An Atheistic Argument from Naturalistic Explanations of Religious Belief: A Preliminary Reply to Robert Nola
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. From Naturalistic Explanations of Religious Beliefs to Denial of Theism
2.1. Freudianism
“We need not accept all of Freud’s dubious theory of oedipal complexes and the panoply of deeply unconscious wishes. However some of the claims Freud makes about wish-fulfilment, when disconnected from his psychoanalytic theories, are initially plausible and open to test” (Nola 2013, p. 170). However, “wish-fulfillment… is an unreliable BFP [belief-forming process]… there is no reason for the Freudian wish-fulfillment BFP to be oriented towards the truth at all; its aim, we might say, is not to uncover truths about the world but to provide beliefs that are comforting and enable us to cope, whatever their truth-value”.
2.2. Hypersensitive Agency Detection Device (HADD)
2.3. Moralising Mind-Policing God (“MMP-God”)
3. Naturalistic Explanations Are Not Incompatible with Theistic Explanations
4. Types of Religious Explanation and Levels of Explanation
Explanatory Pluralism and Competing Explanations
5. Actual versus Potential Explanations
6. Is Freudianism a Good Actual Naturalistic Explanation?
- (1)
- These God-experients all have unresolved unconscious conflicts, perhaps in relation to their attitudes to their fathers;
- (2)
- These unresolved conflicts, together with their memories of their childhood and the childhood of human race, cause them to believe in God, and the inner needs, etc., are projected onto external reality;
- (3)
- This belief somehow causes them to have the theistic beliefs or experiences.
7. How Good Is the Cognitive Science of Religion (CSR)?
8. Is HADD a Good Actual Naturalistic Explanation?
How sensitive is “hypersensitive”? All faculties will produce false positives. We do not expect 100% reliability. Our vision can also be sometimes too sensitive—we need to anticipate (even when reading). So is it hypersensitive or not?How to detect and individuate HADD now?How to prove that a certain belief is formed by HADD now?
9. Is MMP-God a Good Actual Naturalistic Explanation?
10. Epistemic Significance of Naturalistic Explanations
CD1. X entails that Y is false.CD2. X entails that belief in Y is formed in an irrational way.CD3. X is evidence against Y.CD4. X removes/undermines what was once regarded as a source of evidence/good grounds for Y.CD5. X contributes to explaining various phenomena on the hypothesis that Y is false as least almost as well as the hypothesis that Y is true explains the phenomena.
11. Conclusions
Funding
Informed Consent Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | |
2 | Wilkins and Griffiths’ (2013) debunking argument is mainly based on general evolutionary considerations and the lack of the Milvian bridge in the domains of ethics and religion, not founded on the new developments of CSR. |
3 | For example, see Barrett and Church (2013), Clark (2010), Clark and Rabinowitz (2014), Glass (2016), Jong (2013), Jong and Visala (2014), Launonen (2021), Leech and Visala (2012), Murray (2009), Murray and Schloss (2013), Penner (2018), Stepanenko (2021), Thurow (2013, 2014, 2018), Van Eyghen (2016, 2019, 2020), and Visala (2011). |
4 | In fact, not all forms of evolutionary debunking arguments are inimical to theism. For example, Plantinga’s evolutionary argument against naturalism (EAAN) argues that the combination of metaphysical naturalism with an evolutionary account of our belief mechanisms would produce a general debunking argument against all our beliefs, naturalistic evolution included. Hence, this result would be self-defeating (see Plantinga 2011). However, if we do not assume naturalism but are open to the possibility of theism, then, as pointed out below, the naturalistic evolutionary explanations of our cognitive mechanisms need not be debunked in the end. So Plantinga would insist that the real conflict between evolutionary explanations and the reliability of our cognitive mechanisms occur within the naturalistic worldview but not the theistic worldview. Of course, atheists disagree and suggest that there are ways to solve the problem for naturalists—see Wilkins and Griffiths (2013) and note two. We cannot go into these complicated debates here. |
5 | |
6 | |
7 | This kind of perspective is consonant with the explanatory pluralism proposed by some major CSR theorists. For example, see chapter one of McCauley and Lawson (2017) and Visala (2014). |
8 | |
9 | |
