Christian Citizens in a Democratic State: Is a True Separation of Church and State Really Possible?
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Church and State
Community | Society |
The object pursued precedes determinations of the intellect. | The object pursued is determined by the intellect. |
Produced by hereditary, linguistic, ethnical, and regional pressures. | Produced by reason. |
Proceeds from historical and situational contexts that favor the group, and, thus, are from nature. | Proceeds from human desires, in favor of personal interests, and, thus, from human free will. |
Constraints are based upon nature. | Constraints are based upon positive laws or ideas related to the common goal. |
“the Church is a supernatural society, simultaneously divine and human…which unites humans within itself as equal citizens of the Kingdom of God and directs them to eternal life, which is already begun on earth; which teaches them the revealed truths received in a deposit from the incarnate Word himself; and which is the very body of which Christ is the head, a body which is visible by its very nature and as it is ontologically one, visible in the faith which he professes, in its worship, its discipline and its sacraments, and in the refraction of his supernatural personality through its structure and human activity—invisible body in the mystery of the divine grace and charity vivifying souls…For the believer, the Church is the body of Christ supernaturally formed from the human race, where, as Bossuet said, the Christ is spread and communicated”.42
3. What Is a Citizen?
4. The Great Divorce: An Impossible Separation
4.1. Overlapping Origins, Ends, and Means
4.2. Overlapping Members
5. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | There is such a wide spectrum of views on how they should or should not be related, that one might almost suggest that there are as many perspectives on this question as there are authors writing about it. Andrew Naselli has recently published a helpful article attempting to articulate, as clearly as possible, the entire range of approaches to the relation between Church and State (Naselli 2023). |
2 | (cf. Davis 2023, p. 93; Finn 2023, p. 447). It is worth noting, that though some theorists see Jefferson’s notion of the “Wall of Separation” as expressing his view of an absolute separation of Church and State, others have pointed out that Jefferson was quite positive about the role of religion in the State and in State funded education (Benjamin 1969, p. 95). Benjamin goes on to note the historical origins of separationism in the European Anabaptist and Mennonite movements (Benjamin 1969, p. 96), and then explores a number of difficulties that he thinks flow from the Separationist approach to Church and State, including the development of a “club mentality” for many church attendees, pietism, and so on. |
3 | (cf. Davis 2003, p. 6). Davis notes that the notion of a “Wall of Separation” is actually found, prior to Jefferson, in the writings of Roger Williams (Davis 2003, p. 13). The notion of a “wall of separation” in the thought of Roger Williams is also discussed by Joseph M. Dawson (cf. Dawson 2008, pp. 677–78). Dawson appears to interpret the “wall of separation” as implying (if not expressing outright) the absolute separation of Church and State specifically in relation to their relative institutional functions. He suggests that, “[w]hat the Constitution of the United States forbids and constitutions of all the states forbid, although in different forms of expression, is the making of any law or the action of any governmental authority in pursuance of any law that involves the interlocking of the official functions of the state (or any of its agencies) with the official or institutional functions of any church. (Dawson 2008, p. 679)”. |
4 | |
5 | |
6 | |
7 | (Davis 2003, p. 13). Davis does not seem to be suggesting that Jefferson, Williams, or others, suggested that there could be no “cooperation” or “interaction” between Church and State. Rather, in a different paper, Davis notes that “Scholars are fond of stressing that Williams was concerned about protecting the church from the state, whereas Jefferson felt the ‘wall was necessary to protect the state from the church. While this wom-out distinction is generally accurate, there were far more likenesses than differences in Williams’s and Jefferson’s views on church-state relations. Clearly, both believed that a flexible boundary between the institutions of religion and government preserved the health and integrity of both (Davis 1999, p. 201).” |
