Causal Connections, Logical Connections, and Skeptical Theism: There Is No Logical Problem of Evil
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Sterba’s Argument from Evil
2.1. Sterba’s Constraints
TORTURE: You and three friends were hiding from a would-be torturer. Since the torturer was unable to find you and your friends, she found another person to torture instead, call her Sarah. She begins torturing Sarah—say, by reading her passages from the dreaded Hs: Habermas, Heidegger, and Hegel—and you are able to jump from your hiding spot and prevent her from engaging in this torture. If you were to do so, Sarah would be set free. However, it would result in you and your three friends being tortured.
[n]one of the exceptions to the Pauline Principle that are permitted to agents, like ourselves, due to our limitations of power, would hold of God. This means that the Pauline Principle’s prohibition of intentional doing evil would be even more absolute in the case of God than it is our selves.
God, unlike ourselves, is never justified in permitting significant and even horrendous evil consequences of one immoral action so as to prevent the greater evil consequences of another immoral action.(Sterba 2019b, p. 178, emphasis mine)
2.2. Sterba’s Argument Stated
- (1)
- Goods that could be provided to us are of just two types. They are either goods to which we have a right or goods to which we do not have a right.3
- (2)
- With respect to goods to which we have a right, such as freedom from a brutal assault, God would never be causally stuck, as we sometimes are, in situations where we can only provide some with such goods by not providing others with such goods.
- (3)
- Since then God would be facing no causal or logical constraints with respect to providing us with such goods, God should always have provided us with such goods and thereby prevented the evils that would otherwise occur.
- (4)
- But this clearly has not happened because there are significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions that God, if he exists, would have to be permitting, and this is logically incompatible with God’s existence, unless there is a justification for God’s permitting those consequences to provide us with goods to which we do not have a right.
- (5)
- Now with respect to such goods [i.e., goods that we don’t have a right], God would also never be causally constrained by lack of resources, as we sometimes are, and thereby be unable to provide us with such goods without permitting the significant and especially horrendous consequences of immoral actions to be inflicted on us.
- (6)
- Since then God would be facing no causal or logical constraints with respect to providing…us with such goods, God should always have provided us with such goods without permitting the significant and especially the horrendous consequences of immoral action to be inflicted on us.
- (7)
- But that clearly has not happened because there are significant and even horrendous consequences of immoral action inflicted on us which, if God exists, would have to have resulted from God’s widespread permission of just those consequences, and that is logically incompatible with God’s existence (Sterba 2019b, pp. 184–85).
ZUES: God created a powerful creature, Zeus. And God has made an agreement with Zues that he may create a mini-world as he sees fit—God promises not to interfere with Zeus’s world.
AUTONOMY: Humans have a right to autonomy, understood as a right to act as we see fit. And this right is absolute: it’s always wrong to violate no matter what.
2.3. Sterba’s Argument Repaired
- (8)
- God’s permission of the evil consequences of the General’s action could not be a morally acceptable means to prevent some other greater evil consequences of an immoral action. This is because God, being all-powerful, could always prevent the evil consequences of any action, as needed, by just sufficiently restricting the external freedom of the evildoer in each case. Hence, this is just, I claim, what God morally should do.
- (9)
- Neither could God’s permission of the morally evil consequences of the General’s action be a morally justified means to secure some good to which we are not entitled. This is because the greatest good to which we are not entitled that God could morally provide us with would be a Godly opportunity for soul-making, and to make the provision of that good, and other such goods to which we do not have a right, conditional on God’s permission of significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions, like the General’s, would lead to morally perverse incentives for us and for God as well. In addition, making the provision of a Godly opportunity for soul-making, and other such goods to which we do not have a right, conditional on the permission of significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions, like the General’s, would not be morally justified because we do not have a right to such goods, and so clearly their provision could not be conditional on the violation of anyone’s rights, especially when there are countless other ways that these goods could be provided that are not morally objectionable. (Sterba 2019a, pp. 96–97, emphasis mine).
- (10)
- We recognize no evils that are logically entailed by God preventing the child’s death by dogs.
- (11)
- Therefore, probably, there are no such evils.11
Could there be entailment relations between such goods and permitting the consequences of other evils that would render it logically impossible for God to prevent both evil consequences? Yet notice how strange such entailment relations would be. Here we are dealing with situations where we lack the causal power to prevent the evil consequences of both immoral actions and we appeal to the lack of causal power to justify why we permit the lesser evil consumes to prevent the greater evil consequences. Now…we are imagining that it is logically impossible for God to present the consequences of both immoral actions that are just causally impossible for us to prevent. Right off, that would make God impossibly less powerful than ourselves.
