Brief Remarks on Sterba’s Moral Argument from Evil
Abstract
:1. Introduction
In this book, I have drawn on untapped resources in ethics that have proved useful in resolving the problem of evil that has long troubled theists and atheists alike. Those resources cluster around the Pauline Principle that is at the heart of the Doctrine of Double Effect.
In both traditional and contemporary ethics we find an ethical principle that seems to be in direct conflict with God’s permitting evil and then making up for it later. The ethical principle is embedded in the Doctrine of Double Effect and frequently referred to as the Pauline Principle because it was endorsed by St. Paul (Romans 3:8). The principle holds that we should never do evil that good may come of it.
Now the Pauline Principle prohibits doing evil that good may come of it. But good can come of evil in two ways. It can come by way of preventing evil or it can come by way of providing some new good.
(PP) We should never do evil as a means to prevent evil or as a means to provide good.
In recent years, discussion of the problem of evil in the world has been advanced by utilizing resources of contemporary metaphysics and epistemology, for example, Alvin Plantinga’s application of modal logic to the logical problem of evil and William Rowe, Stephen Wykstra and Paul Draper’s application of probabilistic epistemology to the evidential problem of evil.
I think that we can expect a similar advance once we do bring to bear yet untapped resources of ethics on our understanding of the problem of evil. But I also think that this advance will be even more important than the other advances that have come from modal logic and probabilistic epistemology. […] Bringing untapped resources of ethics to bear on the problem […] should actually help us reach a solution to the problem of evil.
Now it might be objected here that while God cannot do evil that good may come of it, God could permit evil that good may come of it. Of course, moral philosophers do recognize a distinction between doing and permitting evil. Doing evil is normally worse than permitting evil. But when the evil is significant and one can easily prevent it, then permitting evil can become morally equivalent to doing it. The same kind of moral blame attaches to both actions […] Likewise, God’s permitting significantly evil consequences when those consequences can easily be prevented is morally equivalent to God’s doing something that is seriously wrong.
the Pauline Principle […] shows that it would be impermissible for God to permit the significantly evil consequences of our immoral actions either as a means to prevent greater evil (given that God could prevent the greater evil without permitting the lesser evil) or as a means to securing a good to which we are not entitled (given that we humans are always prohibited from doing just that). Hence, there is a logical contradiction between the existence of God, our moral requirements, and what would have to be God’s widespread failure to prevent the loss of significant freedoms in our world resulting from immoral actions.
2. Historical Digression: Leibniz, Kant and the Pauline Principle
(EPP) We should never do or permit significant evil as a means to prevent evil or as a means to provide good, if we can easily prevent it
The rule which states, non esse facienda mala, ut eveniant bona, and which even forbids the permission of a moral evil with the end of obtaining a physical good, far from being violated, is here proved, and its source and its reason are demonstrated.
God wills all good […] antecedently, […] wills the best consequently as an end [or ‘intention’], […] wills what is indifferent, and physical evil, sometimes as a means. But he wills moral evil only as the sine quo non or as a hypothetical necessity, for he is bound to singling out the best.
One may say of physical evil, that God wills it often as a penalty owing to guilt, and often also as a means to an end, that is, to prevent greater evils or to obtain greater good. The penalty serves also for amendment and example. Evil often serves to make us savour good the more; sometimes too it contributes to a greater perfection in him who suffers it […]”.(§ 23)
must only be admitted or permitted in so far as it is considered to be a certain consequence of an indispensable duty: as for instance if a man who was determined not to permit another’s sin were to fail of his own duty, or as if an officer on guard at an important post were to leave it, especially in time of danger, in order to prevent a quarrel in the town between two soldiers of the garrison who wanted to kill each other.(§ 24)
(REPP-Leibniz) We should never do or permit significant evil as a means to prevent evil or as a means to provide good, if we can easily prevent the significant evil without violating our duties.
(REPP-Sterba) We should never do or permit a lesser significant evil as a means to prevent a greater significant evil, if we can easily prevent the greater evil without permitting the lesser evil.
Some adversary not being able to answer this argument will perchance answer the conclusion by a counter-argument, saying that the world could have been without sin and without sufferings; but I deny that then it would have been better.
It is true that one may imagine possible worlds without sin and without unhappiness […]: but these same worlds again would be very inferior to ours in goodness. I cannot show you this in detail. For can I know and can I present infinities to you and compare them together? But you must judge with me ab effectu, since God has chosen this world as it is.
