Toward a Buddhist Ecological Ethic of Care
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Buddhist Moral Phenomenology
- Supreme bodhicitta is desire to
- Clear every fault from each and every sentient being
- And to produce infinite good qualities in each of them.
- Even among the wondrous this is wondrous!1
3. Key Aspects of Buddhist Moral Phenomenology
In other words, Buddhist ethical action is characterized by how it closely relates to its ontological commitments. Duḥkha and pratītyasamutpāda are meditatively adopted into how one directly experiences the world, and then one acts from that experience in a spontaneously altruistic manner which the Tibetan tradition calls bodhicitta.The first step in establishing the view is to acquire a proper understanding of the teachings about it. Then, to incorporate the view into our inner experience, we put it into practice over and over again; this is the meditation. Maintaining our experience of the view at all times and under all circumstances is the action.
- That which arises in dependent origination
- Is explained as emptiness.
- That, being a dependent designation
- Is itself the middle way.
- That being so, a thing which is not dependently arisen
- Does not exist.
- Therefore, a thing that is not empty
- Does not exist.2
Care, therefore, should be considered the principal conative disposition of the bodhicitta at the heart of Buddhist moral phenomenological development. The ideal state of bodhicitta is understood in the Tibetan tradition as having two aspects: aspiration and application. While wishing for others to be well has value (bodhicitta in aspiration), actually addressing the causes of duḥkha and working towards their alleviation is necessary in Buddhist ethical and soteriological traditions.Karuṇā connotes not just an emotive response to another, but a commitment to act on behalf of others to relieve their suffering. The standard translation is hence etymologically paradoxical, and can be misleading. The term care nicely captures this commitment to act, as in the case of caregiving, caring for, and other such expressions.
Only when Asaṅga actually put bodhicitta into practice did he meet Maitreya, demonstrating the absolute necessity of engagement and application in Buddhist ethics. In Buddhist ethics, compassion is not something that one feels while simply watching conflict from the sidelines or meditatively cultivates by one’s lonesome self. Compassion and bodhicitta must be active, engaged, and applied to be considered fully developed.Asaṅga was overwhelmed by compassion, and for want of anything to feed the dog, he cut a piece of flesh from his own leg for it to eat. He then turned his attention to its appalling wounds, but soon realized that all attempts to remove the maggots might save the dog but would kill the maggots. The only solution he could think of was to use his tongue to coax the maggots out of the stinking flesh. Shutting his eyes, he bent down to do what he could to heal the animal, only to find himself licking the dust by the side of the road. When he opened his eyes, he found the dog had disappeared. In its place, before him stood Maitreya.
4. Buddhist Moral Phenomenology and Feminist Care Ethics
In opposition to this abstract ethical theorizing, Gruen proposes a perceptual, experiential approach to care ethics which she calls “entangled empathy”. In her words, entangled empathy is “a type of caring perception focused on attending to another’s experience of wellbeing,” and “an experiential process involving a blend of emotion and cognition in which we recognize that we are in relationships with others and are called upon to be responsive and responsible in these relationships” (3). As Garfield notes, Buddhist ethicists rarely talked about ethics in an abstract sense. He writes: “Buddhist moral theorists see ethics as concerned not primarily with actions, their consequences, obligations, sentiments or human happiness, but rather with the nature of our experience” (Garfield 2014, p. 279). Thus, Gruen’s articulation of care ethics or entangled empathy as a reorientation towards “our actual moral experiences” mirrors the moral phenomenological interpretation of Buddhist ethics quite perfectly.As it is usually practiced, ethical theorizing detaches us from our actual moral experiences and practices through abstract reasoning. It sidesteps the complex social and political structures and ideologies that are always in play. It also sets aside our particular concerns, our relationships, and the other things that make life worth living. It thus can seem rather alienating, and an alienating theory will not help us to begin to solve the myriad problems that it is supposedly designed to help us address.
