On the Fiercely Debated Questions of a Chinese Metaphysics and a Tradition of Early Daoism: Western and Chinese Perspectives on the Daodejing and Huang-Lao Daoism
Abstract
:1. Enter the Early Chinese Excavated Manuscripts
2. Western Perspectives on Chinese Metaphysics
If it makes sense to talk about “Chinese” metaphysics, however, then there are at least two presuppositions on a conceptual level that go with it: (1) the adjective introduces a dividing line emphasizing that “Chinese” metaphysics is different from non-Chinese metaphysics (…); (2) yet calling both “metaphysics,” the dividing line also relates what is differentiated as “Chinese” and “non-Chinese.” There can be no difference without at least one commonality in the respect of which the differentiated is what it purports to be, different. The first presupposition is that which most scholars who use the expression wish to emphasize, i.e., the distinctiveness of “Chinese metaphysics.” But the second presupposition, i.e., the commonality shared with other metaphysics, is almost systematically ignored.
Where is “The Dao”? Where is “The One”? What we experience is manifestly multiple, changing, multidirectional; so this One must be an invisible reality beyond our perceptual reach—accessible only to some special faculty like speculative reason, dialectic, or, alternately, mystical intuition or religious experience—or something that happened back at the beginning of time when everything was being “produced.” It sounds immediately as if all this is something that happened or happens behind the curtain, the deep intelligible structure of the world, the source or underlying principle that directs, controls or commands the empirical world.
What is the subject matter of metaphysics? Can the subject matter of Chinese metaphysics be totally different from that of Western? If not, as some have insisted, then, the proper subject matter, as the term “ontology” itself implies, can only be being and its equivalents in the Indio-European languages (to on in Greek, esse in Latin, and Sein, être, etc. in modern Western languages). The challenge to the Chinese is that since there was no term equivalent to “being” in ancient Chinese, there could consequently not be “a science of being” in ancient China.
“Only becoming is.” “Being” and “not-being” are not available as possibilities that would occur to these early thinkers. Said another way around, because the determinate and indeterminate—youwu 有無—are always mutually entailing correlatives, there is no such thing as “not-being” as a gaping void or an absolute nothingness, and no such thing as “being” as something that is independently permanent and unchanging. Wu is aspectual language that describes an emptiness within the bounds of determinate yet changing form captured in the term “empty” (zhong 盅) as in an empty vessel and describes an undulating, inchoate state of indeterminacy reflected in the term “surging” (chong 沖)—wu as the as yet unformed penumbra that honeycombs each of the myriad things and that explains the emergence of novel determinacy in the ceaseless process of transformation. And you describes a persistent yet always changing determinate pattern within the flux and flow of experience.
A distinct difference between a genealogical and a metaphysical cosmogony is that where the latter entails the intervention of some external creative source that establishes a “One-behind-the-Many” idealistic and teleologically driven metaphysics, the genealogical cosmogony always entails two elements in the creative process that needs must collaborate in conception and procreation without appeal to some external source. A second fundamental difference is that whereas metaphysical cosmogonies promise increased illumination as we trace back to and understand the ultimate source, a genealogical cosmogony describes a birthing from an inchoate, incipient life form that presupposes genealogy and progenitors rather than originative principles or divine design, and a pattern of always-situated and cultivated growth in significance rather than the linear actualization of some predetermined potential. Hence, unlike some traditional Western cosmogonies that usher us back to the source of an intelligibility that has deliberately overcome chaos and has established order, Chinese natural cosmogonies direct us back to what, from our present perspective, is a world wherein the further back we go in the birthing canal, the more dark, amorphous, and remote it becomes for us.
3. Chinese Perspectives on Huang-Lao Metaphysics
As defined, the Judeo-Christian conception of God, Aristotle’s Unmoved Mover, and Plato’s Forms as well as the Huang-Lao conception of the natural order are all transcendent. But clearly Dao is not God, and Huang-Lao is not Plato. A further distinction needs to be drawn between transcendence in a strong sense (chaojue 超绝) and a weak sense (chaoyue 超越). The former suggests a radical ontological disparity or separation. The creatio ex nihilo cosmogonic paradigm of Genesis, in which God, ontologically distinct and temporally prior to the world, creates the world out of nothing is perhaps the clearest example. The interpretation of Plato’s Forms as external, existing in some ontologically independent realm, would be another instance of the strong sense, whereas the reading of Aristotle’s universals as indwelling, internal to phenomena, though still teleologically predetermining, would be an example of the weak sense. Huang-Lao advances transcendence of the weak sense (in) that it does not, therefore, entail a radical ontological separation between the source of the determining order and the human realm that complies with this order.
