Unity of the Existence of God and the Knowledge of God in the Phenomenological Ontology of Henry
Abstract
:1. The Absolute Immanence of Life as the Essence of Deity
What is specific to life as self-revelation is therefore the fact that it reveals itself. This apparent tautology implies two distinct meanings that we must now separate for the first time. Self-revelation, when it concerns the essence of life, means, on the one hand, that it is life that achieves the revelation, that reveals, but on the other hand, that what life reveals is itself. And it is here that the mode of revelation specific to life differs fundamentally from that of the world. The world, too, reveals and makes manifest, but within the “outside”, casting a thing outside itself, as we have seen, in such a way that it never shows itself as other, different, external, in its setting of radical exteriority that it the “outside-itself” of the world. Hence it is double exterior: external to the power that makes it manifest—and this is where the contrast between Truth and what it makes true intervenes—and also exterior to itself. … If, then, Life reveals itself not only in the sense that it achieves revelation but also because it is itself that it reveals in such a revelation, then Life is possible only because its own mode of revelation ignores the world and its “outside”. Living is not possible in the world. … Life embraces, experiences without distance or difference. Solely on this condition can it experience itself, be itself what it experiences—and, consequently, be itself that which experiences and which is experienced.
2. The Phenomenological Signification of Henry’s “Material” in the History of Phenomenology
In Logical Investigations, Husserl specifies the objectifying act by the quality of the act, and he distinguishes two types of act: the positional act and the non-positional act. The positional act aims at the object as existing; the non-positional act suspends the existence of its object. The latter is based on the former. The non-objectifying act could also be distinguished into the positional mode and the non-positional mode, but in the non-objectifying act, the non-positional act does not need to be built on the positional act. For example, joy and sadness, as intentional acts, belong to the positional act; they presuppose the existence of the simple object in order to be completely realized. However, we should note that existence here does not signify existence in the consciousness, like the internal object in the consciousness. At the same time, the representation is not an image or a copy of the appearing object, otherwise it presupposes a consciousness of image to explain the constitution of this image-copy of the objective donating intentionally. Briefly, this way of proposing the problem brings about an infinitive regression. In fact, the consciousness of image is another type of act, which has its own essential character and its own quality. Husserl thinks it is absurd to make a distinction between the intentional object and the external physical object. When we say the representation presupposes the existence of an object, it means what exists is the intention, the intended object exists in an intentional way. Consequently, we could not only intend a physical object, but also God, all fictive beings and even a contradictory concept, for example, the circular square. In the intentional consciousness or in the representation, what exists is just the intentional object, regardless of this object’s existence or not in the physical world. The notion of representation, which comes from Brentano, is an ambiguous concept that Husserl tries to clarify in Logical Investigations, so he replaces it with the term of noesis and noema in Idea I. This terminological change indicates Husserl’s transcendental turn in Idea I.“I hear” can mean in psychology “I am having sensations”: in ordinary speech it means “I am perceiving”; I hear the adagio of the violin, the twittering of the birds etc. … whatever the origin of the experienced contents now present in consciousness, we can think that the same sensational contents should be present with a differing interpretation, i.e., that the same contents should serve to ground perceptions of different objects. Interpretations itself can never be reduced to an influx of new sensations; it is an act-character, a mode of consciousness, of “mindedness” (Zumuteseins). We call the experiencing of sensations in this conscious manner the perception of the object in question.
3. The Ontological Unity of Reality and Self-Knowledge in the Subjective Body
Henry points out: I am the life of my body, the ego is the substance of its organism, the matter and the principle of its movements, and it is because it would be nothing without this foundation. It is the absolute life of subjectivity; our transcendent body finds in it its unity and the principle of ontological determinations. Therefore, Henry’s ego is not a pure form without content, but a real substance of the subject manifested in the substantial material of our organic body. Because the organic body confers its unity to the ego, it cannot separate from the subjective reality of our bodily movements. In this sense, the organic body, as a living body, could escape from the phenomenological reduction. According to Henry, the difference between the organic body and the absolute body is a phenomenological difference, but the organic body “presents itself to us in a sort of absolute knowledge. Because it is the strict non-represented correlate of the intentionality of our absolute body, it is always entirely present to us and we possess it in a knowledge which excludes all limitation and all possibility of error” (Henry 1975, p. 194).1. The original being of the subjective body, i.e., the absolute body revealed in the internal transcendental experience of movement. The life of this original body is the absolute life of subjectivity; in it we live, we move, we sense, it is the alpha and the omega of our experience of the world, it is through it that being comes to the world, it is in the resistance which it experiences that the essence of the real is manifested to us and that everything acquires consistency, form, and value.2. The organic body is the immediate and moving terminus of the absolute movement of the subjective body, or rather it is the ensemble of the termini over which movement has a hold. Because there is a structure to this organic body, it is divided into various transcendent masses whose diversity is always maintained in the unity of the absolute life of the original body. The existence of such structures interior to the organic body is of great importance relative to the problem of internal sensations, a problem about which we have not, as yet, spoken.3. The objective body which is the object of an external perception and which can become the theme of scientific research is the only body which philosophical tradition knows, and it is this exclusively objective conception which is at the origin of so many false problems—notably the famous problem of the unity of the soul and body—as of so many theories which strive, even though in vain, to resolve them.