10 | Robert Audi suggests that in fact the truth of the Principle of Simplicity itself may be congenial to a theistic explanation: “if the principle of explanatory simplicity is true, that principle itself apparently cannot be non-circularly confirmed empirically and, in any case, might admit of theistic explanation. Arguably, the universe could have been created with governing laws that are in some sense simple and, harmoniously with this, people could have evolved with an intuitive preference for—with a kind of ‘mental tool’ favoring—simplicity precisely because behavior in accordance with true generalities is more likely to be conducive to survival than behavior in accordance with falsehoods” (Audi 2014, pp. 32–33). |
11 | Of course, accepting Nola’s premises about naturalistic explanation may be difficult, psychologically speaking, for theists who believe that God is in direct contact with them. Daniel Lim thinks that CSR “precludes God from being the direct cause of any religious beliefs” (Lim 2016, p. 953), but this is unacceptable for many religious believers. So he suggests that by modeling on a kind of nonreductive physicalism, we can “enable the folk theist to endorse a picture of the world that does not pit supernatural and natural causes against each other”. In his framework, though cognitive scientific mechanisms “are causally sufficient for the formation of religious beliefs,” they “do not exclude supernatural agents from also being directly causally relevant for the formation of the very same religious beliefs” (Lim 2016, p. 963, italics mine). This may provide some comfort for the folk theist, but I want to point out that the notion of “direct contact” may be illusory, even for our most intimate sense experiences that we feel to be immediate. For example, our visual experience of a table before us, according to the contemporary scientific account, is mediated by the propagation of light in space, the biochemical reactions in our eyes, and a lot of “computations” in our brain. |
12 | However, we need to admit that adoption of this distinction would generate other problems for religious believers. For example, if we completely reject direct supernaturalistic explanations, then it would be difficult to make sense of Jesus’ miracles, answered prayers, and so on. I cannot further explore these problems here, and, in any case, my major claim is only that Nola’s argument does not pose a real threat to theism of some sort or another. |
13 | We can further distinguish the distribution explanation, the explanation of why the originally generated religious beliefs can be distributed and established among the human population, from other explanations. However, I will not go into this in this paper. |
14 | This point is even recognized by a critic: “Nature is due to Divine agency. And a natural history is an explanation that traces a belief back to natural causes. Thus, a natural history of a belief or set of beliefs is an explanation which excludes the possibility of supernatural intervention in support of those beliefs without excluding the possibility that God is responsible for the whole shebang” (Pidgen 2013, p. 150). Here, Charles Pidgen seems to agree with my distinction of a crude supernaturalistic explanation and sophisticated theistic explanation. In fact, there are other ways to explain the compatibility of a theistic explanation and naturalistic explanations: explanatory over-determination and divine action in a non-deterministic universe (Audi 2014, pp. 31–32). We cannot explore these possibilities here. |
15 | |
16 | Some advocates of EP lament, “Despite this groundswell of discussion favoring plurality, it has not won much currency in broader theoretical debate in cognitive science” (Dale et al. 2009, p. 3). |
17 | I am not sure that Nola has always kept this distinction in mind. Sometimes he seems to suggest that some naturalistic explanations are actual, at least to some extent. For example, he says, “The various scientific accounts recently developed of the causes of religious beliefs have gained considerable explanatory efficacy… the naturalistic stance offers the better explanation” (Nola 2013, p. 162). |
18 | If a naturalistic explanation is an acceptable explanation that has no debunking implication, then it would not pose any threat to theism. |
19 | For example, Kelly James Clark asks, “Why, after all, could God not have produced in humans a Freudian god-faculty that makes humans universally aware of God under widely realized circumstances? After all, the sensus divinitatis, assuming there is one, must have some determinate shape or form… To show that there are natural processes that produce religious belief does nothing… to discredit it” (Clark 2010, pp. 507–8). |
20 | While I contend that crude supernaturalistic explanation is not the only type of theistic explanation, I do not rule out entirely direct or even miraculous involvement of God in the world. We just need to be very cautious here. |