A Buddhist moral phenomenological approach to the more-than-world would necessarily involve a spontaneous component and would therefore avoid this critique in ecological contexts. In fact, William Edelglass (2006) has made this exact case and has argued that the Buddhist concept of upāya (Tib. thabs) forms the basis for a context-specific moral pluralism in ecological settings. Similarly, Clayton (2013) has observed Tibetan Buddhists in Nova Scotia caring for their forest retreat center through a “Nothing Missing” ethic of contextual naturalness informed by the notion of tathagatagarbha (Tib. de bzhin gshegs pa) or buddha nature. Thus, both Buddhist moral phenomenology and the care ethics tradition articulate a kind of “moral perception,” to borrow the term from Gruen, wherein ethical responses emerge naturally from our direct encounter with others (Gruen 2015, p. 39).The attempt to formulate universal, rational rules of conduct ignores the constantly changing nature of reality. It also neglects the emotional-instinctive or spontaneous component in each particular situation, for in the end, emotion cannot be contained by boundaries and rules; in a single leap it can cross over the boundaries of space, time, and species. It is, I feel, the failure of most writers within environmental ethics to recognize the role of emotion that has perpetuated within the environmental ethics literature the dualistic thinking so characteristic of Western society.(Kheel 2007, p. 45, emphasis added)
In no Buddhist tradition will you find the causal matrix of pratītyasamutpāda elevated above the well-being of sentient beings. In fact, the notion of the “interconnected web” of pratītyasamutpāda (as it is sometimes called, especially in Huayen contexts) as having a “good” that can be ascribed to it is a fundamentally flawed presentation. Pratītyasamutpāda simply points to the causal matrix in which all beings and phenomena are implicated. It is ethically neutral. However, atomizing individual sentient beings and treating them as the sole arbiters of ethics would also be mistaken. Duḥkha is an interdependent phenomenon similar to any other and cannot be addressed as an isolated experience of individual sentient beings.Many holists will protest that theirs is a nonhierarchical paradigm in that everything is viewed as an integral part of an interconnected web. However, holists such as Aldo Leopold and J. Baird Callicott clearly indicate that the interconnected web does, indeed, contain its own system of ranking. Such writers have dispensed with the system of classification that assigns value to a being on the basis of its possession of certain innate characteristics, only to erect a new form of hierarchy in which individuals are valued on the basis of their relative contribution to the good of the whole (that is, the biotic community).
In the field of animal ethics, Gruen’s notion of entanglement mirrors this holistic approach as well. She writes:The concept of holism I am advocating here does not view the “whole” as composed of discrete individual beings connected by static relationships that rational analysis can comprehend and control. Rather, I am proposing a concept of holism that perceives nature… as comprising individual beings that are part of a dynamic web of interconnections in which feelings, emotions, and inclinations play an integral role.
Beyond this, Gruen’s notion of entanglement, drawing from Karen Barad’s (2007) intra-action, intimates Nāgārjuna’s notion of emptiness quite nicely. She writes:Since we necessarily exist in relation with other organisms, and since our perceptions, attitudes, and even our identities are entangled with them and our actions make their experiences go better or worse (which in turn affects our own experience), we should attend to this social/natural engagement.
Interestingly, how Gruen treats this entanglement in her ethical theory closely reflects the moral phenomenological work of bringing pratītyasamutpāda or śūnyatā into one’s default perceptual mode. In her theory, attending to this entanglement and bringing it into our perceptual field brings about empathy through a shift in affect and cognition (p. 66). Thus, both the care ethics tradition and the Tibetan Buddhist tradition recognize how the welfare of all sentient beings is bound together in a vast matrix of cause and condition, and the relationality of these beings are centered as core aspects of ethical decision-making in both.There can be no individuals that exist prior to and separate from the entangled intra-actions that constitute them. But, importantly, the individual that emerges from her entanglements is distinctly constituted by particular intra-actions. Understanding and reflection on our entanglements are part of what it takes to constitute our selves because there is no self or other prior to our intra-actions.(p. 65)
Kheel’s language here is a direct reaction to the language of J. Baird Callicott (1980) in his now-famous essay “Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair.” Callicott’s contention is that human interests, nonhuman animal interests, and ecological interests occupy distinct points on a triangle and are categorically at odds with one another. By calling the liberation of nature a “circular affair,” Kheel is instead arguing that not only must we not prioritize nonhuman animals over ecological communities (or vice versa), but that the interests of humans, nonhuman animals, and ecological communities are fundamentally related to one another. By moving away from abstract absolutes and towards an ethic which is contextualized, spontaneous, and informed by care, the exclusive prioritization of humans, nonhuman animals, or ecological communities becomes less relevant. Instead, ethical situations are approached with a holistic understanding of duḥkha informed by a deep understanding of its relationality within and across species and communities.If we allow for an element of feeling in our interactions with nature, the positions represented by these camps dissolve into different points on a circle. No point may, thus, be said to be more important than any other. The liberation of nature is, in fact, a circular affair.
