Being as Absolute Beginning: Metaphysical Considerations Regarding the Gifted Character of Being Ex Nihilo
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Value of the Thomistic Donation Essendi in the Question about Being
3. The Donated Nature of Being Ex Nihilo as Absolute Acceptio Esse and Personal Being as Being Ex Deo
In these lines, we find the thesis that giving involves from a free being, so that such an action pertains to what is most peculiar in the giver: its intimacy. A gift is so because it is donated, so that donation can be construed as the character of personal beings, as their radical way of existence according to their being a gifted act, which implies gratuity, that is, no less than an unprecedented giving (González 2013, p. 45).“The phenomenology of the pure gift -Haya writes- describes the manifestation of a reality that is not contained in its precedent conditions insofar as it has none. An absolute gift is no gift if it is contained in the giver, in such a fashion that its being consists only in its deployment or being made explicit. In turn, absolute giving, as an action, is essentially free and gratuitous, in the sense that no necessity constricts either the giver or the giving itself, and the giver is only one insofar as we consider the act of giving itself.”
4. From Absolute Beginning to Absolute Dependence: The Metaphysical Dynamic of the Gifted Act of Being (Acceptio Esse)
“The paradox of the (donatio essendi) is that its dependency is what constitutes (being ex nihilo) insofar as it is an activity, insofar as it is an act, because as its dependency is absolute, it is equivalent to its keeping in existence, not being ultimately constituted, or sufficiently. Creating is not producing something that is already enough, because the dependency would then be broken. Creation has to be something continuous and instantaneous. The demand for a continuation (to being) does not impact God: it is a demand for the creature. Every neediness of (being ex nihilo) is, in this fashion, activity: the creation demands to be ‘kept in existence’, which is precisely its energeia or activity. Thus, God is also given the name Primary Activity or Pure Act.”
5. Conclusions
- Metaphysical nihilism can only be overcome when philosophy welcomes an understanding of finite being that, as ex nihilo, excludes nothingness. In order to do so, we can face the question of the existence of reality and its own actuality based on the metaphysics of the gift. In the first place, the origination of being ex nihilo as donatio essendi, and then towards a reflection on finite being as given and absolute beginning.
- The origin of the finite being should be described as absolute donation. The reason is that it allows us to think of finite being as radical novelty and absolute benefit, with no trace of passivity, ambiguity, or ontological nihilism. In the donatio essendi, the gifted being is in no way existent prior to the given. The nature of giving implies producing or doing what is given, i.e., giving what the given is not previously. In an absolute donation, the gift is “generated” as it is given; being as absolute donation means being-given. The notion of absolute gift through donatio essendi is inseparable from the character of given, a character that defines and determines it. That is why the metaphysics of the gift is so appropriate to determine the ontological character of being ex nihilo as absolute acceptio esse.
- The real communication of being as donatio essendi allows us to consider its radicality through its gratuitousness and freedom. Thus, the origination of finite beings is real communication because it is a real and absolute donation. The very notion of donatio essendi permits the safekeeping of divine freedom because communicating being ex nihilo does not imply a real ad extra relation in God. Consequently, the absolute gratuitousness of creation becomes an absolute benefit.
- The idea of donatio essendi points to the ex nihilo giving of an existence whose perfection is set in its reference to Another, in giving itself. This is the plenitude of the gifted being. As gifted, being ex nihilo is not static, but intrinsically temporal, insofar as gifted being is temporal, because giving being is not limited (on God’s part) to “placing” being. It is donating the gift, or rather, donating the giving.
- The existential value of the principle of noncontradiction is the persistence in noncontradictory activity, which means that we should reject any meaning of possible activity to just affirm the equivalence of being ex nihilo and noncontradiction as activity, precisely in terms of its gifted nature. This implies the rejection of a real equivalence, according to the principle of noncontradiction, between being and nothingness. The idea of existence as “opposed to” nothingness or “non-existence” should also be disregarded, insofar as it is an opposition of reason. On the contrary, the principle of noncontradiction, as real extramental principle, is the noncontradictory existence, i.e., being ex nihilo.