Besides, we must indicate that in Philosophy and phenomenology of the body, only the subjective body belongs to the immanent sphere, but in Incarnation, by integrating the three kinds of body in the absolute immanence or in the original flesh, Henry refines the conception of the flesh7. Henry affirms that “the reality of Christ’s body in the Incarnation as a condition for the identification of man with God” (Henry 2015, p. 9), the reality of Christ’s body presents as a sphere of the absolute immanence, which is the essence of life.It is not because our body is also a transcendent body, a body such as philosophy understood it before the discovery of the subjective body, that the being of man is a situated being. On the contrary, our objective transcendent body is situated in a strictly determined sense peculiar to it only because our absolute body is once and for all situated as subjectivity in a transcendental relationship with the world.
4. The Problem of Creation in Henry, Lao Tseu and Yangming
4.1. The Creation of Life and the Creation of World
The Tao that can be told is not the eternal Tao.The name that can be named is not the eternal name.The nameless is the beginning of heaven and Earth.The named is the mother of the ten thousand things.Ever desireless, one can see the mystery.Ever desiring, one sees the manifestations.These two spring from the same source but differ in name; this appears as darkness.Darkness within darkness. The gate to all mystery.
I do not know its name, Call it Tao.For lack of a better word, I call it great.Being great, it flows. It flows far away.Having gone far, it returns.Therefore, “Tao is great; Heaven is great; Earth is great; The king is also great.”These are the four great powers of the universe. And the king is one of them.Man follows Earth.Earth follows heaven.Heaven follows the Tao.Tao follows what is natural.
It is the positive essence of Being which uncovers itself in the apparently non-essential characteristic of the essence. That such an essence is positive in an ultimate sense is shown in the fact that it is the condition. Everything that is finds in it its foundation. Universal phenomenological ontology, which deliberately orients itself toward the task of an understanding of the essence, is truly fundamental ontology.
4.2. The Immanent Creation of Moral Principle in Wang Yangming
5. Conclusions
Funding
Informed Consent Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | In his later works, Henry proposes self-affection (auto-affection) of the flesh (chair), which is a radical immanance of the flesh. It displays the experience of the self as the flesh, which is the experience of the Life of God (Henry 2012). |
2 | Henry thinks that “The cogito is only one of these rational truths, but precisely because it permits consciousness to attain—at the very heart of its own individual Being—the order of rationality, it remains the ideal of an inquiry which is first realized in itself and to which it imparts or entrusts a specific task: the acquisition of contents which can serve as valid under the rubric of ‘truths’” (Henry 1973, p. 12). At the same time, Henry thinks that “The task of philosophy is in no way an accumulation of truths” (Henry 1973, p. 13). |
3 | In the article «Le commencement cartésien et l’idée de la phénoménologie», Henry analyzes the relation between the philosophy of the ego cogito of Descartes and phenomenology: “A une condition et à une seule, à la condition que le cogito cartésien constitue l’acte de naissance de la phénoménologie elle-même. En ce cas, une étude phénoménologique du cogito n’est pas seulement possible, elle est la seule possible. Que la phénoménologie définisse la seule voie d’accès à ce qui est pensé et doit être pensé dans le cogito” (Henry 1997, p. 200). |
4 | In order to clarify the relationship of the duality of revelation, the self-revelation of life and the revelation of the world, Henry endows an transcendental existence to life. He thinks the self-revelation of life is the possible condition of the revelation of the world, life, as the radical immanence, is the essence of the transcendence or the appearing of world. |
5 | “I am my body” means: “The original being of my body is an internal transcendental experience and; consequently, the life of this body is a mode of the absolute life of the ego. ’I have a body’, this means: A transcendent body manifests itself for me also and presents itself to me as subject to, by a relationship of dependence, the absolute body which, as the theory of the constititution of our own body has shown, also gives basis to this objective body as well as to the relationship of possession which binds it to the ego” (Henry 1975, p. 196). |