8 | In this paper, we will be working with the approach outlined above, which resembles the view outlined by Robert Audi, who describes it as, “the state should not interfere with the church, and (though this is usually given lesser emphasis) the church should not interfere with the state. The separation doctrine is also intended to apply to the state in relation to religious individuals who are not affiliated with any church (Audi 1989, p. 262.).” There are other approaches to the question of Church and State, and, indeed, questions concerning how the “wall of separation” actually works out in practice. A very similar approach to view of the separation of Church and State which has been articulated above, can be found in the arguments of Kathleen M. Sullivan, writing against the position of Michael McConnell (cf. Sullivan 1992, pp. 195–223). Sullivan, in a way which tends to prove the point we are making in this paper, begins her article by noting that Roman Catholic and Protestant religious leaders of the 1980s and 90s tended to wield a great deal of political power (Sullivan 1992, p. 196), by influencing their voting parishioners. She then turns to a discussion of “The Free Exercise Clause and the Establishment Clause” to argue that the public and civil resolving of moral issues must be done on entirely secular grounds (Sullivan 1992, p. 197), that public education must be entirely secular (Sullivan 1992, pp. 199, 202), and “official agnosticism” in all government activities (Sullivan 1992, p. 206). It seems, upon consideration, that Sullivan’s articulation of the separation of Church and State also falls prey to the argument we are presenting In this paper. In other words, an approach to Church and State which requires that all reasons for the establishment of laws or polity be secular (or non-religious), seems to fall prey to the argument presented in this paper. The inverse of this could also be shown to be problematic. That is, an approach to Church and State which requires that all church doctrine and practice must be entirely grounded in exclusively “religious” reasons will also fall prey to the argument presented in this paper (cf. Hooker [1907] 1969). |
9 | The nature of a “true Democracy” will be discussed below. |
10 | The thought of Maritain is particularly helpful for this discussion, as he defended the principles of Democracy, but also thought that it was possible for the Church and a secularized State to cooperate (thus suggesting that he thought that Democracy might not require an absolute separation of Church and State). We might even find, in Maritain, a form of Christian Democracy (cf. Hellman 1991, pp. 460–61, 471). For more on Maritain’s views concerning the secularized state and his views on the separation of Church and State, see (Pink 2015). Pink’s article is wide-ranging, but is helpful for drawing out how Maritain’s general project failed due to the direction that was taken by the contemporary secularization of politics. Maritain thought it would lead to greater freedom for Religion, but, it ended in the State seeking to subsume Religion under its authority as one among a number of common goods (Pink 2015, pp. 12–13, 23–32). Pink ends up providing, using his interaction with Maritain, an interesting analysis of the problems created by the secularation of politics for the separation of Church and State. Pink’s analysis does not appear to necessitate any major changes in the argument we are proposing in the article (but could be seen as ultimately arriving at similar conclusions by a different route). |
11 | (Maritain 1965, p. 1). My translation from the French, “Il n’est pas de tâche plus ingrate que d’essayer de distinguer et de circonscrire de façon rationnelle, en d’autres termes d’essayer d’élever jusqu’à un niveau scientifique ou philosophique, des notions banales qui sont nées des besoins pratiques et contingents de l’histoire humaine et sont chargées d’implications sociales, culturelles et historiques aussi ambiguës que fertiles, et qui pourtant enveloppent un noyeau de signification intelligible. Ce sont là des concepts nomades, non fixés; ils sont changeants et fluides, employés tantôt comme synonymes, tantôt comme contraires”. Jacques Leclercq also notes the difficulty of defining these terms, as they are given multiple meanings (cf. Leclercq 1958, p. 10). |
12 | (Aristotle 1941). Aristotle, Politica, 1252a1–2, trans. Benjamin Jowett, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon (New York: Random House, 1941), 1127. For all references to Aristotle’s Politics, we will use this translation (unless otherwise mentioned), and adhere to standard citation practices for Aristotle’s works. |
13 | Aristotle, Politica, 1252a26–33. |
14 | Aristotle, Politica, 1252b14–27. |