In relation to the Highest-Good possible under his rule alone, namely the existence of rational beings under moral laws, we will conceive of this original being as omniscient, so that even what is inmost in their dispositions (which is what constitutes the real moral value of the actions of rational beings in the world) is not hidden from him; as omnipotent, so that he can make the whole of nature suitable for this highest end; as omnibenevolent and at the same time just, because these two properties (united as wisdom) constitute the conditions of the causality of a supreme cause of the world as a Highest-Good under moral laws; and likewise all of the remaining transcendental properties, such as eternity, omnipresence, etc. (for goodness and justice are moral properties), which must be presupposed in relation to such a final end, must also be thought in such a being.(KU, AA V: 444)
3. Further Thoughts on Sterba’s Moral Argument from Evil
Moral evil prevention requirement IPrevent, rather than permit, significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions without violating anyone’s rights (a good to which we have a right), as needed, when that can easily be done.Moral evil prevention requirement IIDo not permit significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions simply to provide other rational beings with goods they would morally prefer not to have.Moral evil prevention requirement IIIDo not permit, rather than prevent, significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions on would-be victims (which would violate their rights) in order to provide them with goods to which they do not have a right, when there are countless morally unobjectionable ways of providing those goods.
- There is an all-good, all-powerful God. […]
- If there is an all-good, all-powerful God, then necessarily he would be adhering to Moral Evil Prevention Requirements I–III.
- If God were adhering to Moral Evil Prevention Requirements I-III, then necessarily significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions would not be obtaining through what would have to be his permission.
- Significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions do obtain all around us, which, if God exists, would have to be through his permission. […]
- Therefore, it is not the case that there is an all-good, all-powerful God.
By contrast, what would be ideal from the perspective of freedom is a world where everyone’s freedom is appropriately constrained […] Accordingly, I contend that if we want to appropriately constrain freedom, we should have a policy that constrains the less significant freedoms of would-be wrongdoers in order to secure the more significant freedom of their would-be victims. Surely, that would be a justified policy of constraint. In addition, it would not deprive would-be wrongdoers of their status as moral agents nor would it leave with only a toy or a playpen freedom. Thus, even when serious wrongdoers are prevented from carrying out the final steps of their evil actions with significant and especially horrendous consequences for their victims, they would still have the freedom to imagine, intend, and even take initial steps toward carrying out their wrongdoing.
[…] we are not imagining that God is always preventing the evil consequences of wrongful actions. Rather, we are assuming that God would be allowing evildoers to bring about the evil consequences of their actions for a broad range of cases where the consequences, especially for others, are not significantly evil. We are also assuming that God would be allowing would-be wrongdoers to imagine, intend, or even take the initial steps toward carrying out their seriously wrongful actions, and just stopping wrongdoers from bringing about significantly and especially horrendously evil consequences of those actions.
- Say that an immoral action is tendentially harmful if and only if it is true that, if God did not intervene, it would (eventually) lead to significant and horrendous evils.
- Say that an immoral action is potentially harmful if and only if it is true that, if God did not intervene, it might (eventually) lead to significant and horrendous evils.9
- Say that an immoral action is tendentially harmless if and only if it is true that, if God did not intervene, it would not (eventually) lead to significant and horrendous evils.
(CEM) It is either true that (if it were true that p, it would be true that q), or it is true that (if it were true that p, it would not be true that q).
(CC) If it is true that p and it is true that q, then it is true that (if it were true that p, then it would be true that q).