- The donated act is diverse and not opposite to the Original being. It is in this sense that we claim that being ex nihilo is first, and that is why its activity should be understood as beginning, which entails its radical novelty: being ex nihilo, as position extra nihilum, is a form of existence that premieres as beginning. A being that begins is “first” not in the sense of originary, but as absolute beginning, because nothing precedes or follows being ex nihilo. It cannot be compared with anything that exists like it does, as it is secondary to nothing (it is extra nihilum, not extra causam).
- Being ex nihilo is not the kind of being whose activity resolves in becoming free of nothingness in order to continue being. Being ex nihilo, rather, means distinguishing itself radically from nothingness; on the other hand, it is extra nihilum only insofar as it is ad extra regarding God. In other words, as nothingness is nothing, being ex nihilo consists in getting rid of nothingness by differentiating itself from it, which in a positive sense means being donated by an absolute giving (donatio essendi). The ad extra existence of the donatio essendi should therefore be understood as a distinction, not exteriority. This distinction excludes all comparisons: it is no determination or category of gifted being that allows for a comparison with the Giver, with which he is not linked in any causal or relational sense. For gifted being, its existence is not a proper determination that is previous to being gifted, and hence comparable to the Being that is its own being, but rather its reality as lacking its own being, which points towards its determination as being-given (this is what its gifted nature means).
- The activity of being ex nihilo as gifted is not centered in rejecting nothingness but in being-dependent-beginning, i.e., transcendental beginning and absolute dependency on its Origin. This is the proper activity of finite being, characterized here by the principles of noncontradiction and causality. Being ex nihilo is absolute beginning and dependence, which is the way in which a finite being is dependent, as donated by an absolute donation. Being as beginning is being received as gifted, not as caused or produced, and therefore being towards and for another: an existence that refers to another.
- The donatio essendi is an absolute reception of being (esse), as Aquinas claims, and that reception grounds its being an absolute reference and dependence to the Giver. Being subsistent as an absolute gift: this means being an absolute donation. A personal being becomes an absolute donation by accepting and destinating itself, which is its own activity as gifted personal being. This makes it ex Deo rather than ex nihilo: it distinguishes itself more from the Creator than from nothingness (as, properly speaking, nothingness does not actually exist). As ex Deo, personal gifted being has a natural order with regards to nothingness, which determines it as a dependent being, but its personal nature allows for an increase in its donating activity in receiving its own being as its acceptance and donating itself through destinating itself. Its plenitude lies here.
- Through the metaphysics of the gift, a metaphysical understanding of reality can actually acquire the full positivity that is proper to being, one which was lost throughout the history of philosophy. As such, donatio essendi is the theme of the absolute communication and coexistence of two different kinds of being: Original being and originated being. The principiality of originated being rests in its novelty, and beginning being ex nihilo should therefore be characterized, above all, by centering our attention on these two parameters, as beginning and as novelty. Only then, without assuming anything about being, can metaphysics take a step forward to hold that the absence of anything previous explains what being lacks: no thing is its own existence. This lacking, its real distinction, manifests that being, for each thing, is its reference, that is, its dependence. Novelty and dependence are, therefore, the two attributes that define the nature of the gifted character of existence, in its utmost comprehension.