15 | Aristotle, Politica, 1252b27–30. |
16 | Aquinas, CAP, 7. |
17 | Aristotle, Politica, 1253a19–20. |
18 | Aristotle, Politica, 1252b30–1253a39. |
19 | Maritain, HE, 3. |
20 | Maritain, HE, 3–4. |
21 | Maritain, HE, 4. |
22 | Maritain, HE, 5. My translation from the French, “prennent conscience d’eux-mêmes tels que l’histoire les a faits, qui sont attachés au trésor de leur passé et qui s’aiment tels qu’ils se savent ou s’imaginent être, avec une sorte d’inévitable introversion”. |
23 | Maritain, HE, 5. |
24 | Maritain, HE, 5. |
25 | Maritain, HE, 5–6. |
26 | Maritain, HE, 6. |
27 | Maritain, HE, 6. |
28 | Maritain, HE, 6. |
29 | Maritain, HE, 6–7. |
30 | Maritain, HE, 9. |
31 | Maritain, HE, 9. |
32 | Maritain, HE, 9. My translation from the French, “C’est une réalité concrètement et entièrement humaine, qui tend vers un bien concrètement et entièrement humaine, le bien commun. » |
33 | Maritain, HE, 11–12. My translation from the French, “est seulement cette partie du corps politique dont l’objet spécial est de maintenir la loi, de promouvoir la prospérité commune et l’ordre public, et d’administrer les affaires publiques. L’État est une partie spécialisée dans les intérêts du tout”. |
34 | Maritain, HE, 12. My translation from the French, “l’homme n’est à aucun titre pour l’État. L’État est pour l’homme”. |
35 | Leclercq, EP, 11. My translation from the French, “Au sens propre et premier, l’État est donc la collectivité humaine organisée, avec son caractère spécifique d’organisation. » Italics in Leclercq. |
36 | Leclercq, EP, 11. My translation from the French, “l’individu est la fin de l’État, mais l’État n’est pas la fin de l’individu; il n’est pour l’individu qu’un moyen”. Italics in Leclercq. |
37 | Leclercq, EP, 12. |
38 | Leclercq, EP, 13. My translation from the French, “Quand l’État agit, il est représenté par certains hommes, les gouvernants, qui forment ensemble ce que, dans le droit moderne, on appelle le gouvernement”. The italics in Leclercq. |
39 | Leclercq, EP, 12, 13. |
40 | Leclercq, EP, 13. My translation from the French, “simplement les organes de l’État, et ils ne le représentent que dans la mesure où ils en ont reçu mission”. |
41 | Maritain, HE, 140. My translation from the French, “sont des corps organisés ou des associations qui se dédient spécialement aux besoins religieux et aux croyances religieuses d’un certain nombre de ses compagnons de route ici-bas, c’est-à-dire aux valeurs spirituelles auxquelles ils ont commis leur vie et auxquelles leur idéal moral est suspendu”. |
42 | Maritain, HE, 140–41. My translation from the French, “l’Église est une société surnaturelle, à la fois divine et humaine…qui réunit en soi les hommes comme concitoyens du Royaume de Dieu et les conduit à la vie éternelle, déjà commencée ici-bas; qui leur enseigne la vérité révélée reçue en dépôt du Verbe incarné lui-même; et qui est le corps même dont le Christ est la tête, corps visible de par son essence et en tant même qu’ontologiquement un, visible dans la foi qu’il professe, dans son culte, sa discipline et ses sacrements, et dans la réfraction de sa personnalité surnaturelle à travers sa structure et son activité humaine—corps invisible dans le mystère de la grâce et de la charité divines vivifiant les âmes…Pour le croyant, l’Église est le corps du Christ surnaturellement formé de la race humaine, ou, comme l’a dit Bossuet, le Christ répandu et communiqué”. Italics in Maritain. |
43 | Maritain, HE, 140. |
44 | Maritain, HE, 141–42. This view can be found expounded upon in the Roman Catholic notion of the distinction and cooperation of Church and State (cf. Konvitz 1949, pp. 46–48). |
45 | Maritain, HE, 142. |
46 | Aristotle, Politica, 1275b18–21. Cf. Aristotle, Politica, 1275a22–24. |
47 | Aquinas, CAP, 183. |
48 | Aquinas, CAP, 183. |
49 | Aquinas, CAP, 183. |
50 | Aquinas, CAP, 183. |
51 | Aquinas, CAP, 183. |
52 | Aquinas, CAP, 183. |
53 | Aristotle, Politica, 1279a23–1279b4. |
54 | We say “versions” of Democracy, as there are a variety of forms of Democratic State. The most basic understanding of a Democracy is “the rule of the many”, or a people that is governed by itself. In this paper, we will be interacting with what is commonly called a Liberal Democracy, which as Marc F. Plattner has rightly noted, “is what most people mean today when they speak of democracy (Plattner 1998, p. 172). It is generally agreed that the primary criteria for a Liberal Democracy are: (1) that the citizens have a right to express their wishes concerning the direction of the country through free elections; (2) the protection of the various rights or liberties of the person; and (3) the rule of law (cf. Plattner 1998, p. 171.) Michael