21 | So far, I have assumed that the general Freudian theory at least is credible. This, of course, is controversial. Some psychologists, e.g., Hans Eysenck (1985), dismiss Freudianism as psychobabble. Even Adolf Grünbaum, not an unsympathetic commentator, says: “far from having good empirical support, at best these obsessional and oedipal hypotheses have yet to be adequately tested, even prior to their use in a psychology of religion. A fortiori, the psychoanalytic ontogeny of theism still lacks evidential warrant” (Grünbaum 1987, p. 166). See also Farrell (1981), Kline (1972), Masson (1990), and Webster (1995) |
22 | For a response to Feuerbach, see Hans Küng (1990, p. 191ff), D. Z. Phillips (2001, chp. 4), Marcel Neusch (1982, p. 31ff), and Clarke and Byrne (1993, chp. 5). For a response to Freud, see Küng (1990), Phillips (2001, chp. 8), Neusch (1982, p. 90ff), and Clarke and Byrne (1993, chp. 8). This is just a small sample of the relevant literature. |
23 | There are a lot of discussions related to this point in the references mentioned in the previous footnote. |
24 | I agree with both sides’ criticisms of the other side. This means that the problem of appealing to just-so stories seems to be a generic problem for the evolutionary explanation of religion. |
25 | Nola makes another point that HADD has to make a comparative likelihood judgement and “HADD need not always get such likelihood ‘judgements’ right and so is unreliable in a new way” (Nola 2013, p. 177). However, again this falls short of establishing HADD’s overall unreliability. He also says, “The cognitive environment in which it operates ought to be sufficiently similar to the one for which it was evolutionarily designed… In much earlier non-religious contexts, it is an adaptation that has evolved to function as a detector of specific range of agents (predators), but its later use in religious contexts as an agency postulator, some argue, is not an adaptation but a functionless byproduct of a trait that had evolved earlier to be functional” (Nola 2013, p. 178). Here, it is a just-so story with many details that are simply hard to establish. Who really knows the original cognitive environment in which HADD was evolutionarily “designed”? How can we establish that the extension of HADD to religious contexts is really “a functionless byproduct”? In a theistic worldview, would it not be possible that this extension is part of God’s design? So the suggestion that this extension necessarily means even more unreliability seems to beg the question again. |
26 | |
27 | This point has been raised by many scholars, including Joshua Thurow (2013). |
28 | Clark and Rabinowitz (2014) has suggested a process of epistemic winnowing of our belief-forming processes, but they only apply this idea to “exceptionally long testimony chains” (p. 122). My idea is more general. |
29 | Thurow himself thinks that “CSR decreases the degree of justification for belief in God a small degree via way CD5” (Thurow 2014, p. 195, fn 6). I may agree with Thurow here, but I would emphasize that this “small degree” is really slight. |
References
- Alston, William. 1991. Perceiving God: The Epistemology of Religious Experience. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Audi, Robert. 2011. Rationality and Religious Commitment. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Audi, Robert. 2014. Intuition, Agency Detection, and Social Coordination as Analytical and Explanatory Constructs in the Cognitive Science of Religion. In The Roots of Religion: Exploring the Cognitive Science of Religion Account. Edited by Roger Trigg and Justin L. Barrett. London: Routledge, pp. 17–36. [Google Scholar]
- Barrett, Justin L. 2011. Cognitive Science, Religion, and Theology. West Conshohocken: Templeton Press. [Google Scholar]
- Barrett, Justin L., and Emily Reed Burdett. 2010. Empirical Progress in Cognitive Science of Religion. The Psychologist 24: 252–55. [Google Scholar]
- Barrett, Justin L., and Ian M. Church. 2013. Should CSR Give Atheists Epistemic Assurance? On Beer Goggles, BFFs, and Skepticism Regarding Religious Beliefs. Monist 96: 311–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Beauregard, Mario, and Denyse O’Leary. 2007. The Spiritual Brain: A Neuroscientist’s Case for the Existence of the Soul. New York: Harper One. [Google Scholar]
- Bechtel, William, and Robert C. Richardson. 1993. Discovery of Complexity: Decomposition and Localization as Strategies in Scientific Research. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bechtel, William. 1990. Multiple Levels of Inquiry in Cognitive Science. Psychological Research 52: 271–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Beyer, Jason A. 2007. A Comparison of Judeo-Christian Theism and Philosophical Naturalism as Explanatory Worldviews. Lewiston: The Edwin Mellen Press. [Google Scholar]