that God can always prevent the horrendous evil consequences of both actions in contexts where we, due to our limited causal power, can only prevent the evil consequences of one of them.14
2.4. Will Other Constraints Help?
3. Lessons Learned
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
1 | It is worth noting that there have been powerful (and to my mind persuasive) reasons given for rejecting these outweighing constraints. See e.g., Peter Van Inwagen (2006) and Justin Mooney (2019). |
2 | Sterba holds that there’s two additional constraints: he holds that (a) that an action is morally justified only if it is “reasonably acceptable” to all those affected, and (b) that an action should not be permitted if “significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions [occur] simply to provide other rational beings with goods they would morally prefer not to have.” (Sterba 2019a, p. 128). I will briefly discuss these additional constraints in Section 2.4. However, I don’t discuss them here for three reasons. First, I just don’t think it is at all plausible to hold that these are actual constraints on God (or anyone): what makes an action permissible, in my view, is (roughly) just whether its justifying reasons outweigh its requiring reasons (see e.g., Tucker forthcoming a, forthcoming b for models of weighing reasons). Talk of acceptability and moral preferability is not needed. Second, even if these were requirements, it is exceedingly difficult to tell if an action would be “reasonably accepted” or “morally preferred” by all those affected. This is because reasonable acceptance and moral preference would (presumably) be needed after full disclosure of the relevant facts about the world (including the necessary connections between states of affairs) and the role one’s suffering (etc.) played in it. But we don’t know all the relevant facts. Worse yet, it is exceedingly difficult to know under what conditions one would reasonably accept or morally prefer an evil. And third, if we set aside the previous issue momentarily, it is plausible to think that someone would reasonably accept and morally prefer an evil if the justifying reasons in favor of it outweighed the requiring reasons against it. But in that case, these constraints offer nothing beyond the ordinary requirements of morality. |
3 | This distinction between goods which we have a right to and goods which we don’t have a right to is not important for my purposesHowever, a brief word is in order here. Goods of which we have a right to are those that we are (in a sense) owed. And if we are not given those goods, that is itself evil. And so one way to prevent evil is to ensure that we have goods that we have a right to. Conversely, it is not evil if we don’t have goods that we don’t have a right to. For more on this diction, see Sterba (Sterba 2019a, pp. 126–30). |
4 | Below, I use examples to illustrate the differences between causal and logical constraints (and connections). In the meantime, we may say that (roughly) if A and B are logically connected, that A necessitates B or B necessitates A. And we may say that if God is logically constrained with respect to an action A, that (roughly) there is some negative state of affairs logically connected to his performing A. Next, we may say that if A is causally (but not logically) connected to B, then (very roughly) in our world, absent supernatural intervention, A follows from B or B follows from A. Again, these are rough approximations. My examples below should make matters clearer. |
5 | If you maintain that being logically constrained entails being causally constrained, then you can recast my objection as Sterba not providing justification for thinking God is not subject to causal constraints that we are not subject to. Nothing in my argument would be lost by recasting it in this way. Additionally, note that I have not said God must keep his contract with Zues. Instead, I have just noted that God causally intervening logically entails violating the contractAnd since there may be cases in which God can violate contracts, it does not follow that he is causally constrained here. That depends on the strength of God’s reasons for keeping the contract. |
6 | |
7 | Again, if you disagree with this, my point may be recast in the way suggested in footnote 4. |
8 | Yet again, if you disagree with this, follow the instructions given in footnote 6. |
9 | While Sterba’s (2019a, 2019b) have the same publication year, his (Sterba 2019b) was published online in 2018, and is an earlier iteration of his thought. |
10 | Perhaps Sterba thinks no such inference is needed. Perhaps he thinks he can just see that there are no evils logically entailed by God preventing the child’s death in this scenario. This would be a different argument, and it would be similar to the move made by proponents of the so-called commonsense problem of evil, who think that we can see (or have justification for thinking) that there is unjustified evil. This move is difficult to justify, and will doubtless be controversial. And if he makes it, objections given to the commonsense problem of evil will become relevant (e.g., Bergmann 2012; Hendricks 2018; Tweedt 2015). |
11 | I focus on evils here since most of my discussion is related to the PP. However, a similar inference would need to be run about goods as well. |
12 | I will not argue for the truth of skeptical theism here, but see Hendricks (2020a, 2020b) for an argument for it. And see Bergmann (2001, 2009, 2012, 2014), Daniel Howard-Snyder (2009), and Hendricks (2019, 2020c, 2021) for statements and defenses of skeptical theism. For standard objections to skeptical theism, see e.g., Benton et al. (2016), William Hasker (2010), Hud Hudson (2014), and Erik Wielenberg (2010). |
13 | The way that I’m going to consider this objection does not include this “for all we know” language. I have argued elsewhere (Hendricks 2021) that this language is misleading, and that skeptical theists and their critics should not make use of it. |