6 | Henry also thinks, “The dualism of the soul and the body, i.e., the original being of the subjective body and the transcendent body, is only a particular case of ontological dualism. The act whereby subjective movement stretches out the hand as an organic mass which it knows interiorly, as the terminus toward which, not its intellectual knowledge, but its motor knowledge transcends itself is no more or less mysterious than the act whereby my look aims at and attains the tree standing there on the hill. The dualism which the description of these phenomena brings to light is not an ontic dualism; it is a dualism which does not differ from the one we recognized between original truth and the truth of transcendent being, and which expresses the relationship fundative of the unity between these two truths, fundative of the unity of experience—it is a dualism which has nothing to do with Cartesian dualism” (Henry 1975, p. 135). From this paragraph, we can know that Henry proposes a new ontological phenomenology to deepen the phenomenological discussion. |
7 | For a profound analysis of this question (Laoureux 2005, p. 147). |
8 | Lao Tsu or Laozi (l. c. 500 BCE, Chinese: 老子; pinyin: Lǎozǐ; Wade: Lao³Tzu³), his real name is Li Er (李耳, Lǐěr), he was a Chinese philosopher credited with founding the philosophical system of Taoism. He is best known as the author of the Laozi (later retitled the Tao-Te-Ching translated as “The Way of Virtue” or “The Classic of the Way and Virtue”) the work which exemplifies his thought. Lao-Tzu—World History Encyclopedia. |
9 | In this translation, the Ren (人) is translated as the king, but in the original chinese text, Ren means a human being, not the king of a kingdom. From this phrase, we can see that Lao Tseu notices the existence of human in the world, but the human is not a subject in the sense of modern western philosophy, which corresponds to the object, for example the cogito of Descartes. The man of Lao Tsu possesses the same ontological status with the Earth, heaven and the Tao. |
10 | However, in the original sense, the “Tao” is not a religious concept, but a philosophical concept. |
11 | The comparison between western philosophy and oriental philosophy is a difficult work, because it is easy to misunderstand these two traditions when we try to interpret one by the other. However, it is necessary to make a comparison for discovering new possibilities in thought. |
12 | In «La répétition de la “philosophie du christianisme”», Tadayoshi Furuso indicates: «c’est pour cette raison—strictement philosophique—que Henry se trouve conduit à poser la Vie absolue qui rend possible l’auto-affection de la vie humaine, laquelle s’avère passive en tant qu’auto-affectée dans l’auto-affection absolue de la Vie, et ne peut s’éprouver soi-même réellement que dans la Vie qui donne la vie à chaque homme. En revanche, la Vie absolue peut elle-même être source de son auto-affection. […] Selon Henry, c’est le Verbe de la Vie qui permet à tout Soi vivant, y compris le mien, de venir en soi et de vivre.» (Furuso 2015, p. 88) I agree with Tadayoshi Furuso’s idea of the distinction between the absolute life of God, which permits everything to live, and the life of humans. In the main text, when comparing the thought of Henry and the thought of Lao Tsu, we should not forget this radical distinction between God and man in Henry and in Christianity, or we will misunderstand Henry’s phenomenology of life as traditional panthesim. |
13 | Wang Yangming (1472–1529) was a Chinese statesman, general, and Neo–Confucian philosopher. He was one of the leading critics of the orthodox Neo–Confucianism of Zhu Xi (1130–1200). Wang is perhaps best known for his doctrine of the “unity of knowing and acting,” which can be interpreted as a denial of the possibility of weakness of will. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/wang-yangming/, accessed on 9 October 2022. |
14 | In “Unveiling the Pathos of Life: The Phenomenology of Michel Henry and the Theology of John the Evangelist”, John Behr indicates the importance of a new concept of temporality of Henry(the essence of Life’s own temporality): there is neither before nor after in the “pathos-filled temporality, but an ‘eternal flux in which life continuously experiences itself in the Self that life eternally generates’” (see Behr 2018, pp. 104–26). John Behr’s discussion about this new temporality inspires me a lot to consider the difference between God and man: God Himself is the eternal without an end in the time of world, which means the Life of God is the eternal itself, but the life of man has an end in the world. Perhaps this is why there is a distinction between the affection of God and the affection of man: as an I, I affect myself, I am the affecting and the affected. However, I do not bring myself into this condition of experiencing myself. I am myself but I am not in this “being-myself”, I experience myself without being the source of this experience. The auto-affection is not my fact. Moreover, I do not affect myself in an absolute way, in other words, I find myself to be affected. |