This is precisely what Asaṅga did in his hagiographical narrative and is how karuṇā manifests in Tibetan Buddhist ethical contexts. For the end of moral phenomenological development, bodhicitta, to be actualized it must be applied in context-appropriate ways, and this application consists of seeking out and addressing the causes of duḥkha. Thus, the Tibetan Buddhist tradition’s karuṇā can meaningfully translated into Western ethical contexts through the notion of care as understood in the feminist tradition of care ethics.the feminist ethic-of-care tradition in animal ethics, like feminist theory in general, insists on seeking the cause for the suffering—that is, attributing blame. Indeed, the care theory we advocate goes beyond compassion to include caring enough to find out who [or what] is causing the harm and stopping it.
5. Toward a Buddhist Ecological Care Ethic
This contrasts with how environmental ethics are sometimes approached in non-ecofeminist contexts. For example, natural phenomena such as rocks and waters are ascribed intrinsic value in deep ecology and a holistic vision of land is elevated over and above its individual constituents in contemporary iterations of the land ethic. In contrast, ecofeminist approaches to the environment do not involve a change in our valuation of nature but a recognition of the nonsentient natural world’s impact on the lives of human (and nonhuman) beings.A common sight in these countries is village women walking farther every year in search of safe water and fuel for food. In such contexts, the destruction of the environment is a source of women’s oppression. The point here is not that there is a single cause of women’s oppression, or that in countries like India women’s oppression is always ecologically based… I am arguing that, in the mosaic of problems that constitute women’s oppression in a particular context, no complete account can be given that does not make reference to the connection between women and the environment. Caring for women in such a context includes caring for their environment.
Drawing from both Traditional Ecological Knowledge paradigms as well as Donna Haraway’s notion of entanglement and sympoiesis (Haraway 2016), Allison argues that “we need a feminist care ethic of climate change that recognizes the interconnected and indivisible nature of justice” (Allison 2017, p. 157). Rephrased in Buddhist terms, we might say that we need a care ethic that recognizes the interconnected nature of duḥkha and its alleviation. This ecological understanding of pratītyasamutpāda and duḥkha is also strikingly similar to Curtin’s understanding of the relationship between environmental degradation and the oppression of women in India. Curtin’s statement “caring for women includes caring for their environment” could be broadened out to say “caring for sentient beings includes caring for their environment” since the duḥkha of sentient beings (and its alleviation) depends upon myriad environmental factors.Relatedness is constitutive of all living beings, the ‘first and most basic characteristic of the human person,’ the primary and ultimate ground of all that exists. The individual is not a singular, atomistic being but a node in a web of relation. The individual cannot exist outside of the myriad relationships and communities that mutually produce, shape, and constrain the individual.
6. Contextual Moral Veganism
Thus, Shabkar recognizes the market forces behind the killing of nonhuman animals and the consequences of consuming animal products in this interdependent system. But he also frames his argument in positive terms centered around karuṇā or care. He writes:Let us imagine that there is a homestead in the vicinity of a large monastery where the monks eat meat. The inhabitants of the homestead calculate that if they kill a sheep and sell its best meat in spring to the monastic community, they will make a profit on the sheep since they will keep its tripe and offal, head, legs, and hide for themselves. And the monks, knowing full well that the sheep has been slaughtered and its meat preserved, come and buy it. The following year, the family will kill more sheep and sell the meat. And if they make a good living out of it, when the next year arrives, there will be a hundred times more animals slaughtered, and the family will get rich. Thus by trying to enrich themselves through the killing of sheep, they become butchers. They will teach this trade to their children and their grandchildren and all those close to them. And even if they do not actively teach it to others, other people will see their wicked work. They in tum will become butchers doing acts of dreadful evil, and they will set in motion a great stream of negativity that will persist until the ending of samsara. Now all this has happened for one reason only: the monastic community and others eat meat. Who therefore behaves in a more consistently evil manner than they?