- Braddock, Matthew. 2016. Debunking Arguments and the Cognitive Science of Religion. Theology and Science 14: 268–87. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Braddock, Matthew. 2018. An Evidential Argument for Theism from the Cognitive Science of Religion. In New Developments in the Cognitive Science of Religion: The Rationality of Religious Belief. Edited by Hans van Eyghen, Rik Peels and Gijsbert Van den Brink. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 171–98. [Google Scholar]
- Clark, Kelly James, and Dani Rabinowitz. 2014. Knowledge and the Objection to Religious Belief from Cognitive Science. In The Roots of Religion: Exploring the Cognitive Science of Religion Account. Edited by Roger Trigg and Justin L. Barrett. London: Routledge, pp. 113–26. [Google Scholar]
- Clark, Kelly James. 2010. Reformed Epistemology and the Cognitive Science of Religion. In Science and Religion in Dialogue. Edited by Melville Y. Stewart. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, vol. 1, pp. 500–13. [Google Scholar]
- Clarke, Peter B., and Peter Byrne. 1993. Religion: Defined and Explained. New York: St. Martin’s Press. [Google Scholar]
- Clayton, Philip. 2004. Mind & Emergence: From Quantum to Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dale, Rick, Eric Dietrich, and Anthony Chemero. 2009. Explanatory Pluralism in Cognitive Science. Cognitive Science 33: 739–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Cruz, Helen, and Ryan Nichols, eds. 2016. Advances in Religion, Cognitive Science, and Experimental Philosophy. London: Bloomsbury. [Google Scholar]
- De Smedt, Johan, and Helen de Cruz. 2020. Cognitive Science of Religion and the Nature of the Divine: A Pluralist, Nonconfessional Approach. In Theology Without Walls: The Transreligious Imperative. Edited by Jerry L. Martin. New York: Routledge, pp. 128–37. [Google Scholar]
- Dennett, Daniel C. 2006. Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon. New York: Viking. [Google Scholar]
- Egeland, Jonathan. 2022. The Epistemology of Debunking Argumentation. The Philosophical Quarterly 72: 837–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Eysenck, Hans. 1985. Decline and Fall of the Freudian Empire. London: Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- Farrell, Brian Anthony. 1981. The Standing of Psychoanalysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Forrest, Peter. 1996. God Without the Supernatural: A Defense of Scientific Theism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Glass, David. 2016. Explaining Away and the Cognitive Science of Religion. Theology and Science 14: 288–304. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Goodnick, Liz. 2016. A De Jure Criticism of Theism. Open Theology 2: 23–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Gould, Stephen Jay, and Richard Lewontin. 1979. The Spandrels of St. Marcos and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London Series B 205: 581–98. [Google Scholar]
- Green, Adam. 2015. The Mindreading Debate and the Cognitive Science of Religion. Sophia 54: 61–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Grünbaum, Adolf. 1987. Psychoanalysis and Theism. Monist 70: 152–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hay, David. 1990. Religious Experience Today: Studying the Facts. London: Mowbray. [Google Scholar]
- Jong, Jonathan, and Aku Visala. 2014. Evolutionary Debunking Arguments against Theism, Reconsidered. International Journal of Philosophy of Religion 76: 243–58. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jong, Jonathan. 2013. Explaining Religion (Away?): Theism and the Cognitive Science of Religion. Sophia 52: 521–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kahane, Guy. 2011. Evolutionary Debunking Arguments. Nous 45: 103–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Klenk, Michael. 2019. Objectivist Conditions for Defeat and Evolutionary Debunking Arguments. Ratio 32: 246–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Kline, Paul. 1972. Fact and Fantasy in Freudian Theory. London: Methuen. [Google Scholar]
- Koster, John P. 1989. The Atheist Syndrome. Brentwood: Wolgemuth and Hyatt. [Google Scholar]
- Küng, Hans. 1990. Freud and the Problem of God, Enlarg. ed. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kvandal, Halvor. 2021. God Naturalized: Epistemological Reflections on Theistic Belief in Light of the New Science of Religion. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Kwan, Kai-man. 2006. Are Religious Beliefs Human Projections? In A Religious Atheist? Critical Essays on the Work of Lloyd Geering. Edited by Raymond Pelly and Peter Stuart. Dunedin: Otago University Press, pp. 41–66. [Google Scholar]