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | This crisis is not only experienced within the realm of experimental and human sciences, nor is it only an ethical crisis—whether collectively or individually understood—but rather a personal crisis of meaning. Moreover, we must assert that human beings are in a state of constant tension, of permanent crisis, which has to do, among other reasons, with the fact that the spiritual condition of man translates into a capacity for unyielding, limitless growth. The possibility for growth—and lessening—of man manifests our condition of the proper and constitutive crisis of human beings. See (Vargas 2017; Zorroza 2019). |
2 | It is important to point out that the crisis Husserl refers to is not one of science itself regarding its capacity to attain its objects through its proper method (whether it is a physical science or a science of mind): “The scientific rigor of all these disciplines, the convincingness of their theoretical accomplishments, and their enduringly compelling successes are unquestionable” (Husserl 1976); A similar idea may be found in (Zubiri 1994, pp. 27–57). |
3 | “At any rate, the contrast between the “scientific” character of this group of sciences and the “unscientific” character of philosophy is unmistakable” (Husserl 1976, The Crisis, cit., pp. 4–5). |
4 | Derrida will suggest the necessity of moving beyond Heidegger’s failed deconstruction of metaphysics towards one of language itself, as its structure secures the very origin of metaphysics. It is, however, a deconstruction more rightly understood as de-sedimentation rather than demolition. See (Derrida 1967, pp. 21–24); see also (Inciarte and Llano 2007, pp. 28, 121–31). Regarding radical Hermeneutics, cf. (Miguel 2010, pp. 55–75); and (Gadamer 1975). |
5 | In Aquinas’ ontology, the principle of a creature, the proprium esse of each thing, turns every being into a perfection insofar as it makes it be so; that is to say, the proper esse of a being is the perfection of such a being, and not just one among many other constituents. Cf. S. Th., I, q. 4, a. 1, ad 3. Cfr. S. Th., I, q. 3, a. 4; In Sent., I, d. 8, q. 1, a. 1. In this respect, Alejandro Llano properly holds that “the act of being is the immanent origin of the plenitude of each being according to its proper essence. That is why the nobility of each thing arouses from its being. When Thomas Aquinas repeatedly holds that the esse of each thing is its perfection, he is not just pointing out—as a limited sense of ‘perfectio’ might suggest—that it is limit, the definitive realization of something that is coming-to-be. In a metaphysical sense, ‘perfectio’ means positivity, goodness, plenitude, value, in their most radical meaning.” (Llano 1984, p. 295). Regarding the intelligible nature of reality according to Thomistic metaphysics, see (Ramos 2014, pp. 95–111). |
6 | Indeed, if finite being is necessarily ex nihilo, we can establish the classic problems of being in what Zubir rightly calls the “horizon of nihility”. Zubiri himself traces his About the Problem of Philosophy around this plan, dedicating its fifth chapter to “the horizon of Western philosophy: creation and nihility” (Zubiri 1996, pp. 3 y 30). |
7 | |
8 | This quotation is taken from (Inciarte and Llano 2007, p. 349); it translates an expression from Husserl, E., Vorgegeben Welt, Historizität, Trieb, Instinkt (Ms. 1934, Sign. E III 10, p. 18), y citado por S. Strasser, “Das Gottesproblem in der Spätphilosophie Edmund Husserls”, Philosophisches Jahrbuch, 67 (1958), p. 142. |
9 | Our task becomes, then, a metaphysical understanding; in Zubiri’s words, “creation is now, in the concrete, an ‘origination of being’ (…), a radical origin from what is not being, from nothingness. Being is always not-nothingness, it is creatio ex nihilo” (Zubiri 1996, op. cit., p. 47). |
10 | S. Th., I, q. 28, a. 1, ad 3; see also De causis, lect. XI. Translations of the Summa theologiae are taken from the 1920 edition by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province, available online at www.newadvent.org/summa (accessed on 6 May 2020) (ed. Kevin Knight). |