14 | Sterba offers similar comments in his book, saying: [n]otice how strange this claim would be. Clearly, it is difficult for us to even think of cases where we causally cannot provide others with goods to which they do not have a right unless we permit them to be deprived of goods to which they do have a right. Yet, it is for just such analogous cases that we areto imagine that God logically cannot provide us with something to which we do not have a right without permitting us to be deprived of something to which we do have a right. Again, that makes God look impossibly less powerful than ourselves. Thus, we could easily imagine that we never do suffer from this sort of causal inability…while God would be still stuck in a logically impossibility in analogous contexts (Sterba 2019a, pp. 85–86). And several versions of his argument rely on a move like this e.g., premise (4) and premise (12) from The Argument from Moral Evil in the World (Sterba 2019a, pp. 186–87). This line of reasoning falls prey to the same problems as his quotes from the main text. |
15 | |
16 | e.g., if the only way for God to prevent 1,000,000,000 Holocausts was for him to permit a single Holocaust, then it is reasonable to accept the Holocaust, and one should morally prefer it. |
References
- Benton, Matthew, John Hawthorne, and Yoaav Isaacs. 2016. Evil and Evidence. In Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion: Volume 7. Edited by Jonathan Kvanvig. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 1–31. [Google Scholar]
- Bergmann, Michael. 2001. Skeptical Theism and Rowe’s New Evidential Argument from Evil. Nous 35: 278–96. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bergmann, Michael. 2009. Skeptical Theism and the Problem of Evil. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology. Edited by Thomas Flint and Michael Rea. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 374–402. [Google Scholar]
- Bergmann, Michael. 2012. Commonsense Skeptical Theism. In Reason, Metaphysics, and Mind. Edited by Kelly James Clark and Michael Rea. New Essays on the Philosophy of Alvin Plantinga. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 9–30. [Google Scholar]
- Bergmann, Michael. 2014. Skeptical Theism, Atheism, and Total Evidence Skepticism. In Skeptical Theism: New Essays. Edited by T. Dougherty and Justin McBrayer. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 209–20. [Google Scholar]
- Dostoevsky, Fyodor. 1984. The Brothers Karamazov. New York: Bantam Classics. [Google Scholar]
- Draper, Paul. 2013. The Limitations of Pure Skeptical Theism. Res Philosophica 90: 97–111. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hasker, William. 2010. All Too Skeptical Theism. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 68: 15–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hendricks, Perry. 2018. How to be a Skeptical Theist and a Commonsense Epistemologist. Faith and Philosophy 35: 345–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Hendricks, Perry. 2019. The Nature of Skeptical Theism: Answering Non-Standard Objections to Skeptical Theism. Philosophia Christi 21: 105–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hendricks, Perry. 2020a. Skeptical Theism, Pro-Theism, and Anti-Theism. In Four Views on The Axiology of Theism: What Difference Does God Make? Edited by Kirk Lougheed. London: Bloomsbury Publishing, pp. 95–115. [Google Scholar]
- Hendricks, Perry. 2020b. Skeptical Theism Proved. The Journal of the American Philosophical Association 6: 264–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hendricks, Perry. 2020c. Skeptical Theism Unscathed: Why Skeptical Objections to Skeptical Theism Fail. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 101: 43–73. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hendricks, Perry. 2021. We are not in the Dark: Refuting Popular Arguments Against Skeptical Theism. American Philosophical Quarterly 58: 125–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Howard-Snyder, Daniel. 2009. Epistemic humility, arguments from evil, and moral skepticism. In Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion: Volume 2. Edited by Jon Kvanvig. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 17–57. [Google Scholar]
- Hudson, Hud. 2014. The Father of Lies? In Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion: Volume 5. Edited by Jonathan L. Kvanvig. Seattle: Xerxes Press, pp. 147–66. [Google Scholar]
- Mooney, Justin. 2019. How to Solve the Problem of Evil: A Deontological Strategy. Faith and Philosophy 36: 442–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Reitan, Eric. 2014. A Deontological Theodicy? Swinburne’s Lapse and the Problem of Moral Evil. Faith and Philosophy 31: 181–203. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Sterba, James. 2019a. Is a Good God Logically Possible? London: Palgrave-MacMillan. [Google Scholar]
- Sterba, James. 2019b. Skeptical Theism and the challenge of atheism. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 85: 173–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tucker, Chris. forthcoming a. The Dual Scale Model of Weighing Reasons. Nous 56: 366–92. [CrossRef]
- Tucker, Chris. forthcoming b. Weighing Reasons Against. Oxford Studies in Metaethics 17: 77–107.
- Tweedt, Chris. 2015. Defusing the Common Sense Problem of Evil. Faith and Philosophy 32: 391–403. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Van Inwagen, Peter. 2006. The Problem of Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wielenberg, Erik. 2010. Skeptical Theism and Divine Lies. Religious Studies 46: 509–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Hendricks, P. Causal Connections, Logical Connections, and Skeptical Theism: There Is No Logical Problem of Evil. Religions 2022, 13, 668. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13070668
Hendricks P. Causal Connections, Logical Connections, and Skeptical Theism: There Is No Logical Problem of Evil. Religions. 2022; 13(7):668. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13070668
Chicago/Turabian StyleHendricks, Perry. 2022. "Causal Connections, Logical Connections, and Skeptical Theism: There Is No Logical Problem of Evil" Religions 13, no. 7: 668. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13070668
APA StyleHendricks, P. (2022). Causal Connections, Logical Connections, and Skeptical Theism: There Is No Logical Problem of Evil. Religions, 13(7), 668. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13070668