4. Conclusions
Author Contributions
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
1 | All citations from Leibniz’s work are based on the following translation: (Leibniz 2009). |
2 | One might think that in that case God is determined to single out the best of all possible worlds; thus, it cannot be considered as a free act (for it seems that God could have not done otherwise). Leibniz’s argument is here more complicated; however, we cannot dwell on this issue here. For an interpretation according to which Leibniz cannot avoid such a conclusion see (Adams 1994), pp. 40–42; for a different position see, e.g., (Rateau 2014), pp. 105–9. |
3 | Among other things, Leibniz thinks that not creating at all is (i) a possibility of God as well, and that (ii) this possibility is nevertheless not the best. |
4 | Sterba might insist that, given any possible world, God—as an infinitely powerful being—would always be able to create a better possible world (compare, e.g., Aquinas’s treatment of the topic in s. th. I q. 25 art. 6). He might conclude that it is logically contradictory to assume both that God exists and that there is a best of all possible worlds. However, the argument from above works even without assuming both that God exists and that there is a best of all possible worlds. Suppose, for example, that God exists and that every possible world in which God prevents the evils of the actual world is worse than the actual world (compare, e.g., Aquinas’s suggestions in s. th. I q. 22 art. 2). It follows that God cannot prevent the greater evil of a worse world without permitting the evils of the actual world. Arguably, there is no logical contradiction in both assuming that God exists and that every possible world in which God prevents the evils of the actual world is worse than the actual world. The passages of Aquinas’s work can be found in Thomas Aquinas, “Summa Theologiae”, in (Aquinas 1888–1906). |
5 | We will use the following abbreviations: RGV, AA VI = Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der bloßen Vernunft; KpV, AA V = Kritik der praktischen Vernunft; KU, AA V = Kritik der Urteilskraft. All citations are taken from Kant’s Akademieausgabe (=AA) (Kant 1900a, 1900b, 1900c). |
6 | For a detailed analysis of Kant’s argument see (Kravitz 2022). |
7 | There are two (intimately connected) debates in contemporary philosophy of religion that turn out to be relevant in this regard: First, the debate about whether counterfactuals of creaturely freedom (e.g., counterfactuals about what a free agent would have chosen, had God not intervened) are possibly true. Second, the debate about whether counterfactuals of creaturely freedom, if possibly true, are possibly foreknown by God. See, for example, (Hasker 1989; van Inwagen 1997, 2006; Flint 1998). In view of these debates, it is far from clear whether God—as an omniscient being—would have to foreknow what a free agent would have chosen, had God not intervened. |
8 | In a way, Kant seems to suggest a ‘philosophical defence of theism’, contrary to a ‘theodicean argument’. Roughly: To argue that the presence of evil in the world is compatible with God’s attributes amounts to advocating a philosophical defence of theism; to suggest a further account of God’s possible reasons for issuing (permitting) evil constitutes a theodicean argument. For interpretation in this spirit see, e.g., (Dieringer 2009). This analogy, however, does not capture Kant’s precise intent, but this issue lies beyond the scope of this paper. For details see (Kravitz 2020). |
9 | Say that it is true that (if it were true that p, then it might be true that q) if and only if it is not true that (if it were true that p, it would not be true that q). For the interdefinability of ‘might’ and ‘would’, see (Lewis 1973, pp. 2, 80–81; van Inwagen 1997, p. 232). See also (Bennett 2003, pp. 189–92; Stalnaker 1978; DeRose 1994; Leitgeb 2012, p. 111). |
10 | The claim is not that we know that God has prevented every tendentially harmful action; the claim is that arguing that God has prevented every tendentially harmful action is compatible with what we know. But, again, it is enough to assume that it is not logically contradictory that God has prevented every tendentially harmful immoral action. |
11 | Sterba might insist, of course, that God would still have violated his obligation to prevent the significant and horrendously evil consequences of immoral actions. This, however, would not solve but only postpone the problem. The reason is that one might distinguish between tendentially and potentially harmful consequences of immoral actions and still maintain that God has always intervened in the course of events that have resulted from immoral actions when his not intervening would have led to significant and horrendous evils (and that he has not intervened, by contrast, when his not intervening only might have led to significant and horrendous evils). |
12 | Proof: Take any immoral action that is potentially harmful. It follows that, if God did not intervene, it might lead to significant and horrendous evils. It follows, further, that it is not true that, if God did not intervene, it would not lead to significant and horrendous evils (because of the interdefinability of ‘might’ and ‘would’). By CEM, it is true that, if God did not intervene, it would lead to significant and horrendous evils. This potentially harmful immoral action is, therefore, not only potentially harmful but also tendentially harmful. |
13 | For a discussion of CEM, see (Stalnaker 1978; Lewis 1973, pp. 79–83; Bennett 2003, pp. 183–93; Cross 2009; Williams 2010; Leitgeb 2012, pp. 88–90). |
14 | Proof: Take any immoral action that God has not prevented and that has led to significant and horrendous evils. It follows, by CC, that, if God did not prevent it, it would have led to significant and horrendous evils. This immoral action, therefore, is tendentially harmful. |