- Kwan, Kai-man. 2011. The Rainbow of Experiences, Critical Trust, and God: A Defense of Holistic Empiricism. New York: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
- Launonen, Lari. 2021. Debunking Arguments Gain Little from Cognitive Science of Religion. Zygon 56: 416–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Leech, David, and Aku Visala. 2012. How Relevant Is the Cognitive Science of Religion to Philosophy of Religion? In Scientific Approaches to the Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Yujin Nagasawa. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 165–83. [Google Scholar]
- Leech, David, and Aku Visala. 2014. The Cognitive Science of Religion and Theism Again: A Reply to Leo Nareaho. Religious Studies 50: 67–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lim, Daniel. 2016. Cognitive Science of Religion and Folk Theistic Belief. Zygon 51: 949–65. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Masson, Jeffrey. 1990. Final Analysis: The Making and Unmaking of a Psychoanalyst. London: Fontana. [Google Scholar]
- Mawson, Timothy. J. 2014. Cognitive Science of Religion and the Rationality of Classical Theism. In The Roots of Religion: Exploring the Cognitive Science of Religion Account. Edited by Roger Trigg and Justin L. Barrett. London: Routledge, pp. 149–66. [Google Scholar]
- McBrayer, Justin. 2018. The Epistemology of Genealogies. In New Developments in the Cognitive Science of Religion: The Rationality of Religious Belief. Edited by Hans Van Eyghen, Rik Peels and Gijsbert Van den Brink. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 157–70. [Google Scholar]
- McCauley, Robert N., and E. Thomas Lawson. 2017. Philosophical Foundations of the Cognitive Science of Religion: A Head Start. London: Bloomsbury Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Murray, Michael J. 2009. Scientific Explanations of Religion and the Justification of Religious Belief. In The Believing Primate: Scientific, Philosophical, and Theological Reflections on the Origin of Religion. Edited by Jeffrey Schloss and Michael Murray. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 168–78. [Google Scholar]
- Murray, Michael J., and Jeffrey P. Schloss. 2013. Evolutionary Accounts of Religion and the Justification of Religious Belief. In Debating Christian Theism. Edited by James P. Moreland, Chad Meister and Khaldoun A. Sweis. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 242–58. [Google Scholar]
- Neusch, Marcel. 1982. The Modern Sources of Atheism. New York: Paulist. [Google Scholar]
- Nola, Robert. 2013. Do Naturalistic Explanations of Religious Beliefs Debunk Religion? In A New Science of Religion. Edited by Gregory W. Dawes and James Maclaurin. New York: Routledge, pp. 162–88. [Google Scholar]
- Nola, Robert. 2018. Demystifying Religious Belief. In New Developments in the Cognitive Science of Religion: The Rationality of Religious Belief. Edited by Hans van Eyghen, Rik Peels and Gijsbert Van den Brink. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 71–92. [Google Scholar]
- Penner, Myron A. 2018. Cognitive Science of Religion, Atheism, and Theism. Faith and Philosophy 35: 105–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Phillips, Dewi Zephaniah. 2001. Religion and the Hermeneutics of Contemplation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pidgen, Charles R. 2013. Subversive Explanations. In A New Science of Religion. Edited by Gregory W. Dawes and James Maclaurin. New York: Routledge, pp. 147–61. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Alvin C. 2011. “Evolution versus Naturalism” and “It’s No Illusion!”. In The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science. Edited by Bruce L. Gordon and William A. Dembski. Wilmington: ISI Books, pp. 137–51, 166–71. [Google Scholar]
- Powell, Russell, and Steve Clarke. 2012. Religion as an Evolutionary Byproduct: A Critique of the Standard Model. British Journal of Philosophy of Science 63: 457–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Preus, J. Samuel. 1987. Explaining Religion. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Putnam, Hilary. 1992. Renewing Philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rowland, Richard. 2019. Local Evolutionary Debunking Argumentation. The Philosophical Perspective 33: 170–99. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schupbach, Jonah N. 2016. Competing Explanations and Explaining-Away Arguments. Theology and Science 14: 256–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schupbach, Jonah N., and David H. Glass. 2017. Hypothesis Competition beyond Mutual Exclusivity. Philosophy of Science 84: 810–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Segal, Robert A. 1992. Explaining and Interpreting Religion: Essays on the Issue. New York: Peter Lang. [Google Scholar]
