Islamic Insights on Religious Disagreement: A New Proposal
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Two Preliminaries
2.1. Epistemic Peerhood and Disagreement
EP: epistemic agents similarly well-qualified—in terms of epistemic virtue and evidential familiarity—to form judgements with respect to some issue.
2.2. The Epistemic Problem of Religious Disagreement
- (1)
- There are people who hold theistic beliefs incompatible with mine, and yet they appear roughly as epistemically virtuous and evidentially familiar as me (RD-evidence).
- (2)
- RD-evidence, when considered against my total evidence, speaks against my theistic belief.
- (3)
- If premises (1)–(2) are true, then I ought to reduce my confidence in my theistic belief or if not, give it up completely.
- (4)
- Therefore, I ought to reduce my confidence in my theistic belief or if not, give it up completely.
3. Islamic Rationalist Conciliationism
3.1. Islamic Rationalist Religious Epistemology
TE: S’s theistic belief that p is epistemically justified/a piece of knowledge for S only when S’s belief that p is based on sufficiently supporting evidence e.
STE: S’s theistic belief that p is epistemically justified/a piece of knowledge for S only when S’s belief that p is based on sufficiently supporting evidence e, where (i) e is propositional and (ii) S is aware that e supports p.6
3.2. Religious Disagreement and Limited Conciliationism
[1] We find that all people, with their different religious opinions and sects, agree on one statement, namely, that whatever one holds to be true, is valid, and, as a result, that whatever others than him hold, is invalid … Therefore, it is taken for granted that taqlīd [i.e., blind social imitation/following] excuses its embracer from holding the opposite view on the same question. This, however, only accounts for the multiplicity of the number. The only way out of this is if one of them has his ultimate argument based on intellect (ʿaql) by way of which his truth can be known and if he has proof by way of which he can persuade fair-minded people to accept his truth
[2] The learned man knows that there are people who are wrong in their speculation (yukhṭiʾu) and others who are right (yuṣību), however each of them claims that he is right. Why, then, is the taqlīd of one of them better than the other? Why is the taqlīd of the believer of God’s unity better than the taqlīd of the unbeliever? … What is the proof that the learned man must speculate [i.e., reason] in order to obtain the knowledge of God? … [because he knows] there are systems which are right and others which are wrong.(quoted in Abrahamov 1998, pp. 58–59)
(1*) There are people who hold theistic beliefs incompatible with mine, and yet they appear to be my epistemic peers because they similarly hold their beliefs on the basis of either (a) socio-religious imitation (i.e., taqlīd) or (b) private religious experience/evidence (i.e., ilhām; kashf). (RD-evidence).
3.3. The Limits of Limited Conciliationism
4. Islamic Traditionalist Steadfastness
4.1. Islamic Traditionalist Religious Epistemology
RE: S’s theistic belief that p may be epistemically justified/a piece of knowledge for S, even where S’s belief is not based on some argument that supports p.
4.2. Islamic Traditionalist Steadfastness
4.3. The Problems of Traditionalist Steadfastness
5. Combining Insights
5.1. Inferential and Noninferential Reflective Responsibility
IRR: Inferential reflective responsibility is exercised where S has carefully considered the relevant evidence that directly bears on p, and where S forms her belief that p by a conclusion of inference.
NIRR: Noninferential reflective responsibility is exercised where S has carefully considered the relevant evidence that directly bears on p, and where S forms her belief that p by a conclusion of reflection.
5.2. Reflection, Disagreement, and Skepticism
… whereas this sort of [doxastic] ‘directness’ is the norm in the perceptual case, it is more naturally thought of as the exception to the norm in the religious case. Indeed, whereas perceptual beliefs seem to be, in the main, ‘forced’ upon us, religious beliefs often seem to be formed in a far less compelling fashion … the more common way of conceiving such belief is in terms of being ‘nudged’ or ‘invited’ towards a certain doxastic commitment.