11 | In the same line of the metaphysics of the gift, Angel Luis González claims that “the highest sense of being is precisely gifting” (González 2013, p. 49). Indeed, as pointed out by Haya and Gonzalez, personal being has more to do with giving than with that which is given: what is given, gifts, belong to the essence, while being is giving. The origin of this metaphysical view is in Leonardo Polo, who, in his study Having and gifting (Tener y dar), suggests that a human person is not only nor specifically defined as a being capable of having, but rather he is personal because, while endorsing having, he is capable of gifting. That is why, against the question of what lies beyond our tendency to possess and possession itself, Polo answers the following: “Obviously, donation. If the activity of the Will is donating, it transcends what the Greeks understood as télos: this is a Christian hyperteleology. Gifting is giving without losing, an activity that is above a balance of wins and loses, winning without acquiring or acquiring while giving” (Polo 2015c, pp. 229–30). Thus, the personal created being consists in gifting: gifting gifts, not gifting itself, for gifting as such belongs exclusively to God, as only he can donate existence, which cannot be confused with the given (the essence). |
12 | “Creare autem est dare esse”; In Sent., I, d. 37, q. 1, a. 1, sol. Cfr. In Sent., I, d. 7, q. 1, a. 1, ad 3; In Sent., II, d. 1, q. 1, a. 2, ad 2; S. Th., I, q. 9, a. 2, sol.; q. 104, a. 1, ad 4. In line with these considerations, I hold that any investigation into the meaning of creation as gifting demands that our metaphysical viewpoint is extended to anthropology, as gifting is a free action that is proper to personal beings, and the only accessible freedom to our natural understanding is the one of the personal human being. In the same way, Trinitarian theology itself makes use of our analysis of the personal created being, only then being able to analogously consider divine personal relations. |
13 | See (de Aquino 2005b, Super Io., cap. 1, l. 5, n. 133). Polo comments that “when Aquinas says creatio est donatio essendi, he is no longer regarding being in the order of grounding: he augments the causal view. When you gift something, you are not grounding; gifting goes beyond grounding. That is to say: being is; it is not caused or made, but rather given. Which is more proper of creation: making being or gifting being? (…) Gifting, insofar as gifted, is in the order of coexistence.” (Polo 1993, p. 175). |
14 | Regarding human freedom in Aquinas’ thought, cfr. (Peiró and Zorroza 2014, pp. 435–49). |
15 | Cfr. De Pot., q. 3, a. 4, sol.; C. G., II, cap. 15. |
16 | “Creatio active significat actionem divinam, quae est eius essentia cum relatione ad creaturam”; S. Th., I, q. 45, a. 3, ad 1, but this is a relation of reason. |
17 | We should note that a metaphysics of totality allows no intensification: it is a closed system that depends on making explicit what is already implicitly present. Cfr. (Haya 1997, op. cit., p. 315). The intensification of being, on the other hand, is always inside a finite order, for the domain of donated being can be a greater and better remission to the Origin (never in identifying with it). The perfection of gifted being does not consist in it stopping being donated, nor in its falling into nothingness, nor in the sense that its perfection lies in “divinizing” itself, so as to be confused with divine being. To the metaphysical view of creation as donatio essendi, against Hegelian dialectics, the overcoming of the limitations of created being, as distinct to the divine being, cannot be solved in the confusion of the created and the divine, but rather in intensifying its own being created qua created, which implies a greater sharpness in its distinction from uncreated being. For a creature, “being more” means to be a better creature. |