J. Perry only lists the first 2 of the three criteria we have named, in his article (Perry 2009, pp. 621–22). John Hellman’s analysis of Maritain’s political thought, as seen in letters written by Maritain to Yves Simon, shows that this is also, more or less, what Maritain understood as fundamental to a Democracy (Hellman 1991, p. 458). There are, of course, other forms of Democracy. In his paper, Plattner mentions and briefly discusses the following variations: “illiberal democracy (Plattner 1998, p. 172),“ “electoral democracies (Plattner 1998, p. 171)”, Republican or Representational Democracies versus Pure Democracies (Plattner 1998, p. 174), and so on. He also suggests that for Montesquieu and Rousseau, as soon as a Democracy turns towards “representation” it is no longer truly democratic or free (Plattner 1998, p. 174). Ralph Ketcham, in his book The Idea of Democracy in the Modern Era, also discusses forms of Democracy such as “social democracy”, or, he suggests, “the post-1945 liberal corporate state” (Ketcham 2021, pp. 90, 99) He also appears to use, at least, the first two criteria we mentioned above in affirming that some form of governance is democratic (cf. Ketcham 2021, pp. 20–22, 41, 44, 93, 99, and so on). For a discussion of other versions of Democracy, see (Miller 1984, pp. 205–8). |
55 | Aquinas, CAP, 184. |
56 | Aquinas, CAP, 184. |
57 | The question of religious pluralism in a given State creates even greater complications for the Church-State debate. |
58 | Dawson points to Roger Williams as one who would disagree with what we are suggesting in this section, suggesting that “As argued by Roger Williams in the beginning, the functions and objectives of religion and state differ. (Dawson 2008, p. 681)”. We propose to show that so understood, Dawson, and Williams as interpreted by Dawson, are wrong. Rather, as we will show, Church and State overlap in relation to origins, ends, and means. |
59 | Aristotle, Politica, 1253a2. |
60 | Cf. Ex. 22:28; Rom. 13:1–7; 1 Tim. 2:1–2; 1 Pet. 2:13–17. |
61 | This can be taken to mean both: God divinely ordains that man must live in a temporal political body with some form of governing body and God providentially governs all of human political and governing bodies (raising and tearing down all human governments as He sees fit). This is, of course, a point of contention for Christian theologians. |
62 | Cf. Ex. 22:28; Rom. 13:1–7; 1 Cor. 7:20–24; Phil. 4:11; 1 Tim. 2:1–2; 1 Pet. 2:13–17. |
63 | The point of overlap we are noting here appears to be what Konvitz is pointing to when he discusses the question of monetary support (or lack of support) for religious institutions, including religious schools (Konvitz 1949, pp. 48–50). Konvitz goes on to discuss the possibility of distinction and cooperation in the United States, ultimately arguing that the wall of separation idea does not allow for the possibility of the doctrine of distinction and cooperation (Konvitz 1949, pp. 50–60). |
64 | Maritain, HE, 143. Translation from the French, “Du fait que la même personne humaine est à la fois membre de cette société qu’est l’église et membre de cette société qu’est le corps politique, une division absolue entre ces deux sociétés signifierait que la personne humaine doit être coupée en deux”. |
65 | Maritain, HE, 143. |
66 | Maritain, HE, 154. |
67 | Maritain, HE, 154. Translated from the French, “le corps politique en tant que tel a une obligation à l’égard de la vérité à laquelle le peuple lui-même, ou les citoyens qui constituent le corps politique, adhèrent en conscience. Le corps politique ne connaît pas d’autre vérité que celle que le peuple connaît”. Italics in Maritain. |
68 | Maritain, HE, 155. Translated from the French, “tout dépendra, en pratique, de ce que le peuple ou les citoyens croient librement en conscience”. |
69 | It was common amongst philosophers of the early to mid-1900s to portray Rousseau as one of the greatest Democratic theorists of the 18th century (cf. Miller 1984, p. 2). This approach has since been questioned, creating something of a debate on the matter. Though some might be inclined to outright deny that Jean-Jacques Rousseau can be portrayed as proning either political liberalism or Democracy (and there is certainly reason to doubt that Rousseau promoted Democracy in any way that would be recognized by Democratic theorists today. cf. Miller 1984, p. 2), there is reason to think that both of these notions can be found in Rousseau (and, thus, some primitive form of Liberal Democracy). For example, Rousseau has been portrayed as denying that a Representational Democracy is a true Democracy (Plattner 1998, p. 174), but, far from rejecting Democracy, Rousseau