- (5)
- If peer disagreement in philosophy based on opposing philosophical arguments means that one ought to withhold their philosophical beliefs, then this entails philosophical skepticism.
- (6)
- But philosophical skepticism is false.
- (7)
- Therefore, peer disagreement in philosophy based on opposing philosophical arguments does not mean that one ought to withhold their philosophical beliefs.
5.3. IRR, NIRR, and Epistemic Significance
An integrated image of Islam was now emerging with a finality, a decisiveness that sometimes astounded me. It was taking shape by a process that could only be described as a kind of mental osmosis—that is; without any conscious effort on my part to piece together and ‘systematize’ the many fragments of knowledge that had come my way during the past four years. I saw before me something like a perfect work of architecture, with all its elements harmoniously conceived to complement and support each other, with nothing superfluous and nothing lacking—a balance and composure which gave one the feeling that everything in the outlook and postulates of Islam was in its proper place.
5.4. A Partial Solution?
Prof. Smith and Prof. Jones were reputable scholars in their field and experts in the literary work, genre, and biographical details of Russian novelist Fyodor Dostoyevsky. Over the years, Smith and Jones would often gather at their local café to both read and discuss Dostoyevsky’s novels, perhaps reminiscent of meetings between J.R.R. Tolkien and C.S. Lewis. On occasion, the two professors engaged in a dispute as to the precise meaning of certain passages in Dostoyevky’s writings. Specifically, the two disagreed over what Dostoyevsky himself intended by such passages. Although Smith and Jones argued vehemently that the passage meant either A or it meant B, their disagreement was amicable; though they both regarded the other as wrong, they did nonetheless consider the other as reasonable.
6. Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | |
2 | A weaker version of steadfastness might allow for a reduction in confidence without any doxastic change. |
3 | |
4 | |
5 | On theistic evidentialist and other approaches to religious epistemology in general, cf., Dougherty and Tweedt (2015). |
6 | To re-emphasize, as Doko and Turner (2023) rightly point out, it is not the case that all Muslim rationalists uphold this strong version of theistic evidentialism. However, this does seem to be the paradigmatic view among such theologians. |
7 | With respect to general epistemology, there does seem to be a consenus on these matters among the Muslim rationalists. Cf., Wensinck (1965, pp. 252–63), Peters (1976, p. 53), Abrahamov (1993), Ibrahim (2013, p. 102), Wilmers (2018, p. 152), Mihirig (2022, p. 13). |
8 | Emphasis mine. |
9 | On the relevance of epistemic luck and Muslim rationalists’ condemnation of taqlīd, cf., Adamson (2022, pp. 7–11). |
10 | On the distinction between partialist and impartialist evidence, cf., Dormandy (2018, pp. 62–67). |
11 | John Pollock and Joseph Cruz (Pollock and Cruz 1999, p. 62) offer an example of reflection and subsequent conclusion that seems similar to Audi’s idea, using the example of an abstract painting. As Pollock points out, it is not the case that, upon reflection, one needs to form beliefs and thereby infer from them. So, the conclusion of reflection may be noninferential. |
12 | For more on the notion of intellectual carefulness, cf., King (2021, pp. 58–80). |
13 | Interestingly, this seems to be a point of difference that Muslim rationalists make about beliefs evident to the senses and religious or theistic beliefs, that only the former is in some sense “necessary” (ḍarūrī) or doxastically irresistible (cf., Abrahamov 1993). |
14 | This is partly what I take to be the intuition motivating conciliation in the disagreement of Peter and Khadijah in Imran Aijaz’s (2024) article. |
15 | An oft-cited example relevant to this point concerns the disagreement in metaphysics between David Lewis and Peter van Inwagen, cf., van Inwagen (1996). |
16 | |
17 | |
18 | On the distinction between partial and full defeaters, cf., Plantinga (2000, p. 362). |