- Sober, Elliott. 2015. Ockham’s Razors: A User’s Manual. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Stepanenko, Walter Scott. 2021. The Epistemic Parity of Religious-Apologetic and Religion-Debunking Responses to the Cognitive Science of Religion. Religions 12: 466. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Swinburne, Richard G. 1968. The Argument from Design. Philosophy 43: 199–212. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Swinburne, Richard. 1997. Simplicity as Evidence of Truth. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Swinburne, Richard. 2004. The Existence of God, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Thurow, Joshua C. 2013. Does the Cognitive Science Show Belief in God to Be Irrational? The Epistemic Consequences of the Cognitive Science of Religion. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 74: 77–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Thurow, Joshua C. 2014. Some Reflections on Cognitive Science, Doubt, and Religious Belief. In The Roots of Religion: Exploring the Cognitive Science of Religion Account. Edited by Roger Trigg and Justin Barrett. London: Routledge, pp. 189–207. [Google Scholar]
- Thurow, Joshua C. 2018. Debunking and Fully Apt Belief. Unisinos Journal of Philosophy 19: 294–301. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Trigg, Roger, and Justin L. Barrett, eds. 2014. The Roots of Religion: Exploring the Cognitive Science of Religion. Farnham: Ashgate. [Google Scholar]
- Van Eyghen, Hans, Rik Peels, and Gijsbert Van den Brink, eds. 2018. New Developments in the Cognitive Science of Religion: The Rationality of Religious Belief. Cham: Springer International Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Van Eyghen, Hans. 2016. Two Types of ‘Explaining Away’ Arguments in the Cognitive Science of Religion. Zygon 51: 966–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Eyghen, Hans. 2019. Is Supernatural Belief Unreliably Formed? International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 85: 125–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Eyghen, Hans. 2020. Arguing from Cognitive Science of Religion: Is Religious Belief Debunked? London: Bloomsbury. [Google Scholar]
- Visala, Aku. 2011. Naturalism, Theism and the Cognitive Study of Religion: Religion Explained? Farnham: Ashgate. [Google Scholar]
- Visala, Aku. 2014. Explaining Religion at Different Levels: From Fundamentalism to Pluralism. In The Roots of Religion: Exploring the Cognitive Science of Religion Account. Edited by Roger Trigg and Justin L. Barrett. London: Routledge, pp. 55–74. [Google Scholar]
- Vitz, Paul C. 1999. Faith of the Fatherless: The Psychology of Atheism. Dallas: Spence. [Google Scholar]
- Webster, Richard. 1995. Why Freud Was Wrong: Sin, Science and Psychoanalysis. London: Fontana. [Google Scholar]
- Wilkins, John S., and Paul E. Griffiths. 2013. Evolutionary Debunking Arguments in Three Domains: Fact, Value, and Religion. In A New Science of Religion. Edited by Gregory W. Dawes and James Maclaurin. New York: Routledge, pp. 133–46. [Google Scholar]
- Wilson, David Sloan. 2009. Evolutionary Social Constructivism: Narrowing (but Not Yet Bridging) the Gap. In The Believing Primate: Scientific, Philosophical, and Theological Reflections on the Origin of Religion. Edited by Jeffrey Schloss and Michael Murray. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 318–38. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Kwan, K.-m. An Atheistic Argument from Naturalistic Explanations of Religious Belief: A Preliminary Reply to Robert Nola. Religions 2022, 13, 1084. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13111084
Kwan K-m. An Atheistic Argument from Naturalistic Explanations of Religious Belief: A Preliminary Reply to Robert Nola. Religions. 2022; 13(11):1084. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13111084
Chicago/Turabian StyleKwan, Kai-man. 2022. "An Atheistic Argument from Naturalistic Explanations of Religious Belief: A Preliminary Reply to Robert Nola" Religions 13, no. 11: 1084. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13111084
APA StyleKwan, K. -m. (2022). An Atheistic Argument from Naturalistic Explanations of Religious Belief: A Preliminary Reply to Robert Nola. Religions, 13(11), 1084. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13111084