Recognition and Responsibility
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Discourse on Recognition
2.1. Dimensions of Recognition
There is at some primary level a recognition that one’s own life is bound up with this other life, and though this dependency changes form, I would suggest that this is the psychoanalytic basis for a theory of the social bond.3
2.2. Recognition Ethics
3. Responsivity and Responsibility
3.1. Phenomenology of Responsivity
What provokes us, comes from a temporal and spatial distance towards us. It is always too early if measured in view of our self-initiative. On the other hand, our response is always too late measured in view of what occurs to us. It is not that something precedes us, for instance as causal stimulus with an effect that it brings about. We precede ourselves. […] I am younger and older than myself. We are dealing with an originary beforehandness and and a likewise originary belatednes. The consequence is that our speaking and acting is never entirely up to date. A response that begins elsewhere is separated from that to which it responds by a hiatus. For this time gap I choose the ancient expression diastasis.15
3.2. The Demands of Responsibility
3.3. Responsibility and Recognition in Paul Ricœur’s Ethics
4. Recognition and Responsibility
4.1. Critical Ethics of Recognition and Responsibility
4.2. Recognition and Responsibility as a Hermeneutical Lens: Narrative Biblical Ethics
4.3. Indigenous Ecology and the Ethics of Recognition and Responsibility
The earth gives away for free the power of wind and sun and water, but instead, we break open the earth to take fossil fuels. Had we taken only that which is given to us, had we reciprocated the gift, we would not have to fear our own atmosphere today. We are all bound by a covenant of reciprocity: plant breath for animal breath, winter and summer, predator and prey, grass and fire, night and day, living and dying. Water knows this, clouds know this. Soil and rocks know they are dancing in a continuous giveaway of making, unmaking, and making again the earth. Our elders say that ceremony is the way we can remember to remember […].
The moral covenant of reciprocity calls us to honor our responsibilities for all we have been given, for all that we have taken.
5. Conclusions
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
1 | For the link between morality and discourse theory see (Habermas [1983] 1990). |
2 | For the contextualization and argumentation see (Haker 2020a). |
3 | See (Butler 2020, kindle edition position 1138). Butler’s work on recognition and responsibility, deeply influenced by the Frankfurt School and developed in conversation with it. Whereas Honneth works with Winnicott and Jessica Benjamin’s psychoanalyis, Butler is more influenced by French psychoanalysis, Lacan in particular. Her approach to recognition theory can be seen as the counterpart to Taylor’s politics of recognition. My own work takes her interest in both recognition and responsibility serious, but in this essay, I develop them into a singluar ethical approach, the ethics of recognition and responsibility. For my analysis of Butler’s concept of the moral self see (Haker 2005). |
4 | I borrow the terms from psychoanalist’s Jessica Benjamin’s book on parent-child and more specifically, mother-child relationships (Benjamin 1988). See also the instructive study on personal relationships (Benjamin 2013). |
5 | For a a reconstruction of the history of the idea of recognition in France, Britain, and Germany, see Axel Honneth’s study, first published in German in 2018. This book is also a response to the different versions of recognition that have emerged over the last decades. Honneth’s systematic account differs, however, in important points from mine, especially concerning the ethical dimension of the concept to which I turn below (Honneth 2020). |
6 | For the problems with the linguistic differences of the term see (Ricœur 2005). Because the term recognition is commonly used as translation of Anerkennung, however, I will stick to it, too. |
7 | See for a thorough study on the effects of misrecognition (Bernstein 2015). |
8 | For my purpose in this paper, I will not debate whether Hegel (deliberately) misinterpreted Kant; however, it is clear that he was influenced by Schiller’s critique of Kant’s ethics, raised from an aesthetic perspective that points to the relevance of moral emotions (Schiller 1971, 2016; Herdt 2020). |
9 | Patchen Markell is especially influenced by Arendt but overlooks the much more complex conceptualization, especially when one goes beyond Honneth or Taylor (Markell 2003). Especially harsh is (McNay 2008). Rarely did the critics mention the particular context within the Frankfurt School’s own debates, or engaged in thorough readings of Hegel’s theory of recognition. See, however (Pippin 2000; Williams 2012, 1997). |
10 | I borrow the term “doer and done to” from Jessica Benjamin (Benjamin 2017). |
11 | Critical theory countered Hegel’s optimism with the warning of the “dialectic of englightenment”, i.e., the violence underneath the surface of the seemingly peaceful “civilization” (Adorno and Horkheimer [1944] 2016; Adorno [1966] 1983). |
12 | “Widerfahrnis or af-fect, marked by a hyphen in order to suggest that something is done to us.” “I have suggested using the term patient in its literal sense in order to underline this passive pre-status of the so-called subject. The corresponding status would be that of a respondent who re-spond to what strikes him or her” (Waldenfels 2004, p. 238). For a short introduction into Waldenfels’ work see (Waldenfels 2011). |