First and most importantly, the meaning of Dao and De, which is at the core of philosophical Daoism, is consistent with “the study of the beyond form” (xingershang) in the ancient Chinese sense, as it is told in the “Xici” commentary on the Book of Change (易經·系辭): “That which goes beyond form is termed Dao (形而上者謂之道).” This is because philosophical Daoism is a philosophical system that goes beyond you (having form and name) and focuses on wu (formless and nameless). From a philosophical point of view, the theory of Dao and the theory of De in Daoist texts are metaphysical theories in the ancient Chinese sense, that is, the “study of what is beyond form.” In fact, there is no other theory that befits the name.
In summary, our consideration of the nature of philosophical Daoism references the study of metaphysics, i.e., theories of being qua being in ancient Greece. There are aspects of Daoist philosophy that are similar to the metaphysics of the ancient Greeks, but it also departs from the study of physical objects more radically, as Dao is not delimited by form or defined by words. This is the most important interpretive key for understanding philosophical Daoism.
A central factor in all Huang-Lao and early Daoist thinking is the notion of oneness—also called Great Oneness or Dao—as representative of the highest ultimate of the universe and the most fundamental principle of the world. One is not only the original number that gives meaning to all objects, but also the original cosmic state at the beginning of time. And just as “one” is closely related to all other numbers and the many, so original oneness remains forever connected to the multiplicity of the world and the myriad beings. This understanding in due course leads to the apperception of oneness as a central metaphysical concept, a highly abstract notion, an absolute value that provides an inherent commonality and universality among the unlimited multitude of existence. The relation of the one to the many, then, is the core model of Huang-Lao thinking in its effort at comprehending the world and its beings.”
4. Modern Perspectives on Huang-Lao Daoism
Yue Chenggong studied the teachings of Huangdi and Laozi [i.e., Huang-Lao], and his important teacher was called Heshang Zhangren, but it is unknown from where he came. Heshang Zhangren was the teacher of An Qisheng, An Qisheng was the teacher of Maoxi Gong, Maoxi Gong was the teacher of Yuexia Gong, Yuexia Gong was the teacher of Yue Chengong, Yue Chengong was the teacher of Gao Gong. Gao Gong taught in the regions of Gaomi and Jiaoxi in the state of Qi, and he was the teacher of Cao of the state of Xiang.(Shiji 80.2427–2437)
This term, which first appears in the Shiji but is never defined therein, has become a philosophical football in which modern scholars invent their own traditions by combining whatever texts meet their chosen criteria. Setting aside the question of whether there was a philosophical tradition known as Huang-Lao, and not just a set of diffuse and ill-defined tendencies, it is significant that the majority of the figures to whom Sima Qian applies the term were not scholars at all but political figures.
There are many points of controversy surrounding Huang-Lao, not least of which concern the identity and integrity of the school (along with the issue of just which texts should be attributed to it). Huang-Lao, like “Daoism” in early China, is a difficult idea to trace. There are no texts that refer to themselves as Huang-Lao texts, and our only references in early texts to the existence of Huang-Lao as a school are in the Shiji…It is far from clear whether Huang-Lao was ever a coherent school, trend, or other associative category (such as the Ru or Confucians), and most of the texts associated with Huang-Lao today gained this association due to later and contemporary scholars categorizing them as Huang-Lao. Given the difficulties and controversy surrounding the vague notion of Huang-Lao, the category as a whole is not terribly helpful for many purposes.
In the pre-Qin period, the term “Daoism” [i.e., Lao-Zhuang] did not yet exist, but this lack of a name does not necessarily indicate that there was no Daoist thought. The same point can be made for Huang-Lao as well. The “Under Heaven” (天下) chapter in the Zhuangzi and the “Against the Twelve Masters” (非十二子) chapter in the Xunzi both explicitly summarize various intellectual lineages without identifying them by name. Sima Qian first identifies the schools of both Daoism [Lao-Zhuang] and Huang-Lao.”
5. A Brief Excursus on Peerenboom and Defoort
Foundational naturalism coupled with a natural law theory differentiates Huang-Lao thought from that of other ancient schools, including classical Daoism [Lao-Zhuang]. Ironically, however, the standard practice has been to read Laozi and Zhuangzi as if they were Huang-Lao Daoists, attributing to them the metaphysical view of a single, predetermined natural order to be followed by humans. The view I explicate as that of the Huangdi sijing will therefore seem familiar to those acquainted with the standard [Chinese] reading, or misreading, as I argue, of Laozi and Zhuangzi. One of the main objectives of this work is then to challenge the traditional account of classical Daoism and demonstrate that the differences between classical Daoism and Huang-Lao thought go well beyond the latter’s adoption of a rule of law rejected by the former.