18 | We could say that being finite as donated and dependence is what Aquinas calls being by participation. The Thomistic doctrine of participation in being, one of whose manifestations is the real distinction between being and essence, sets the real state of the creature in the metaphysical consideration of the real composition of beings. It is through the real distinction that Aquinas achieves an explanation for the authenticity of the created being as an act by participation without its disollution in the divine Being. Only God is its own Being; in everything else, being differs from the essence. Cfr. S. Th. I, q. 61, a. 1, sol. |
19 | Cfr. In Sent., I, d. 5, q. 2, a. 2, sol. Cfr. S. Th., I, q. 45, a. 1, ad 3; q. 46, a. 2, ad 2; In Sent., II, d. 1, q. 1, a. 2, sol. |
20 | In the realm of reason, the principle of noncontradiction is a certain prelude to the idea of nothingness, which is a being of reason. In reality, however, nothingness should be understood as “to cease” or “being followed” by absolute beginning. Not ceasing points directly to the Origin insofar as in beings; the act of being is really distinct from the essence and, because it is caused, can be investigated without mentally determining it or making it dependent on the essence. This ultimately means that, for created beings, the lacking of themselves and the nature of dependence are intrinsically linked. In other words, radical beginning shows radical dependence, because persisting in beginning is imposible without radical dependence. Cfr. (Polo 2015b, op. cit., p. 207). |
References
- de Aquino, Tomas. 2001. De potentia Dei, cuestión 3. La creación. Edited by Ángel Luis González and Enrique Moros. Cuadernos de Anuario Filosófico, Serie Universitaria 128. Pamplona: Servicio de Publicaciones de la Universidad de Navarra. [Google Scholar]
- de Aquino, Tomas. 2005a. Comentario a las Sentencias de Pedro Lombardo, II/1: La creación: ángeles, seres corpóreos, hombre (II, d1-20). Edited by Juan Cruz Cruz. Pamplona: Eunsa. [Google Scholar]
- de Aquino, Tomas. 2005b. Sobre el Verbo. Comentario al prólogo del Evangelio de San Juan. Edited by Juan Fernando Sellés. Pamplona: Eunsa. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1967. De la Grammatologie. Paris: Les Éditions de Minuit. [Google Scholar]
- Fabro, Cornelio. 2009. Participación y causalidad según Tomás de Aquino. Pamplona: Eunsa. [Google Scholar]
- Falgueras, Ignacio. 1997. Crisis y renovación de la Metafísica. Málaga: Uma Editorial. [Google Scholar]
- Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 1975. Wahrheit und Methode. Grundzüge einer philosophischen Hermeneutik (Verdad y método. Fundamentos de una hermenéutica filosófica: Sígueme). Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck). [Google Scholar]
- García, Juan A. 2014. El tiempo como indicio de existencia. In Escritos en memoria de Leonardo Polo. Ser y conocer I. Cuadernos de Pensamiento Español. Pamplona: Servicio de Publicaciones de la Universidad de Navarra, pp. 57–58. [Google Scholar]
- García-Valdecasas, Miguel. 1998. Límite e identidad. La culminación de la filosofía en Hegel y Polo. Cuadernos de Anuario Filosófico, Serie de Filosofía Española 6. Pamplona: Servicio de Publicaciones de la Universidad de Navarra. [Google Scholar]
- González, Ángel Luis. 2013. Persona, libertad, don. Lección inaugural del curso académico 2013–14. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra. [Google Scholar]
- Haya, Fernando. 1997. El ser personal. De Tomás de Aquino a la metafísica del don. Pamplona: Eunsa. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1927. Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag, (El ser y el tiempo. 1967. FCE.). [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, Edmund. 1976. Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die Transzendentale Phänomenologie. Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff, (In English, The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology. Translated by David Carr. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1970, p. 4). [Google Scholar]
- Inciarte, Fernando, and Alejandro Llano. 2007. Metafísica tras el final de la Metafísica. Madrid: Cristiandad. [Google Scholar]
- Kerr, Gaven. 2019. Aquinas and the Metaphysics of Creation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Llano, Alejandro. 1984. Metafísica y lenguaje. Pamplona: Eunsa. [Google Scholar]