Shabkar argues that if one has indeed developed bodhicitta and is operating with care as their central conative mode then abstaining from meat is the natural outcome. Shabkar’s ethical writings thus quite clearly demonstrate the positive consequences of a Buddhist ethic of care in a more-than-human world.The Buddha has defined as evil any action that directly or indirectly brings harm to beings. And since what he says is true, it is clear that the eating of meat most certainly involves more injury to beings than the consumption of any other food… I believe therefore that if one wishes to commit oneself to an ongoing habit of goodness, there is nothing better than the resolve to abstain from meat. Those few monks who do actually have compassion [Skt. karuṇā] should keep this in their hearts!(pp. 101–2)
In my estimation, this position would fairly map on to a Buddhist ecological ethic of care. While abstention from animal products may be the ideal, there may be context-specific reasons for one’s care for the more-than-human world not resulting in a strictly vegan diet.As a “contextual moral vegetarian,” I cannot refer to an absolute moral rule that prohibits meat eating under all circumstances. There may be some contexts in which another response is appropriate. Though I am committed to moral vegetarianism, I cannot say that I would never kill an animal for food. Would I not kill an animal to provide food for my son if he were starving? Would I not generally prefer the death of a bear to the death of a loved one? I am sure I would. The point of a contextualist ethic is that one need not treat all interests equally as if one had no relationship to any of the parties.
7. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Tib. sems can re re’i skyon kun sel/re re’ng yon tan mtha’ klas pa/skyed ‘dod byang chub sems mchog ste/rmad byung las kyang ‘di rmad byung. Sourced from: (khu nu bla ma bstan ‘dzin rgyal mtshan 2016, p. 7). |
2 | Tib. rten cing ‘brel bar ‘bying ba gang/de ni stong pa nyid du bshad/de ni brten nas gdags pa ste/de nyid dbu ma’I lam yin no/gang phyir rten ‘breng ma yin pa’i/chos ‘ga’ yod pa ma yin pa/de phyir strong pa ma yin pa’i/chos ‘ga’ yod pa ma yin no. Sourced from: (Nāgārjuna 2016, p. 159). |
References
- Adams, Carol J. 2007. The War on Compassion. In Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Edited by Cass R. Sunstein and Matha C. Nussbaum. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 21–36. [Google Scholar]
- Aitken, Daniel T. 2016. Experience and Morality: Buddhist Ethics as Moral Phenomenology. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Tasmania, Tasmania, Australia. [Google Scholar]
- Allison, Elizabeth. 2017. Toward a Feminist Care Ethic for Climate Change. Journal of Feminist Studies in Religion 33: 152–58. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Allison, Elizabeth. 2023. Collective responsibility and environmental caretaking: Toward an ecological care ethic with evidence from Bhutan. Ecology and Society 28: 1–8. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Asaṅga. 2018. A Feast of the Nectar of the Supreme Vehicle: An Explanation of the Ornament of the Mahāyāna Sūtras—Maitreya’s Mahāyānasūtrālamkāra with a Commentary by Jamgön Mipham. Translated by Padmakara Translation Group. Boulder: Shambhala Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Barad, Karen. 2007. Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter and Meaning. Durham: Duke University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Barstow, Geoffrey. 2017. Food of Sinful Demons: Meat, Vegetarianism, and the Limits of Buddhism in Tibet. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Barstow, Geoffrey. 2019. Canonical Precedents: The Laṅkāvatāra and Mahāparinirvāṇa Sūtras. In The Faults of Meat: Tibetan Buddhist Writings on Vegetarianism. Edited by Geoffrey Barstow. Somerville: Wisdom Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Borlée, Floor, C. Joris Yzermans, Bernadette Aalders, Jos Rooijackers, Esmeralda Krop, Catharina B. M. Maassen, François Schellevis, Bert Brunekreef, Dick Heederik, and Lidwien A. M. Smit. 2017. Air Pollution from Livestock Farms is Associated with Airway Obstruction in Neighboring Residents. American Journal of Respiratory and Critical Care Medicine 196: 1152–61. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Callicott, J. Baird. 1980. Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair. Environmental Ethics 2: 311–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Capper, Daniel. 2022. Roaming Free Like a Deer: Buddhism and the Natural World. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Central Tibet Administration. 2020. His Holiness the Dalai Lama Urges Promotion of Vegetarianism, Says the World Can’t Do Without Animals. Central Tibetan Administration. Available online: https://tibet.net/his-holiness-urges-promotion-of-vegetarianism-says-the-world-cant-do-without-animals (accessed on 30 May 2023).