6. The Excavated Manuscripts and the Chinese Perspectives on Huang-Lao Daoism
There is a thing that developed from primordial chaos,Born before Heaven and Earth.Silent and still, it stands on its own and does not change.It can be regarded as the Mother of the World.Not yet knowing its name,I give it the character “Dao.”Forcing a name on it, I call it the Great.
Daoist descriptions of the original state thus do not make use of concrete terms but speak of it as being without name, without form, without image, greatly empty, merged in chaos. Yet the state also contains the potentiality of all and is the greatest font of all existence. Still, we have to take this a step further and realize that the original creative state of the universe is real, it is something: Dao, oneness, Great Oneness, or Constancy Before. These are highly abstract concepts, despite the fact that they are also expressed in metaphors such as the “mysterious female” [玄牝 xuanpin] or the “spirit of the valley” [谷神 gushen] [from Chapter 6]. Although Daoist thinkers often use the negative “non” [無] to describe the original nature of the pre-creation state, yet—as is well known—they do not mean ‘pure empty nonbeing’ but rather ‘ultimate being’.”
Dao gave birth to One.One gave birth to Two.Two gave birth to Three.Three gave birth to the myriad beings.
All early cosmologists believed that the universe took its beginning from a foundational natural entity and created life in a particular order, but they had a hard time determining what exactly that central pivot or foundation was. In addition, while they all insisted that simpler factors generated more complex structures (e.g., wood being shaped into different types of furniture), the more concrete entity they proposed at the origin, the harder it was for them to see it evolve into complexity (e.g., once wood is shaped into a chair, it is hard to transform into a table). The Daoist vision of universal emergence and cosmic structure always moves from darkness to light, from chaos to order, from simplicity to complexity, from the one to the many. Within this, it proposes various abstract or figurative (concrete) factors to outline levels and goals, increasingly differentiating beings from chaos in the process of arising.
The Great One gave birth to water. Water returned and assisted Taiyi, in this way developing heaven. Heaven returned and assisted Taiyi, in this way developing earth. Heaven and earth [repeatedly assisted each other], in this way developing the gods above and below. The gods above and below repeatedly assisted each other, in this way developing Yin and Yang. Yin and Yang repeatedly assisted each other, in this way developing the four seasons. The four seasons repeatedly assisted each other, in this way developing cold and hot. Cold and hot repeatedly assisted each other, in this way developing moist and dry. Moist and dry repeatedly assisted each other; they developed the year, and the process came to an end.
In Constancy Before, there is no material existence [有 you]. There is simplicity, stillness, and emptiness. Simplicity is Great Simplicity; stillness is Great Stillness; emptiness is Great Emptiness. It fulfills itself without repressing itself. Space works. Once there is space, there is energy; once there is energy, there is material existence; once there is material existence, there is a beginning; once there is a beginning, there is the passage of time. There is not yet heaven and earth; there is not yet working, progression, emergence, or birth. Empty, still, and as though one. Muddled and murky! All is still and homogeneous. There is not yet light, not yet teeming life.
The One birthed the Two.The Two birthed the Three.The Three birthed the Mother.The Mother formed the Congelations (結 jie).
At the beginning of constant nonbeing [恒無 hengwu],All was merged in great emptiness.Empty and same, all was in oneness,Constant oneness, nothing more…Therefore, it never depends on existence [有 you].Never relies on any of the myriad beings…Therefore, it does not possess form.It is immensely pervasive yet nameless…Oneness is its appellation.Emptiness is its dwelling.Nonaction is its element.Harmony is its function.
So lofty it cannot be scrutinized,So deep it cannot be fathomed.Clear and bright, no one can name it.Vast and large, no one can give it form.It stands alone and is not paired with anything else.
The Daoist tradition is thus at the center of the development of early Chinese nature cosmology. As clearly expressed in Daodejing Chapter 25, they defined Dao as the underlying force of the universe. Under its influence, the three early manuscripts developed the concepts of Oneness (一 yi) [Fanwu liuxing], Great Oneness (太一taiyi) [Taiyi sheng shui], and Constancy Before (恒先hengxian) [Hengxian] in an effort to describe the origin of the myriad beings. The “Daoyuan”, too, uses Dao to speak of the root of all beings and identifies it with oneness…All these are ways in which early Daoist cosmology developed during the Eastern Zhou.