- Miguel, Cirilo Flórez. 2010. La tradición hermenéutica en el siglo XX. Revista Internacional de Filosofía 50: 55–75. [Google Scholar]
- Pangallo, Mario. 1991. Il principio di causalità nella metafísica di S. Tommaso. Saggio di ontología tomista alla luce dell’interpretazione di Cornelio Fabro. Roma: Pontificia Academia di S. Tommaso. [Google Scholar]
- Peiró, Juliana. 2014. La distinción criatura-Creador como máxima distinción metafísica. In Comunicación en las LI Reuniones Filosóficas. Metafísica del Logos: Conocimiento de sí y automanifestación. Hermenéutica medieval. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra. [Google Scholar]
- Peiró, Juliana. 2020. Ser y nada. Consideraciones metafísicas en torno a la noción tomista de positio extra nihilum. In Red de Investigaciones Filosóficas SCIO. Valencia: Ediciones Universidad Católica de Valencia. [Google Scholar]
- Peiró, Juliana, and Idoya Zorroza. 2014. La noción de libertad como causa sui en Tomás de Aquino. Cauriensia 9: 435–49. [Google Scholar]
- Pérez-Guerrero, Javier. 1996. La creación como asimilación a Dios. Un estudio desde Tomás de Aquino. Pamplona: Eunsa. [Google Scholar]
- Piá, Salvador. 1996. De la criatura a Dios. La demostración de la existencia de Dios en la primera dimensión del abandono del límite mental. Anuario Filosófico 29: 929–48. [Google Scholar]
- Polo, Leonardo. 1991. El conocimiento habitual de los primeros principios. In Cuadernos de Anuario Filosófico, Serie Universitaria 10. Pamplona: Servicio de Publicaciones de la Universidad de Navarra. [Google Scholar]
- Polo, Leonardo. 1993. Presente y futuro del hombre. Madrid: Rialp. [Google Scholar]
- Polo, Leonardo. 2015a. El acceso al ser. Obras Completas, II. Pamplona: Eunsa. [Google Scholar]
- Polo, Leonardo. 2015b. El ser I: La existencia extramental. Obras completas, III. Pamplona: Eunsa. [Google Scholar]
- Polo, Leonardo. 2015c. Tener, dar, esperar. In Filosofía y economía, Obras Completas, XXV. Pamplona: Eunsa. [Google Scholar]
- Polo, Leonardo. 2016. Antropología transcendental. Obras Completas, XV. Pamplona: Eunsa. [Google Scholar]
- Ramos, Alice. 2014. A Metaphysics of the Logos in St. Thomas Aquinas: Creation and Knowledge. Cauriensia XIX: 95–111. [Google Scholar]
- Soto-Bruna, Ma J. 2002. La criatura como distinción. Studia Poliana 4: 141–65. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vargas, Alberto I. 2017. Genealogía del miedo. Un estudio antropológico de la modernidad desde L. Polo. Cuadernos de pensamiento español. Pamplona: Servicio de publicaciones de la Universidad de Navarra. [Google Scholar]
- Vargas, Alberto I. 2020. Ser y don. Una Teoría Antropológica del Juego. Madrid: Sindéresis. [Google Scholar]
- Verdú, Ignacio. 2019. Amor y metafísica. Una reflexión acerca de la filosofía primera. Cauriensia XIV: 117–30. [Google Scholar]
- Zorroza, Idoya. 2019. Nuestra ‘situación meta-física’. Cauriensia XIV: 131–37. [Google Scholar]
- Zubiri, Xavier. 1994. Nuestra situación intelectual. In Naturaleza, historia, Dios. Madrid: Editora Nacional. [Google Scholar]
- Zubiri, Xavier. 1996. Sobre el problema de la filosofía. Madrid: Fundación Xavier Zubiri, pp. 3 y 30. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Peiró Pérez, J. Being as Absolute Beginning: Metaphysical Considerations Regarding the Gifted Character of Being Ex Nihilo. Religions 2023, 14, 310. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14030310
Peiró Pérez J. Being as Absolute Beginning: Metaphysical Considerations Regarding the Gifted Character of Being Ex Nihilo. Religions. 2023; 14(3):310. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14030310
Chicago/Turabian StylePeiró Pérez, Juliana. 2023. "Being as Absolute Beginning: Metaphysical Considerations Regarding the Gifted Character of Being Ex Nihilo" Religions 14, no. 3: 310. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14030310
APA StylePeiró Pérez, J. (2023). Being as Absolute Beginning: Metaphysical Considerations Regarding the Gifted Character of Being Ex Nihilo. Religions, 14(3), 310. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14030310