- Chatral Rinpoche. 2007. Compassionate Action. Translated by Adam Pearcey. Edited by Zach Larson. Ithaca: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar]
- Cheng, Chin-Fa. 2016. Environmental Ontology in Deep Ecology and Mahāyāna Buddhism. Environmental Ethics 38: 145–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Clayton, Barbra. 2006. Moral Theory in Śantideva’s Śikṣāsamuccaya: Cultivating the Fruits of Virtue. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Clayton, Barbra. 2013. Buddha’s Maritime Nature: A Case Study in Shambhala Buddhist Environmentalism. Journal of Buddhist Ethics 20: 572–91. [Google Scholar]
- Clayton, Barbra. 2018. The Changing Way of the Bodhisattva: Superheroes, Saints, and Social Workers. In The Oxford Handbook of Buddhist Ethics. Edited by Daniel Cozort and James Mark Shields. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 135–60. [Google Scholar]
- Cromsigt, Joris P. G. M., Mariska te Beest, Graham I. H. Kerley, Marietjie Landman, Elizabeth le Roux, and Felisa A. Smith. 2018. Trophic Rewilding as a Climate Change Mitigation Strategy? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 373: 20170440. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Curtin, Deane. 1991. Toward an Ecological Care Ethic. Hypatia 6: 60–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dilgo Khyentse Rinpoche. 1992. The Heart Treasure of the Enlightened Ones. Translated by Padmakara Translation Group. Boston: Shambhala Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Donovan, Josephine, and Carol J. Adams. 2007. Introduction. In Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Edited by Cass R. Sunstein and Matha C. Nussbaum. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 1–20. [Google Scholar]
- Edelglass, William. 2006. Moral Pluralism, Skillful Means, and Environmental Ethics. Environmental Philosophy 3: 8–16. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Eisen, Michael B., and Patrick O. Brown. 2022. Rapid global phaseout of animal agriculture has the potential to stabilize greenhouse gas levels for 30 years and offset 68 percent of CO2 emissions this century. PLoS Climate 1: e0000010. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Garfield, Jay L. 2010. What is it like to be a bodhisattva? Moral phenomenology in Śantideva’s Bodhicaryāvatarā. Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 33: 333–57. [Google Scholar]
- Garfield, Jay L. 2014. Engaging Buddhism: Why It Matters to Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Garfield, Jay L. 2021. Buddhist Ethics: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gilligan, Carol. 1982. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Goodman, Charles. 2009. Consequences of Compassion: An Interpretation & Defense of Buddhist Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gruen, Lori. 2015. Entangled Empathy: An Alternative Ethic for our Relationships with Animals. New York: Lantern Books. [Google Scholar]
- Sakya, Pandita Kunga Gyaltsen. 2002. A Clear Differentiation of the Three Codes: Essential Distinctions among the Individual Liberation, Great Vehicle, and Tantric Systems. Translated by Jared Douglas Rhoton. Edited by Victoria R. M. Scott. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hall, Matthew. 2022. Empathy for Plants. Environmental Ethics 44: 121–36. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Haraway, Donna J. 2016. Staying with the Trouble: Making Kin in the Chthulucene. Durham: Duke University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Harris, Ian. 1994. Causation and Telos: The Problem of Buddhist Environmental Ethics. Journal of Buddhist Ethics 1: 45–56. [Google Scholar]
- Harris, Ian. 1997. Buddhism and the Discourse of Environmental Concern: Some Methodological Problems Considered. In Buddhism and Ecology: The Interconnection of Dharma and Deeds. Edited by Mary Evelyn Tucker and Duncan Ryūken Williams. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, pp. 377–402. [Google Scholar]
- Harvey, Peter. 2000. An Introduction to Buddhist Ethics: Foundations, Values and Issues. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Henning, Daniel H. 2000. Buddhism and Deep Ecology. Bloomington: AuthorHouse Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hopkins, Jeffrey. 2007. Nāgārjuna’s Precious Garland: Buddhist Advice for Living and Liberation. Boulder: Snow Lion Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Jamieson, Dale. 1998. Animal Liberation is an Environmental Ethic. Environmental Values 17: 41–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Karmapa, Orgyen Trinley Dorje. 2007. Talk on Vegetarianism. Paper presented at the 24th Annual Great Kagyu Monlam, Bodhgaya, India, January 3; Available online: http://www.shabkar.org/download/pdf/Talk_on_Vegetarianism.pdf (accessed on 30 May 2023).