“Constant” here means “eternal” and signifies the ongoing course of the heavenly bodies and natural cycles. Both “constant” [heng] and “before” [先 xian] refer to temporal phenomena, but “before” here is not an ordinary ranking in a sequence; rather, it indicates the eternal or primordial state before creation, the starting point and initial glimmer of the entire universe… In this sense, Constancy Before [hengxian] matches Great Oneness [太一 taiyi] in the Taiyi sheng- shui, the “initiation of constant nonbeing” [恒無之初 heng wu zhi chu] in the “Daoyuan,” and even the Great Initiation [泰初 taichu] of Zhuangzi Chapter 12. It is, moreover, the point or origin where, as the Hengxian says, “there is no material existence” [無有 wuyou], when all is still nameless and formless.
We can conclude that the Hengxian comes after the Daodejing for two reasons. One, it stands in the tradition of Daoism founded by Laozi; two, it is contemporaneous with the Guodian Laozi, which is neither the first nor the original version of the text. While the Hengxian does not make use of Laozi’s central concepts of Dao and De, it has quite a few central concepts in common with the text: constancy, simplicity, stillness, emptiness, energy, space, oneness, return, self-generation, names, and more. In many ways, it inherits the overall philosophical thrust of the Daodejing, yet it also develops its thought, proposing unique concepts that are yet based on Laozi, such as Constancy Before, Great Simplicity, Great Stillness, Great Emptiness, heavenly workings, muddy and clear energy, self-working, self-acting, and the like. More specifically, it adopts Laozi’s notions of simplicity, stillness, and emptiness, then expands them in its own way, making this by adding the prefix “great” to each of them. It uses the idea of constancy, already found in Daodejing Chapter 1, using the word heng rather than the transmitted chang. In Chapters 4 and 25, Laozi describes Dao as “before images and gods” [象帝之先] and as “born before heaven and earth” [先天地 生], using the word “before” to indicate a very long, infinite, cosmic time span. Adapting the two terms “constancy” and “before” from the Daodejing, the Hengxian creates its own unique concept of Constancy Before to express the starting point and original state of the universe. All this strongly indicates that the text came after the Daodejing and inherited and developed its ideas.
Both the Hengxian and the Huangdi sijing develop Laozi’s basic notions. The Hengxian begins by speaking of the state before being (wuyou 无有), describing it in terms of simplicity (pu 朴), stillness (jing 静), and emptiness (xu 虚), emphasizing each by adding the epithet “great” (tai 太), meaning to the highest degree, ultimate, utmost… Based on this, it becomes clear that the original state of the universe was long-lasting, “a constant and permanent state.”
7. Concluding with the Daodejing
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | The title “Daodejing” generally refers to the text that was canonized in two parts, Dao and De, in the course of the Western Han Dynasty, whereas the title “Laozi” is used for the pre-canonized and excavated editions of the text, as with the Guodian Laozi and the Mawangdui Laozi, that had not yet become stabilized into what we familiarly call the received edition. |
2 | Yates (1997, pp. 193–94) summarizes current debates about the title, with some calling it the Boshu or Silk Manuscripts, like Yates (1997) and Peerenboom (1993), some calling it the Four Texts of the Yellow Emperor, like Chang and Feng (1998), and some calling it Huangdi sijing (Four Classics of the Yellow Emperor), including the Chinese scholars at issue in this study; I follow them and have changed all alternative references to the Huangdi sijing. |
3 | Because the current study is focused on issues in the modern study of Huang-Lao Daoism, it spends little time analyzing the manuscripts themselves. Next to readily available English translations of the Guodian and Mawangdui Laozis, English translations of the other manuscripts are taken from the works of Wang Zhongjiang, to which readers who wish to consult them are referred. Editions of other early Chinese texts discussed herein are taken from the Chinese Text Project website (https://ctext.org/), accessed on 24 September 2023, as consistent with contemporary practice. |