19 | It is worth noting here that belief firmness being reduced by way of partial defeat, as already noted, need not mean one lacks knowledge, neither does it need to imply that one ought to shun full conviction in religious faith. On this, cf., Basil Mitchell’s (1978, pp. 122–30) discussion of a kind of “principle of tenacity”. |
20 | An important point to note: I think that epistemic permissivism might apply in one sense but not another. Alvin Goldman (1988) makes a distinction between weak and strong justification. The former refers to holding a belief blamelessly, and the latter refers to forming a belief on something ike reliable grounds or methods. In my view, it may be that some body of evidence permits different justified doxastic attitudes in the weak but not strong sense. So, in upholding the view of epistemic permissivism, one need not commit themselves to the view of religious pluralism. On the contrary, one might be a religious exclusivist in holding that there is only one unique justified doxastic attitude in the strong sense. |
21 | I am grateful to Imran Aijaz, Zain Ali, and Tyler McNabb for their comments on an earlier draft. I’d also like to thank the four anonymous referees for their constructive feedback. |
References
- Abrahamov, Binyamin. 1993. Necessary Knowledge in Islamic Theology. British Journal of Middle Eastern Studies 20: 20–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Abrahamov, Binyamin. 1998. Islamic Theology: Traditionalism and Rationalism. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Adamson, Peter. 2022. Don’t Think For Yourself: Authority and Belief in Medieval Philosophy. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. [Google Scholar]
- Aijaz, Imran. 2024. The ‘Diderot Objection’ to Plantinga’s Reformed Epistemology. Religious Studies 60: 123–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Asad, Muhammad. 1999. The Road to Mecca. Petaling Jaya: Islamic Book Trust. [Google Scholar]
- Audi, Robert. 1994. Dispositional Beliefs and Dispositions to Believe. Nous 28: 419–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Audi, Robert. 2004. The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Baker-Hytch, Max. 2024. God and the Problem of Evidential Ambiguity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bergmann, Michael. 2009. Rational Disagreement after Full Disclosure. Episteme 6: 336–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bergmann, Michael. 2017. Religious Disagreement and Epistemic Intuitions. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 81: 19–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ceric, Mustafa. 1995. Roots of Synthetic Theology in Islam: A Study of Abu Mansur al-Maturidi. Kuala Lumpur: International Institute of Islamic Thought and Civilization. [Google Scholar]
- Christensen, David. 2009. Disagreement as Evidence: The Epistemology of Controversy. Philosophy Compass 4: 756–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Cruz, Helen. 2018. Religious Disagreement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Doko, Enis, and Jamie B. Turner. 2023. Islamic Religious Epistemology. In The Cambridge Handbook of Religious Epistemology. Edited by Jonathan Fuqua, John Greco and Tyler McNabb. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 148–62. [Google Scholar]
- Dormandy, Katherine. 2018. Resolving Religious Disagreements: Evidence and Bias. Faith and Philosophy 35: 56–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dormandy, Katherine. 2023. Religious Disagreement. In The Cambridge Handbook of Religious Epistemology. Edited by Jonathan Fuqua, John Greco and Tyler McNabb. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 208–23. [Google Scholar]
- Dougherty, Trent, and Chris Tweedt. 2015. Religious Epistemology. Philosophy Compass 10: 547–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Feldman, Richard. 2007. Reasonable Religious Disagreement. In Philosophers Without Gods. Edited by Louise Antony. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 194–214. [Google Scholar]
- Frances, Bryan, and Jonathan Matheson. 2019. Disagreement. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/disagreement/ (accessed on 21 April 2024).