- Kheel, Marti. 2007. The Liberation of Nature: A Circular Affair. In The Feminist Care Tradition in Animal Ethics. Edited by Josephine Donovan and Carol J. Adams. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 39–57. [Google Scholar]
- khu nu bla ma bstan ‘dzin rgyal mtshan. 2016. byang chub sems kyi bstod pa rin chen sgron me dang. BDRC: W1KG25183. Lha sa: Ser gtsug nang bstan dpe rnying ‘tshol bsdu phyogs sgrig khang. [Google Scholar]
- Kim, Brent F., Raychel E. Santo, Allysan P. Scatterday, Jillian P. Fry, Colleen M. Synk, Shannon R. Cebron, Mesfin M. Mekonnen, Arjen Y. Hoekstra, Saskia de Pee, Martin W. Bloem, and et al. 2020. Country-specific dietary shifts to mitigate climate and water crises. Global Environmental Change 62: 101926. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kongtrul, Jamgön, and Lodrö Thayé. 2008. The Treasury of Knowledge: Book Eight, Part Three: The Elements of Tantric Practice. Translated by Kalu Rinpoche Translation Group. Edited by Ingrid McLeod. Boston: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar]
- Locke, Jessica. 2018. Training the Mind and Transforming Your World: Moral Phenomenology in the Tibetan Buddhist Lojong Tradition. Comparative and Continental Philosophy 10: 251–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Main, Jessica L., and Rongdao Lai. 2013. Introduction: Reformulating ‘Socially Engaged Buddhism’ as an Analytical Category. The Eastern Buddhist 44: 1–34. [Google Scholar]
- Mason, Jim. 1993. An Unnatural Order: Uncovering the Roots of Our Domination of Nature and Each Other. New York: Simon & Schuster. [Google Scholar]
- Mekonnen, Mesfin M., and Arjen Y. Hoekstra. 2012. A Global Assessment of the Water Footprint of Farm Animal Products. Ecosystems 15: 401–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nāgārjuna. 2016. The Root Stanzas of the Middle Way: The Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. Translated by Padmakara Translation Group. Boulder: Shambhala Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Noddings, Nel. 1984. Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nussbaum, Martha C. 2004. Beyond ‘Compassion and Humanity’: Justice for Nonhuman Animals. In Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Edited by Cass R. Sunstein and Matha C. Nussbaum. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Patrul Rinpoche. 2011. Words of My Perfect Rinpoche. Translated by Padmakara Translation Group. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plumwood, Val. 1993. Feminism and the Mastery of Nature. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Poore, Joseph, and Thomas Nemecek. 2018. Reducing food’s environmental impacts through producers and consumers. Science 360: 987–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Powys White, Kyle, and Chris J. Cuomo. 2017. Ethics of Caring in Environmental Ethics: Indigenous and Feminist Philosophies. In The Oxford Handbook of Environmental Ethics. Edited by Stephen M. Gardiner and Allen Thompson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 234–47. [Google Scholar]
- Queen, Christopher S. 2003. Introduction: From Altruism to Activism. In Action Dharma: New Studies in Engaged Buddhism. Edited by Christopher S. Queen, Charles Prebish and Damien Keown. New York: Routledge Curzon, pp. 1–35. [Google Scholar]
- Shabkar, Tsogdruk Rangdrol. 2008. Food of Bodhisattvas: Buddhist Teachings on Abstaining from Meat. Translated by Padmakara Translation Group. New Delhi: Shechen Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Rao, Sailesh. 2021. Animal Agriculture is the Leading Cause of Climate Change—A Position Paper. Journal of Ecological Society 33: 155–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ruddick, Sara. 1989. Maternal Thinking: Toward a Politics of Peace. Boston: Beacon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schmithausen, Lambert. 1997. The Early Buddhist Tradition and Ecological Ethics. Journal of Buddhist Ethics 4: 1–74. [Google Scholar]