4 | I use the terms “Chinese scholarship” and “Chinese scholars” in a geographical and not an ethnic sense to refer to mainland Chinese scholars trained in the Chinese academy. The phrase does not necessarily refer to the growing number of Chinese scholars trained in the Western academy, nor to the growing number of Western scholars trained in the Chinese academy. For example, I do not consider the eminent Chinese scholar of Chinese philosophy, Cheng Chung-ying, who received his M.A. from the University of Washington and his Ph.D. from Harvard and who spent much of his career at the University of Hawai’i, as representative of “Chinese scholarship,” especially since his views (Cheng 1990, pp. 167–68) about “Chinese Metaphysics as Non-metaphysics,” which holds that it is not concerned with the “separation of the sensible from the nonsensible, the practical from the transcendental,” are not representative of “Chinese scholarship.” |
5 | The most important work is Wang Zhongjiang’s 简帛文明与古代思想世界 (translated as Civilization of Bamboo-Silk and the World of Ancient Thought) published in 2011 (Z. Wang 2011). Its twenty chapters in nearly 600 pages devoted to fifteen excavated texts widely supplemented with attention to the Daodejing, given the word space disparity between Chinese and English, marks it as a massive work by any measure. Many of its chapters have been revised and translated into English for publication in the two books, Daoism Excavated: Cosmos and Humanity in Early Manuscripts (2015) and Order in Early Chinese Excavated Texts: Natural, Supernatural, and Legal Approaches (2016). The work of Zheng Kai is 道家政治哲学发微, published in 2019 (Zheng 2019); translated into English as The Metaphysics of Philosophical Daoism, it was published in 2021. The work of Cao Feng is 近年出土黃老思想文獻研究, published in 2015 (Cao 2015); translated into English as Daoism in Early China: Huang-Lao Thought in Light of Excavated Texts, it was published in 2021. |
6 | To counter potential claims that I am setting up a straw man argument, I point out that some eminent Western scholars hold the opposite position. Benjamin Schwartz (1985, pp. 186–254) and Harold Roth (2021), for example, both argue that the Dao is an ineffable metaphysical reality that can be encountered by way of a Chinese style of mysticism. |
7 | The work of Zheng Kai is especially insightful with respect to Huang-Lao political philosophy. |
8 | |
9 | The emergent naturalism that scholars such as Ames, Liu, and Defoort see in the formations of primordial qi largely proceeds along the same course but without the direction of the Dao and its principles. |
10 | I do not provide further analysis of De, often translated as “Virtue,” because it has only a minimal role in the arguments with which this study engages, centered as they are on cosmogony. It does, however, play an important role in Huang-Lao political philosophy, which this study does not accommodate. |
11 | This body of work begins with the two complete English translations of the Huangdi sijing, the first by Yates (1997) and the second by Chang and Feng (1998). The introductory materials of each are concerned with positioning the writings in the context of early Chinese political thought as a whole and offer little for Daoist studies. Yates recognizes that the writings “are composed of two types of texts: some belong to what has been identified as the Huang-Lao Daoist tradition, others belong to this more esoteric, lesser-known Yin-Yang tradition” (1997, p. 16), but he does not go into detail. Chang and Feng recognize that “Laozi’s philosophy of Dao may have influenced the Huangdi sijing” (Chang and Feng 1998, p. 17), but they anyway read the text as companion to the Confucian tradition because the Confucian gentleman “ideally personifies the cardinal Confucian moral virtues and thereby become legitimate exemplars for others to follow. Hence, we may characterize this mode of governing as yang ru 阳儒 or ‘overt Confucianism.’ In contrast to yang ru, the Huangdi sijing will be characterized as yin 隐 or ‘covert’ (because it) is clearly written for the ruler and the ruling elites as an ‘internal document’ of ‘the art of governing,’ obviously not intended for public consumption” (Chang and Feng 1998, p. 76). Given that both were published in the late 1990s, they oddly never mention the more recently excavated Huang-Lao manuscripts. More recent work added to this body of scholarship worthy of note includes Perkins (2013, 2016), Brindley (2013), Brindley et al. (2013), and Gomouline (2013). |
12 | The same could be said for other received texts like the Hanfeizi, Wenzi, Heguanzi, and Huainanzi, all of which strive to subordinate an earlier anarchic strain of Daoist ideas to the needs of the state and all of which also post-date 221 BCE when Qinshi Huangdi became the emperor of a unified Chinese realm, which raises the possibility that Huang-Lao just might refer to him. I refrain from discussing these texts, as well as other Han-era apocrypha (緯 wei), for that matter, since I preserve them for a future study of the political aspects of Huang-Lao. |
13 | Brown and McLeod (2021, pp. 15–32) give an insightful discussion of Western notions of naturalism and metaphysics and how they have impacted Western studies of Chinese thought. |
