | For an interesting discussion see Tom Cochrane (2021). |
6 | I have deep reservationsn against this view, but included it as an option. For a detailed work against such a view, see Bird and Harrower (2019). |
7 | John Peckham and Greg Ganssle provided specific feedback on this objection. Peckham, John, and Greg Ganssle. 2023. Evangelical Philosophical Society, San Antonio, TX, USA. Personal communication. |
8 | I owe this language to my Liberty University colleague, Josh Waltman. |
References
- Aquinas, Thomas. 2007. Summa Theologica. Part 1. Translated by the Fathers of the Dominican Province. New York: Cosimo Classics, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Bird, Michael F., and Scott Harrower, eds. 2019. Trinity without Hierarchy: Reclaiming Nicene Orthodoxy in Evangelical Theology. Grand Rapids: Kregel Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Brown, David. 1985. The Divine Trinity. London: Open Court. [Google Scholar]
- Butakov, Pavel. 2022. What Exactly Are the Intra-Trinitarian Relations? TheoLogica 6: 162–73. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cochrane, Tom. 2021. A Case of Shared Consciousness. Synthese 199: 1019–37. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Craig, William Lane. 2009. Toward a Tenable Social Trinitarianism. In Philosophical and Theological Essays on The Trinity. Edited by Thomas McCall and Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 89–99. [Google Scholar]
- Crisp, Oliver D. 2019. A Parsimoious Model of Divine Simplicity. Modern Theology 35: 558–73. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Davis, Stephen T. 2016. Christian Philosophical Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Duby, Steven J. 2016. Divine Simplicity: A Dogmatic Account. New York: Bloomsbury. [Google Scholar]
- Harrison, Verna. 1991. Perichoresis in the Greek Fathers. St Vladimir’s Theological Quarterly 35: 53–65. [Google Scholar]
- Hasker, William. 2017. Metaphysics and the Tri-Personal God. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hasker, William. 2023. In Defense of the Trinitarian Processions. Annals of Philosophy/Roczniki Filozoficzne LXXI: 59–71. [Google Scholar]
- Hodgson, Leonard. 1944. The Doctrine of the Trinity. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons. [Google Scholar]
- Hollingsworth, Andrew. 2023. Mere Social Trinitarianism, the Eternal Relations of Origin, and Models of God. Journal of Analytic Theology 11: 23–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Leftow, Brian. 2009a. A Latin Trinity. In Philosophical and Theological Essays on the Trinity. Edited by Thomas McCall and Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 171–200. [Google Scholar]
- Leftow, Brian. 2009b. Anti Social Trinitarianism. In Philosophical and Theological Essays on the Trinity. Edited by Thomas McCall and Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 52–88. [Google Scholar]
- Longenecker, Richard N. 2016. The Epistle to the Romans. Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co. [Google Scholar]
- McCall, Thomas H. 2010. Which Trinity? Whose Monotheism? Philosophical and Systematic Theologians on the Metaphysics of Trinitarian Theology. Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co. [Google Scholar]
- McCall, Thomas H. 2014. Trinity Doctrine, Plain and Simple. In Advancing Trinitarian Theology: Explorations in Constructive Dogmatics. Edited by Oliver D. Crisp and Fred Sanders. Grand Rapids: Zondervan, pp. 42–59. [Google Scholar]
- McCall, Thomas H. 2021. Analytic Christology and the Theological Interpretation of the New Testament. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- McCall, Thomas, and Michael C. Rea. 2009. Philosophical & Theological Essays on the Trinity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Moltmann, Jürgen. 1993. The Trinity and the Kingdom. Minneapolis: Fortress Press. [Google Scholar]
- Moreland, James Porter, and William Lane Craig. 2017. Philosophical Foundations for a Christian Worldview, 2nd ed. Downers Grove: InterVarstiy Press. [Google Scholar]
- Moser, J. David. 2019. Divine Simplicity, Triune Action, and Appropriation. In The Lord is One: Reclaiming Divine Simplicity. Edited by Joseph Minich and Onsi A. Kamel. Leesburg: The Davenant Institute, pp. 81–94. [Google Scholar]
- Mullins, Ryan T. 2013. Simply Impossible: A Case against Divine Simplicity. Journal of Reformed Theology 7: 181–203. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mullins, Ryan T. 2023. The Trinitarian Processions. Annals of Philosophy/Roczniki Filozoficzne LXXI: 33–57. [Google Scholar]
- Peckham, John. 2021. Divine Attributes: Knowing the Covenantal God of Scripture. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Cornelius, Jr. 1989. Social Trinitarianism and Tritheism. In Trinity, Incarnation and Atonement: Philosophical and Theological Essays. Edited by Ronald J. Feenstra and Cornelius Plantinga, Jr. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 21–57. [Google Scholar]
- Savulescu, Julian, and Ingmar Persson. 2016. Conjoined Twins: Philosophical Problems and Ethical Challenges. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 41: 37–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Swinburne, Richard. 1994. The Christian God. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Thom, Paul. 2012. The Logic of the Trinity: Augustine to Ockham. New York: Fordham Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ware, Bruce. 2019. Unity and Distinction of the Trinitarian Persons. In Trinitarian Theology: Theological Models and Doctrinal Application. Edited by Keith S. Whitfield. Nashville: B&H Academic, pp. 17–61. [Google Scholar]
- Williams, Scott M. 2013. Indexicals and the Trinity: Two Non-Social Models. Journal of Analytic Theology 1: 74–94. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Williams, Scott M. 2017. Unity of Action in a Latin Social Model of the Trinity. Faith and Philosophy 34: 321–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 2010. Inquiring About God: Selected Essays. Edited by Terrence Cuneo. New York: Cambridge University Press, vol. 1, pp. 91–111. [Google Scholar]
- Zagzebski, Linda. 2008. Omnisubjectivity. In Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Jonathan L. Kvanvig. New York: Oxford University Press, vol. 1, pp. 231–47. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Campbell, R. Divine Simplicity, Divine Relations, and the Problem of Robust Persons. Religions 2024, 15, 874. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15070874
Campbell R. Divine Simplicity, Divine Relations, and the Problem of Robust Persons. Religions. 2024; 15(7):874. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15070874
Chicago/Turabian StyleCampbell, Ronnie. 2024. "Divine Simplicity, Divine Relations, and the Problem of Robust Persons" Religions 15, no. 7: 874. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15070874
APA StyleCampbell, R. (2024). Divine Simplicity, Divine Relations, and the Problem of Robust Persons. Religions, 15(7), 874. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15070874