- Sejian, Veerasamy, Iqbal Hyder, T. Ezeji, Jeffrey Lakritz, Raghavendra Bhatta, J. P. Ravindra, Cadaba S. Prasad, and Rattan Lal. 2015. Global Warming: Role of Livestock. In Climate Change Impact on Livestock: Adaptation and Mitigation. Edited by Veerasamy Sejian, John Gaughan, Lance Baumgard and Cadaba Prasad. New Delhi: Springer, pp. 141–69. [Google Scholar]
- Simonds, Colin H. 2021a. Buddhist Ethics as Moral Phenomenology: A Defense and Development of the Theory. Journal of Buddhist Ethics 28: 339–402. [Google Scholar]
- Simonds, Colin H. 2021b. This Precious Human Life: Human Exceptionalism and Altruism in Tibetan Buddhism. Worldviews 25: 239–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Simonds, Colin H. 2022. Moral Phenomenology in a More-Than-Human World: A New Approach to Buddhist Environmental Ethics. Ph.D. dissertation, Queen’s University at Kingston, Kingston, ON, Canada. [Google Scholar]
- Simonds, Colin H. 2023a. Ethical Veganism as Moral Phenomenology: Engaging Buddhism with Animal Ethics. Journal of Animal Ethics 13: 48–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Simonds, Colin H. 2023b. Lta sgom spyod gsum: A Tibetan Approach to Moral Phenomenological Praxis. Journal of Buddhist Ethics 30: 93–137. [Google Scholar]
- Simonds, Colin H. 2023c. The Trouble of Rocks and Waters: On the (Im)Possibility of a Buddhist Environmental Ethic. Environmental Ethics, 45, in press. [Google Scholar]
- Singer, Peter. 1975. Animal Liberation: A New Ethics for Our Treatment of Animals. New York: Avon Book. [Google Scholar]
- Smyer Yü, Dan. 2023. Freeing Animals: Sino-Tibetan Buddhist Environmentalism and Ecological Challenges. Religions 14: 110. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tronto, Joan C. 1993. Moral Boundaries: A Political Argument for an Ethic of Care. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Vetesse, Troy, and Drew Pendergrass. 2022. Half-Earth Socialism: A Plan to Save the Future from Extinction, Climate Change, and Pandemics. London: Verso Books. [Google Scholar]
- Victor, Karen, and Antoni Barnard. 2016. Slaughtering for a living: A hermeneutical phenomenological perspective on the well-being of slaughterhouse employees. International Journal of Qualitative Studies in Health and Well-Being 11: 30266. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wasley, Andrew, and Alexandra Heal. 2018. Revealed: Shocking Safety Records of UK Meat Plants. London: The Bureau of Investigative Journalism. Available online: https://www.thebureauinvestigates.com/stories/2018-07-29/uk-meat-plant-injuries (accessed on 30 May 2023).
- Wing, Steve, Dana Cole, and Gary Grant. 2000. Environmental Injustice in North Carolina’s Hog Industry. Environmental Health Perspectives 108: 225–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Simonds, C.H. Toward a Buddhist Ecological Ethic of Care. Religions 2023, 14, 893. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070893
Simonds CH. Toward a Buddhist Ecological Ethic of Care. Religions. 2023; 14(7):893. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070893
Chicago/Turabian StyleSimonds, Colin Harold. 2023. "Toward a Buddhist Ecological Ethic of Care" Religions 14, no. 7: 893. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070893
APA StyleSimonds, C. H. (2023). Toward a Buddhist Ecological Ethic of Care. Religions, 14(7), 893. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070893