14 | Liu (2014a, p. 63) argues that “Chinese qi-cosmology falls into the category of naturalism because the operations of qi do not violate the laws of nature… In Chinese qi-cosmology, the universe is seen as self-existent and self-sufficient. There is no supernatural entity that operates in any way on things in the natural world.” |
15 | |
16 | |
17 | Since the Chinese scholars primarily rely on the Huang-Lao version of the Daodejing, which is more or less what we recognize as the received version, I refrain from complicating matters by bringing the Guodian Laozi into discussion unless specifically noted, in this case by refraining from discussion of the import of its use of “form” (狀 zhuang) that the Huang-Lao thinkers changed to “thing” (物 wu), which by itself gives evidence of the distinction between Laozi’s pre-metaphysical philosophy and Huang-Lao’s metaphysical philosophy. |
18 | Not all Huang-Lao texts present cosmogonies, even as many later Huang-Lao texts, such as the Wenzi and the Huainanzi, provide even more sophisticated versions. |
19 | By the early Han, Huang-Lao had resolved on the Dao as the formal and standard title of the metaphysical entity, heng was no longer used due to its taboo, and other appellations for it, although still used (such as the One, etc.), became relegated to secondary status as primary attributes of the Dao. For a detailed analysis of heng and chang, see Michael (2022a). |
20 | There is a third reason, not examined here, for the recent attention paid to the Hengxian and its profound influence over the later Huang-Lao tradition, namely its explicit connecting of the cosmogony to governance (not accommodated in this study). This in fact can be argued to be the true raison d’etre of Huang-Lao Daoism, which appears most fully developed in the Huangdi sijing, in the Huainanzi, and in Heshang Gong’s Daodejing. |
21 | Zhouyi qian zuo du (1994, p. 46) states: “The Supreme Origin is the beginning of qi, the Supreme Beginning is the beginning of form, and the Supreme Elemental is the beginning of substance” (太初者氣之始也,太始者形之始也,太素者質也). Weishu Jicheng (Shanghai 1994, p. 46). |
22 | Liezi Chapter 1 states: “There is Supreme Simplicity, there is Supreme Origin, there is Supreme Beginning, and there is Supreme Elemental” (有太易,有太初,有太始,有太素). For this discussion, see Michael (2011, pp. 118–21). |
23 |
References
- Ames, Roger. 2015. Reading the Zhongyong ‘metaphysically’. In Chinese Metaphysics and Its Problems. Edited by Chenyang Li and Franklin Perkins. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 85–104. [Google Scholar]
- Ames, Roger, and David Hall. 2003. Daodejing “Making This Life Significant”: A Philosophical Translation. New York: Ballantine Books. [Google Scholar]
- Brindley, Erica F. 2013. The Cosmos as Creative Mind: Spontaneous Arising, Generating, and Creating in the Heng Xian. Dao 12: 189–206. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brindley, Erica F., Paul R. Goldin, and Esther S. Klein. 2013. A Philosophical Translation of the Heng Xian. Dao 12: 145–151. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brown, Joshua, and Alexus McLeod. 2021. Transcendence and Non-Naturalism in Early Chinese Thought. London: Bloomsbury. [Google Scholar]
- Cao, Feng 曹峰. 2015. Daoism in Early China: Huang-Lao Thought in Light of Excavated Texts 近年出土黃老思想文獻研究. Beijing: Zhongguo shehui kexue chubanshe. [Google Scholar]
- Cao, Feng 曹峰. 2017. Daoism in Early China: Huang-Lao Thought in Light of Excavated Texts. Translated by Callisto Serle, Sharon Y. Small, and Jeffrey Keller. New York: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Chan, Alan. 1991. Two Visions of the Way: A Study of the Wang Pi and the Ho-shang-kung Commentaries on the Laozi. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Chang, Leo S., and Yu Feng. 1998. The Four Political Treatises of the Yellow Emperor: Original Mawangdui Texts with Complete English Translations and an Introduction. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. [Google Scholar]
- Cheng, Chung-Ying. 1990. Chinese Metaphysics as Non-Metaphysics: Confucian and Daoist Insights into the Nature of Reality. In Understanding the Chinese Mind. Edited by Robert E. Allinson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 167–208. [Google Scholar]
- Chen, Li-Kuei, and Hiu Chuk Winnie Sung. 2015. The Doctrines and Transformation of the Huang-Lao Tradition. In Dao Companion to Daoist Philosophy. Edited by Xiaogan Liu. London: Springer, pp. 241–64. [Google Scholar]
- Cohen, S. Marc, and C. D. C. Reeve. 2021. Aristotle’s Metaphysics. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Winter 2021 ed. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/ (accessed on 24 September 2023).