15 | By developing a phenomenology of life, Henry presents the phenomenological structure of this ethical existence of man in Christianity and the relationship between man and God. However, Wang Yangming does not have to deal with the problem of creation and the problem of the relationship of man to God. The innate moral principles in Wang Yangming is the principle of value but not the principle of fact. However, in Christianity, the truth of God is not only the truth of value but also the truth of fact. This is the radical difference between Wang Yangming and Henry. |
References
- Behr, John. 2018. Unveiling the Pathos of Life: The Phenomenology of Michel Henry and the Theology of John the Evangelist. Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy 26: 104–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chang, Carsun. 1955. Wang Yang-ming’s Philosophy. Philosophy East and West 5: 3–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cui, Weifeng. 2019. D’une phénoménologie du visible à une ontologie phénoménologique de l’invisible. Louvain-la-Neuve: Presses Universitaires de Louvain. [Google Scholar]
- Falque, Emmanuel. 2001. Michel Henry Théologien (À Propos De C’est Moi La Vérité). Laval Théologique et Philosophique 57: 525–36. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Furuso, Tadayoshi. 2015. La répétition de la “philosophie du christianisme”. In Revue internationale Michel Henry n°6—2015: La phénoménologie française au Japon. Louvain-la-Neuve: Presse universitaire de Louvain. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hao, Changchi. 2022. Is Michel Henry’s Radical Phenomenology of Life a Christian Philosophy? Religions 13: 761. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Henry, Michel. 1973. The Essence of Manifestation. Translated by Girard Etzkorn. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 1975. Philosophy and Phenomenology of the Body. Translated by Girard Etzkorn. The Hague: Nijhoff. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 1990. Phénoménologie Matérielle. Paris: Presse Universitaire de France. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 1997. Le commencement cartésien et l’idée de la phénoménologie. In Lire Descartes aujourd’hui: Actes. Louvain-la-Neuve: Peeters. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 2003. I Am the Truth: Toward a Philosophy of Christianity. Translated by Susan Emanuel. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 2004a. Le bonheur de Spinoza. Paris: Presse Universitaire de France. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 2004b. The Essence of Manifestation. Translated by Girard Etzkorn. The Hague: Nijhoff. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 2012. Words of Christ. Translated by Christina M. Gschwandtner. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Michel. 2015. Incarnation: A Philosophy of Flesh. Translated by Karl Hefty. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, Edmund. 1970. Logical Investigations. Translated by John Niemeyer Findlay. London: Routledge and K. Paul. New York: Humanities Press. [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, Edmund. 1983. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy, First Book, General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology. Translated by F. Kersten. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Janicaud, Dominique. 1991. Le Tournant Théologique de la Phénoménologie Française. Combas: Éditions de l’Éclat. [Google Scholar]
- Laoureux, Sébastien. 2005. L’immanence à la Limite: Recherches sur la Phénoménologie de Michel Henry. Paris: Central Emergency Response Fund. [Google Scholar]
- Li, Er. 1972. The Tao Te Ching. Translated by Gia Fu Feng, and Jane English. New York: Vintage Books, a Division of Random House. [Google Scholar]
- Mitchell, Andrew. 2015. The Fourfold: Reading the Late Heidegger. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Tu, Wei-ming. 1976. Neo-Confucian Thought in Action: Wang Yang-ming’s Youth (1472–1509). Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Yangming. 1572. Wang Wencheng Gong Quanshu. Edited by Tingjie Xie. In the Sibu congkan. Available online: https://curiosity.lib.harvard.edu/chinese-rare-books/catalog/49-990072262460203941 (accessed on 9 October 2022).
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Cui, W. Unity of the Existence of God and the Knowledge of God in the Phenomenological Ontology of Henry. Religions 2022, 13, 964. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13100964
Cui W. Unity of the Existence of God and the Knowledge of God in the Phenomenological Ontology of Henry. Religions. 2022; 13(10):964. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13100964
Chicago/Turabian StyleCui, Weifeng. 2022. "Unity of the Existence of God and the Knowledge of God in the Phenomenological Ontology of Henry" Religions 13, no. 10: 964. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13100964
APA StyleCui, W. (2022). Unity of the Existence of God and the Knowledge of God in the Phenomenological Ontology of Henry. Religions, 13(10), 964. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13100964