15 | For a discussion of CC, see (Stalnaker 1978; Lewis 1973, pp. 26–31; Walters 2009; Ahmed 2011; Leitgeb 2012, pp. 86–93; Walters and Williams 2013). |
16 | The law of Counterfactual Modus Ponens (CMP) is the law that, if it is true that p and it is true that (if it were true that p, it would be true that q), then it is true that q. Take now any immoral thought, intention, action, etc., that God has in fact not prevented and that has in fact led to significant and horrendous evils. If this immoral thought, intention, action, etc., were not potentially harmful, it would not be true that (if God did not prevent it, it might have led to significant and horrendous evils). It would follow (from the interdefinability of ‘might’ and ‘would’) that it is true that (if God did not prevent it, it would not have led to significant and horrendous evils). It would follow, by CMP (given that God has not prevented it), that it has not led to significant and horrendous evils (contrary to the assumptions). This immoral thought, intention, action, etc., therefore, is potentially harmful. |
References
- Adams, Robert Merrihew. 1994. Leibniz: Determinist, Theist, Idealist. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ahmed, Arif. 2011. Walters on Conjunction Conditionalization. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 111: 115–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1888–1906. Summa Theologiae. In S. Thomae Aquinatis Doctoris Angelici Opera Omnia. Vols. 4–12, Rome: Commissio Leonina. [Google Scholar]
- Bennett, Jonathan. 2003. A Philosophical Guide to Conditionals. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Cross, Charles B. 2009. Conditional Excluded Middle. Erkenntnis 70: 173–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- DeRose, Keith. 1994. Lewis on ‘Might’ and ‘Would’ Counterfactual Conditionals. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 24: 413–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dieringer, Volker. 2009. Kants Lösung des Theodizeeproblems. In Eine Rekonstruktion. Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog. [Google Scholar]
- Flint, Thomas P. 1998. Divine Providence. The Molinist Account. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hasker, William. 1989. God, Time, and Knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel, ed. 1900a. Kants Gesammelter Schriften. Akademieausgabe. In Preussische Akademie der Wissenschaften. Berlin: De Gruyter, vols. 1–22. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel, ed. 1900b. Kants Gesammelter Schriften. Akademieausgabe. In Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin. Berlin: De Gruyter, vol. 23. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel, ed. 1900c. Kants Gesammelter Schriften. Akademieausgabe. In Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen. Berlin: De Gruyter, vol. 24. [Google Scholar]
- Kravitz, Amit. 2020. Kant’s Conception of Theodicy and his Argument from Metaphysical Evil against it. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 102: 453–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kravitz, Amit. 2022. Revelation’s Entrenchment in Pure Reason in Fichte’s Versuch einer Kritik aller Offenbarung. Kant-Studien 113: 299–329. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 2009. Theodicy. Essays on the Goodness of God, the Freedom of Man and the Origin of Evil. Translated by E. M. Huggard. Chicago: Open Court. [Google Scholar]
- Leitgeb, Hannes. 2012. A Probabilistic Semantics for Counterfactuals. Part B. The Review of Symbolic Logic 5: 85–121. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Lewis, David. 1973. Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Rateau, Paul. 2014. The Theoretical Foundations of the Leibnizian Theodicy and its Apologetic Aim. In New Essays on Leibniz’s Theodicy. Edited by Larry M. Jorgensen and Samuel Newlands. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 92–111. [Google Scholar]
- Stalnaker, Robert C. 1978. A Defense of Conditional Excluded Middle. In Ifs. Edited by William Harper, Robert C. Stalnaker and Glenn Pearce. Dordrecht: Dordrecht Reidel, pp. 87–104. [Google Scholar]
- Sterba, James P. 2019. Is a Good God Logically Possible? Cham: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- van Inwagen, Peter. 1983. An Essay on Free Will. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- van Inwagen, Peter. 1997. Against Middle Knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 21: 225–36. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- van Inwagen, Peter. 2006. The Problem of Evil. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Walters, Lee. 2009. Morgenbesser’s Coin and Counterfactuals with True Components. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 109: 365–79. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Walters, Lee, and J. Robert G. Williams. 2013. An Argument for Conjunction Conditionalization. The Review of Symbolic Logic 6: 573–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Williams, J. Robert G. 2010. Defending Conditional Excluded Middle. Noûs 44: 650–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Hausmann, M.; Kravitz, A. Brief Remarks on Sterba’s Moral Argument from Evil. Religions 2022, 13, 1038. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13111038
Hausmann M, Kravitz A. Brief Remarks on Sterba’s Moral Argument from Evil. Religions. 2022; 13(11):1038. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13111038
Chicago/Turabian StyleHausmann, Marco, and Amit Kravitz. 2022. "Brief Remarks on Sterba’s Moral Argument from Evil" Religions 13, no. 11: 1038. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13111038
APA StyleHausmann, M., & Kravitz, A. (2022). Brief Remarks on Sterba’s Moral Argument from Evil. Religions, 13(11), 1038. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13111038