- Csikszentmihalyi, Mark, and Michael Nylan. 2003. Constructing Lineages and Inventing Traditions through Exemplary Figures in Early China. T’oung Pao 89: 59–99. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Defoort, Carine. 1994a. Obscurity about Clarity: A Reply to R. P. Peerenboom. Philosophy East and West 44: 379–85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Defoort, Carine. 1994b. The ‘Transcendence’ of Tian: Reviewed Work: Law and Morality in Ancient China: The Silk Manuscripts of Huang-Lao. by Randall Peerenboom. Philosophy East and West 44: 347–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Els, Paul van. 2002. “Guest Editor’s Preface: The Many Faces of Huang-Lao. Contemporary Chinese Thought 34: 3–18. [Google Scholar]
- Ess, Hans van. 1993. The Meaning of Huang-Lao in Shiji and Hanshu. Études chinoises 12: 161–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Girardot, Norman. 1988. Myth and Meaning in Early Daoism. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gomouline, Andrei. 2013. Permanence, Something, Being: The Cosmogonic Argument of the Heng Xian. Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 12: 179–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Graham, Angus Charles. 1990. Studies in Chinese Philosophy. New York: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hall, Roger, and David Ames. 1987. Thinking Through Confucius. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hall, Roger, and David Ames. 1997. Thinking from the Han: Self, Truth, and Transcendence in Chinese and Western Culture. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hansen, Chad. 1992. A Daoist Theory of Chinese Thought: A Philosophical Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kramers, Robert. 1986. The development of the Confucian schools. In The Cambridge History of China, Vol. 1: The Ch’in and Han Empires, 221 BC-AD 220. Edited by Denis Twitchett and Michael Loewe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 747–56. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, Mark Edward. 1999. Writing and Authority in Early China. New York: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Li, Chenyang, and Franklin Perkins, eds. 2015. Chinese Metaphysics and Its Problems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Li, Ling. 1995–1996. An Archaeological Study of Taiyi (Grand One) Worship. Translated by Donald Harper. Early Medieval China 1995–1996: 1–39. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, JeeLoo. 2014a. Chinese Qi-Naturalism and Liberal Naturalism. Philosophy, Theology, and the Sciences 1: 59–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Liu, JeeLoo. 2014b. Was There Something in Nothingness? The Debate on the Primordial State between Daoism and Neo-Confucianism. In Nothingness in Asian Philosophy. Edited by JeeLoo Liu and Douglas L. Berger. New York: Routledge, pp. 181–96. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, JeeLoo. 2015. In defense of Chinese qi-naturalism. In Chinese Metaphysics and Its Problems. Edited by Chenyang Li and Franklin Perkins. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 35–53. [Google Scholar]
- Major, John S. 1993. Heaven and Earth in Early Han Thought: Chapters Three, Four, and Five of the Huainanzi. New York: State University of New York. [Google Scholar]
- Meyer, Andrew. 2010–2011. The Altars of the Soil and Grain are Closer than Kin 社稷戚於親: The Qi 齊 Model of Intellectual Participation and the Jixia 稷下 Patronage Community. Early China 34: 37–99. [Google Scholar]
- Michael, Thomas. 2011. The That-Beyond-Which of the Pristine Dao: Cosmogony in the Liezi. In Riding the Wind with Liezi. Edited by Ronnie Littlejohn and Jeffrey Dippmann. Albany: State Universit of New York Press, pp. 101–26. [Google Scholar]
- Michael, Thomas. 2022a. Philosophical Enactment and Bodily Cultivation: In the Matrix of the Daodejing. London: Bloomsbury. [Google Scholar]
- Michael, Thomas. 2022b. The Original Text of the Daodejing: Disentangling Versions and Recensions. Religions 13: 325. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Michael, Thomas. 2023. Original Nothingness and Wu-Compounds: Re-interpreting Daodejing’s Discourse on Nothingness. Philosophy East and West 73: 698–717. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Peerenboom, Randall P. 1993. Law and Morality in Ancient China: The Silk Manuscripts of Huang-Lao. New York: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Peerenboom, Randall P. 1994. The Rational American and the Inscrutable Oriental as Seen from the Perspective of a Puzzled European: A Review (And Response) in Three Stereotypes: A Reply to Carine Defoort. Philosophy East and West 44: 368–379. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Perkins, Franklin. 2013. The Spontaneous Generation of the Human in the Heng Xian. Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 12: 225–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Perkins, Franklin. 2015. Chinese Metaphysics Methodology in a Cross-Cultural Context. In The Bloomsbury Research Handbook of Chinese Philosophy Methodologies. Edited by Sor-hoon Tan. London: Bloomsbury, pp. 183–98. [Google Scholar]