is generally interpreted as affirming that freedom is only possible through a form of Democracy (cf. Willhoite 1965, p. 501). Furthermore, not only is Rousseau taken to affirm Democracy, he also appears to have promoted the three main criteria of a Liberal Democracy that we outlined above, namely: the idea that the will of the people is the source of the constitution and law, that the rule of law is supreme over people and government (Dunning 1909, p. 406), the importance of individual liberty (Dunning 1909, p. 405), and, that his thought is the precursor for the notion of free voting by the people concerning both the revision/creation of laws and the election of politicians (Dunning 1909, p. 404). Furthermore, at least one scholar argues that though Rousseau may not be seen to be a “traditional” Liberal, he is most certainly promoting a revised version of Liberalism (cf. Sorenson 1990, pp. 443–66). Based upon the appearance, in the thought of Rousseau, of the three criteria of a Liberal Democracy, and the fact that we find him both promoting Democracy and a qualifed Liberalism, it seems that we are entitled to conclude that if he is not himself promoting a version of Liberal Democracy, then he is a legitimate forefather of Liberal Democratic theory. It is, indeed, as the legitimate forefather of a variety of contemporary Democracies that we find Rousseau presented to us by James Miller in his work on Rousseau’s dream of democracy (Miller 1984, pp. 202–10). |
70 | Leclercq, EP, 158. Translated from the French, “Les hommes, abandonnant leur liberté à la communauté la retrouvent en elle, puisque la communauté, c’est eux; mais la communauté ne peut, à son tour, aliéner cette liberté. Le peuple ne peut se remettre à un souverai; il est lui-même le souverain, et le seul souverain possible”. |
71 | John Rawls appears to agree that an actual separation of Church and State is not fully possible, but that it is possible to work around this through what he calls “overlapping consensus”. In his paper, “The Idea of Overlapping Consensus”, Rawls suggests a way of working around the fact that all of the members of any Democracy necessarily have a Religion or Life-Philosophy (what he calls a General and Comprehensive doctrine) which is the basis of their views about moral and political questions (Rawls 1987, pp. 9–11). His theory appears to state that, despite the pluralism of any contemporary Democratic state, there will be some rock-bottom ideas that all people agree upon, and that we can use these ideas as principles upon which to base the Democracy (Rawls 1987, p. 6). This may be a solution, though there are some potential difficulties with the theory proposed by Rawls, and it may yet fall prey to the problem we have underlined in this article. We do not, however, have space to consider his theory and its attending difficulties in this paper. |
72 | In the course of revising this paper for publication, we came across a paper published 71 years ago, by the eminent philosopher Gregory Vlastos, which appears to propose an argument which is very similar to the one we have articulted above. (cf. Vlastos 1953). Discussing Maritain’s work Man and the State, Vlastos notes that Maritain clearly wants to defend both Democracy and the complete independence of Church and State (Vlastos 1953, p. 564), both functioning in their proper spheres (Vlastos 1953, pp. 565–66). Vlastos notes that the way that authority functions in the Church, versus in the State, is quite different (Vlastos 1953, pp. 566–67). Confirming our reading of Maritain, Vlastos notes that Maritain recognizes, as he must, that the two spheres (Church and State) are necessarily overlapping (Vlastos 1953, p. 569). Vlastos suggests, that the authority of the Church over its members in relation to moral matters brings it in to conflict with the State in relation to those same matters, thus creating precisly the problem we have raised above (Vlastos 1953, pp. 570–76). Though Vlastos approaches this subject from a slightly different direction, he appears to arrive at very similar conclusions. |
References
- Aquinas, Thomas. 2007. Commentary on Aristotle’s Politics. Translated by Richard J. Regan. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Co. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1941. Politica. In The Basic Works of Aristotle. Translated by Benjamin Jowett. Edited by Richard McKeon. New York: Random House. [Google Scholar]
- Audi, Robert. 1989. The Separation of Church and State and the Obligations of Citizenship. Philosophy & Public Affairs 18: 259–96. Available online: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2265345 (accessed on 5 December 2023).