- Frank, Richard. 1989. Knowledge and Taqlīd: The Foundations of Religious Belief in Classical Ashʿarism. Journal of the American Oriental Society 109: 37–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Goldman, Alvin. 1988. Strong and Weak Justification. Philosophical Perspectives 2: 51–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Greco, John. 1997. Catholics and Calvinists on Religious Knowledge. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 71: 13–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Greco, John. 2003. Knowledge as Credit for True Belief. In Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology. Edited by Michael DePaul and Linda Zagzebski. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 111–34. [Google Scholar]
- Greco, John. 2010. Achieving Knowledge: A Virtue-Theoretic Account of Epistemic Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Heer, Nicholas. 1993. The Priority of Reason in the Interpretation of Scripture: Ibn Taymiya and the Mutakallimun. In Literary Heritage of Classical Islam. Edited by Mustansir Mir and Jarl E. Fossum. Feltham: Darwin Press, pp. 181–95. [Google Scholar]
- Hoitenga, Dewey. 1991. Faith and Reason from Plato to Plantinga: An Introduction to Reformed Epistemology. New York: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Hazm, Abu Muhammad. 2014. al-Fiṣal fī al-Milal wa-l-Ahwaʾ wa al-Naḥl. Cairo: Taṣwīr Maktaba al-Salām al-ʿĀlimiyya. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Taymiyya, Taqī al-Dīn. 1979. Darʾ Taʿāruḍ al-ʿAql wa-l-Naql. Riyadh: Dār al-Kunūz al-Adabiyya. [Google Scholar]
- Ibn Taymiyya, Taqī al-Dīn. 2004. Majmūʿ Fatāwā Shaykh al-Islām Aḥmad b. Taymiyya. Riyadh: Mujammaʿ al-Malik Fahd. [Google Scholar]
- Ibrahim, Mohd Radhi. 2013. Immediate Knowledge according to Qadi ʿAbd al-Jabbar. Sciences and Philosophy 23: 101–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Izutsu, Toshihiko. 2006. The Concept of Belief in Islamic Theology: A Semantic Analysis of Īmān and Islām. Petaling Jaya: Islamic Book Trust. [Google Scholar]
- Jackson, Elizabeth, and Greta LaFore. 2024. Permissivism, Underdetermination, and Evidence. In The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Evidence. Edited by Maria Lasonen-Aarnio and Clayton Littlejohn. London: Routledge, pp. 358–70. [Google Scholar]
- Jackson, Sherman. 2009. Islam and The Problem of Black Suffering. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- James, William. 1982. The Varities of Religious Experience. Harmondsworth: Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- Kam, Hureye. 2022. Dual Epistemology: Abū Manṣūr al-Māturīdī. In Māturīdī Theology: A Bilingual Reader. Edited by Lejla Demiri, Philip Dorroll and Dale J. Correa. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, pp. 33–46. [Google Scholar]
- Kelly, Thomas. 2005. The Epistemic Significance of Disagreement. In Oxford Studies in Epistemology. Edited by Tamar Szabó Gendler and John Hawthorne. Oxford: Oxford University Press, vol. 1, pp. 167–96. [Google Scholar]
- Kelly, Thomas. 2010. Peer Disagreement and Higher Order Evidence. In Social Epistemology: Essential Readings. Edited by Alvin Goldman and Dennis Whitcomb. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 183–217. [Google Scholar]
- Kelly, Thomas. 2014. How to be an Epistemic Permissivist. In Contemporary Debates in Epistemology. Edited by Matthias Setup, John Turri and Ernest Sosa. Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 298–312. [Google Scholar]
- King, Nathan L. 2012. Disagreement: What’s the Problem? or A Good Peer is Hard to Find. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85: 249–72. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- King, Nathan L. 2021. The Excellent Mind: Intellectual Virtues for Everyday Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kraft, James. 2012. The Epistemology of Religious Disagreement: A Better Understanding. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Lackey, Jennifer. 2010. What Should We Do When We Disagree? In Oxford Studies in Epistemology. Edited by Tamar Szabó and John Hawthorne. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 274–93. [Google Scholar]
- Lackey, Jennifer. 2014. Taking Religious Disagreement Seriously. In Religious Faith and Intellectual Virtue. Edited by Laura Frances Callahan and Timothy O’Connor. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 299–316. [Google Scholar]
- Lougheed, Kirk. 2018. Is Religious Experience a Solution to the Problem of Religious Disagreement. Logos and Episteme 9: 173–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mihirig, Abdurrahman Ali. 2022. Typologies of Scepticism in the Philosophical Tradition of Kalām. Theoria 88: 13–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mitchell, Basil. 1978. The Justification of Religious Belief. London: The Macmillan Press Ltd. [Google Scholar]
- Moffett, Marc. 2007. Reasonable Disagreement and Rational Group Inquiry. Episteme 3: 352–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moon, Andrew. 2016. Recent work in reformed epistemology. Philosophy Compass 11: 879–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Peters, J. R. T. M. 1976. God’s Created Speech. A Study in the Speculative Theology of the Muʿtazilī Qādī l-Quḍāt Abū l-Ḥasan ʿAbd al-Jabbār b. Aḥmad al-Hamadhānī. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Pittard, John. 2015. Religious Disagreement. In Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online: https://iep.utm.edu/rel-disa/ (accessed on 21 April 2024).