- Perkins, Franklin. 2016. The Laozi and the Cosmogonic Turn in Classical Chinese Philosophy. Frontiers of Philosophy in China 11: 185–205. [Google Scholar]
- Robinet, Isabelle. 1981. Les Commentaires du Tao To King jusqu’au VIIe Siècle. Paris: Mémoires de l’Institut des Hautes Études Chinoises. [Google Scholar]
- Roth, Harold. 2021. The Contemplative Foundations of Classical Daoism. New York: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schwartz, Benjamin. 1985. The World of Thought in Ancient China. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Seidel, Anna. 1992. La Divinisation de Lao Tseu dans le Taoisme des Han. Paris: École Française d’Extreme-Orient. [Google Scholar]
- Shanghai. 1994. Zhouyi Qian Zuo Du 周易乾鑿度. Shanghai: Weishu Jicheng. [Google Scholar]
- Sivin, Nathan. 1978. On the Word ‘Taoist’ as a Source of Perplexity. History of Religion 17: 303–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Smith, Kidder. 2003. Sima Tan and the Invention of Daoism, ‘Legalism,’ et cetera. The Journal of Asian Studies 62: 129–56. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Strickmann, Michel. 1979. On the Alchemy of T’ao Hung-ching. In Facets of Taoism: Essays in Chinese Religion. Edited by Holmes Welch and Anna Seidel. New Haven: Yale University Press, pp. 123–92. [Google Scholar]
- Wagner, Rudolf. 2003. A Chinese Reading of the Daodejing: Wang Bi’s Commentary on the Laozi with Critical Text and Translation. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Bo. 2011. The Discovery and Establishment of Wu: Daoist Metaphysics and Political Philosophy. English translation by Trenton, Wilson. Contemporary Chinese Thought 43: 9–29. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Zhongjiang 王中江. 2011. Civilization of Bamboo-Silk and the World of Ancient Thought 简帛文明与古代思想世界. Beijing: Beijing Daxue Chubanshe. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Zhongjiang 王中江. 2015. Daoism Excavated: Cosmos and Humanity in Early Manuscripts. Translated by Livia Kohn. St. Petersburg: Three Pines Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Zhongjiang 王中江. 2016. Order in Early Chinese Excavated Texts: Natural, Supernatural, and Legal Approaches. Translated by Misha Tadd. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Weber, Ralph. 2013. Why talk about Chinese metaphysics? Frontiers of Philosophy in China 8: 99–119. [Google Scholar]
- Yates, Robin. 1997. Five Lost Classics: Tao, Huang-Lao, and Yin-yang in Han China. New York: Ballantine Books. [Google Scholar]
- Yu, Jiyuan. 2011. Is Chinese Cosmology Metaphysics?”—A Greek-Chinese Comparative Study. Journal of East-West Thought 1: 137–50. [Google Scholar]
- Zhao, Dunhua. 2006. Metaphysics in China and in the West: Common Origin and Later Divergence. Frontiers of Philosophy in China 1: 22–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zheng, Kai 郑开. 2019. The Metaphysics of Philosophical Daoism 到家政治哲学发微. Beijing: Peking University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Zheng, Kai. 2021. The Metaphysics of Philosophical Daoism. Translated by Hanliang Ruan, and Roger Ames. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Ziporyn, Brook. 2018. Vast Continuity versus the One Thoughts on Daodejing 42, Taiyishengshui, and the Legacy of Roger T. Ames. In Appreciating the Chinese Difference: Engaging Roger T. Ames on Methods, Issues, and Roles. Edited by Jim Behuniak. New York: State University of New York Press, pp. 111–32. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Michael, T. On the Fiercely Debated Questions of a Chinese Metaphysics and a Tradition of Early Daoism: Western and Chinese Perspectives on the Daodejing and Huang-Lao Daoism. Religions 2023, 14, 1281. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14101281
Michael T. On the Fiercely Debated Questions of a Chinese Metaphysics and a Tradition of Early Daoism: Western and Chinese Perspectives on the Daodejing and Huang-Lao Daoism. Religions. 2023; 14(10):1281. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14101281
Chicago/Turabian StyleMichael, Thomas. 2023. "On the Fiercely Debated Questions of a Chinese Metaphysics and a Tradition of Early Daoism: Western and Chinese Perspectives on the Daodejing and Huang-Lao Daoism" Religions 14, no. 10: 1281. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14101281
APA StyleMichael, T. (2023). On the Fiercely Debated Questions of a Chinese Metaphysics and a Tradition of Early Daoism: Western and Chinese Perspectives on the Daodejing and Huang-Lao Daoism. Religions, 14(10), 1281. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14101281