- Benjamin, Walter W. 1969. Separation of Church and State: Myth and Reality. Journal of Church and State 11: 93–109. Available online: https://www.jstor.org/stable/23913938 (accessed on 5 December 2023). [CrossRef]
- Calvin, John. 2006. Institutes of the Christian Religion. Translated by Ford Lewis Battles. Edited by John T. McNeill. Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Davis, Derek H. 1999. Editorial: The Enduring Legacy of Roger Williams: Consulting America’s First Separationist on Today’s Pressing Church-State Controversies. Journal of Church and State 41: 201–12. Available online: https://www.jstor.org/stable/23920275 (accessed on 5 December 2023). [CrossRef]
- Davis, Derek H. 2003. Thomas Jefferson and the ‘Wall of Separation’ Metaphor. Journal of Church and State 45: 5–14. Available online: https://www.jstor.org/stable/23920156 (accessed on 5 December 2023). [CrossRef]
- Davis, James Calvin. 2023. Roger Williams. In Baptist Political Theology. Edited by Thomas S. Kidd, Paul D. Miller and Andrew T. Walker. Brentwood: B&H Academic, pp. 73–96. [Google Scholar]
- Dawson, Joseph M. 2008. The Meaning of Separation of Church and State in the First Amendment. Journal of Church and State 50: 677–81. Available online: https://www.jstor.org/stable/23921771 (accessed on 5 December 2023). [CrossRef]
- Dunning, Wm A. 1909. The Political Theories of Jean Jacques Rousseau. Political Science Quarterly 24: 377–408. Available online: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2140885 (accessed on 5 December 2023).
- Finn, Nathan A. 2023. The Christian Right: From Reagan to Trump. In Baptist Political Theology. Edited by Thomas S. Kidd, Paul D. Miller and Andrew T. Walker. Brentwood: B&H Academic, pp. 431–58. [Google Scholar]
- Hellman, John. 1991. The Anti-Democratic Impulse in Catholicism: Jacques Maritain, Yves Simon, and Charles de Gaulle during World War II. Journal of Church and State 33: 453–71. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hooker, Richard. 1969. Of the Laws of Ecclesiastical Polity. Reprint. London: J. M. Dent & Sons/Everyman’s Library. First published in 1907. [Google Scholar]
- Ketcham, Ralph. 2021. The Idea of Democracy in the Modern Era. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas. [Google Scholar]
- Konvitz, Milton R. 1949. Separation of Church and State: The First Freedom. Law and Contemporary Problems 14: 44–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Leclercq, Jacques. 1958. L’État ou La Politique. In Leçons de Droit Naturel, 4th ed. Namur and Louvain: Maison d’éditions ad, Wesmael-charlier (S.A.)/Société D’études Morale, Sociale Et Juridiques. vol. 2. [Google Scholar]
- Maritain, Jacques. 1965. L’homme et l’état, 2nd ed. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. [Google Scholar]
- Miller, James. 1984. Rousseau: Dreamer of Democracy. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Naselli, Andrew David. 2023. What Is the Spectrum of Major Views on Political Theology? A Proposed Taxonomy of Seven Views on Religion and Government. Christ Over All, November 10. Available online: https://christoverall.com/article/longform/what-is-the-spectrum-of-major-views-on-political-theology-a-proposed-taxonomy-of-seven-views-on-religion-and-government/ (accessed on 5 December 2023).
- Perry, Michael J. 2009. Liberal Democracy and the Right to Religious Freedom. The Review of Politics 71: 621–35. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pink, Thomas. 2015. Jacques Maritain and the Problem of Church and State. The Thomist: A Speculative Quarterly Review 79: 1–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Plattner, Marc F. 1998. Liberalism and Democracy: Can’t Have One without the Other. Foreign Affairs 77: 171–80. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rawls, John. 1987. The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 7: 1–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sorenson, Leonard R. 1990. Rousseau’s Liberalism. History of Political Thought 11: 443–66. [Google Scholar]
- Sullivan, Kathleen M. 1992. Religion and Liberal Democracy. The University of Chicago Law Review 59: 195–223. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vlastos, Gregory. 1953. Of Sovereignty in Church and State. The Philosophical Review 62: 561–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Willhoite, Fred H., Jr. 1965. Rousseau’s Political Religion. The Review of Politics 27: 501–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Haines, D. Christian Citizens in a Democratic State: Is a True Separation of Church and State Really Possible? Religions 2024, 15, 262. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15030262
Haines D. Christian Citizens in a Democratic State: Is a True Separation of Church and State Really Possible? Religions. 2024; 15(3):262. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15030262
Chicago/Turabian StyleHaines, David. 2024. "Christian Citizens in a Democratic State: Is a True Separation of Church and State Really Possible?" Religions 15, no. 3: 262. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15030262
APA StyleHaines, D. (2024). Christian Citizens in a Democratic State: Is a True Separation of Church and State Really Possible? Religions, 15(3), 262. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15030262