- Plantinga, Alvin. 2000. Warranted Christian Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pollock, John, and Joseph Cruz. 1999. Contemporary Theories of Knowledge. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Pritchard, Duncan. 2005. Reforming Reformed Epistemology. In Basic Belief and Basic Knowledge: Papers in Epistemology. Edited by Rene von Woudenberg, Sabine Roeser and Ron Rood. Vienna: De Gruyter, pp. 177–210. [Google Scholar]
- Pritchard, Duncan. 2016. Epistemology. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Quinn, Philip L. 1985. In Search of the Foundations of Theism. Faith and Philosophy 2: 469–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Roberts, Robert, and Jay Wood. 2007. Intellectual Virtues: An Essay in Regulative Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rosen, Gideon. 2001. Nominalism, Naturalism, and Epistemic Relativism. Philosophical Perspectives 15: 69–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Simpson, Robert Mark. 2013. Epistemic peerhood and the epistemology of disagreement. Philosophical Studies 164: 561–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Spevack, Aaron. 2020. Continuing Conversations: Later Sunni Kalam-Theology’s Onging Engagement with Philosophy. In Philosophical Theology in Islam: Later Ash‘arism East and West. Edited by Ayman Shihadeh and Jan Thiele. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Thune, Michael. 2010a. ‘Partial Defeaters’ and the Epistemology of Disagreement. The Philosophical Quarterly 60: 355–72. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Thune, Michael. 2010b. Religious Belief and the Epistemology of Disagreement. Philosophy Compass 5: 712–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Turner, Jamie B. 2021. An Islamic Account of Reformed Epistemology. Philosophy East and West 71: 767–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Turner, Jamie B. 2022. Ibn Taymiyya on theistic signs and knowledge of God. Religious Studies 58: 583–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vahid, Hamid. 2014. Some Problems With Steadfast Strategies for Rational Disagreement. Symposion 1: 89–107. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- van Inwagen, Peter. 1996. It is Wrong, Everywhere, Always, for Anyone, to Believe Anything upon Insufficient Evidence. In Faith, Freedom and Rationality. Edited by Jeff Jordan and Daniel Howard-Synder. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 137–54. [Google Scholar]
- Wensinck, Arent Jan. 1965. The Muslim Creed: Its Genesis and Historical Development. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Wilmers, Damaris. 2018. Beyond Schools: Muḥammad b. Ibrahīm al-Wazīr’s (d. 840/1436) Epistemology of Ambiguity. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Turner, J.B. Islamic Insights on Religious Disagreement: A New Proposal. Religions 2024, 15, 574. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050574
Turner JB. Islamic Insights on Religious Disagreement: A New Proposal. Religions. 2024; 15(5):574. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050574
Chicago/Turabian StyleTurner, Jamie B. 2024. "Islamic Insights on Religious Disagreement: A New Proposal" Religions 15, no. 5: 574. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050574
APA StyleTurner, J. B. (2024). Islamic Insights on Religious Disagreement: A New Proposal. Religions, 15(5), 574. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050574