13 | |
14 | Waldenfels’ analyses match with Judith Butler’s reflections on phenomenology and subjectivity in (Butler 2015). |
15 | “Was uns anspricht, dringt aus einer zeiträumlichen Ferne zu uns. Es kommt immer schon zu früh, gemessen an unserer Eigeninitiative. Umgekehrt kommt unsere Antwort zu spät, gemessen an dem, was uns widerfährt. Es ist nicht so, dass etwas uns vorausgeht, etwa als kausaler Stimulus, der eine Wirkung nach sich zieht. Wir gehen uns selbst voraus. […] Ich bin jünger und älter als ich selbst. Wir haben es mit einer originären Vorgängigkeit und einer ebenso originären Nachträglichkeit zu tun. Dies hat zur Folge, dass unser Reden und Tun nie völlig auf der Höhe der Zeit ist. Ein Antworten, das anderswo beginnt, ist von dem, worauf es antwortet, durch einen Hiatus getrennt. Für diese Zeitverschiebung wähle ich den alten Ausdruck Diastase.” (Waldenfels 2010, p. 77f), (my translation, emphasis in the text). |
16 | “Der Blick des Anderen ist nicht etwas in meiner Welt, sondern er ist ein Geschehen, in dem eine Welt sich mir öffnet und verschließt”. (Waldenfels 2016, p. 384) (my translation). |
17 | The “gaze” also concerns the crossing of boundaries between animals and human, among others (Derrida 2002) Aesthetic experiences depend upon the response by a reader to an address, for example by a poem (Haker 2020a, chp. 12: Responsibility for the Past). |
18 | Husserl student (Schapp 1953; Haker 1999). For the concept of responsibility by implication (Rothberg 2019). |
19 | For a thorough study of the ‘other’ see (Theunissen 1984) Today, one would want to add to this group Emmanuel Levinas. |
20 | Waldenfels is, of course, aware of the effect of othering and has dedicated several works to it, but he shies away from a normative ethical theory. See (Waldenfels 2006). For an analysis of the othering of black people in American literature (Morrison 2007, 2017). |
21 | The seminal study in feminist theology by (Plaskow 1980) An important existentialist argument was provided by Simone de Beauvoir (De Beauvoir 1962). For the postcolonial context see (Fanon [1952] 1967). |
22 | Philip Roth has told the drama of identity in many of his novels. One striking example is The Human Stain, in which the protagonist conceals for decades the secret of his ethnicity in order to pursue a career that he would have otherwise been denied (Roth 2000). |
23 | Adorno creates an interesting link between theology and critical theory, using the notion of the Bilderverbot or image ban: “The materialist longing to grasp the thing aims at the opposite [of idealism]: it is only in the absence of images that the full object could be conceived. Such absence concurs with the theological ban on images. Materialism brought that ban into secular form by not permitting Utopia to be positively pictured; this is the substance of its negativity. At its most materialistic, materialism comes to agree with theology. Its great desire would be the resurrection of the flesh, a desire utterly foreign to idealism, the realm of the absolute spirit” (Adorno [1966] 1983, p. 207). For a discussion of the image ban in Adorno’s work (Pritchard 2002). |
24 | See for a (in my view misleading) identification of recognition and responsibility in Levinas’ works (Sohn 2014). For the linguistic distinctions of the French terms (Ricœur 2005, Part 1). |
25 | For a more thorough analysis see (Haker 2005). |
26 | See (Levinas 1990) There is a long discussion surrounding the Law and Violence that wrestles with an essay by Walter Benjamin (Benjamin 1996). Inspired by Levinas, Jacques Derrida took this discussion further and used it as a critique of justice in the name of responsibility (Derrida 1992, 1999). |
27 | In Oneself as Another, Ricœur still follows John Rawls but he returns to the question of justice in later works that take another turn inspired by the political philosophy of Hannah Arendt, which is not the subject of my essay. (Haker 2020a, chp. 1, No Place Nowhere. Refugees and the Problem of Human Dignity and Rights in Arendt and Ricœur). |
28 | The justification of lying to persecutors in order to save the life of a friend is a textbook example for such a dilemma, invoked already by Kant who unconvincingly argues that even in this extreme situation, truthfulness must trump the impulse to lie. Ricœur discusses the difficult case of abortion as a tragic dilemma. Sociological and ethnograpical studies support this claim: abortions often result in a sense of tragic guilt even when women continue to believe they made the right decision. This also supports the claim that no matter what position one takes, abortion must be discussed as a moral problem (Boltanski 2007; Haker 2011). |
29 | Ricœur (1992, p. 218). Critical theory insists that “evil” may easily be detached from the concreteness of violence and atrocities. It therefore the names, narrates, and analyzes historical experiences in empirical studies. |
30 | Ricœur (2005, Part 2). It deals with the “capable human” who can be held accountable for their actions and thereby connects recognition and responsibility. |
31 | Her argumentation has drawn some critique, in my view in a misreading of her understanding of mutuality. See among others (Orange 2010). |
32 | A good study on the scope of responsibility from an analytical perspective is (Mason 2019). |
33 | See for a critical assessment of the politics of responsibility (Lavin 2008). |
34 | The man-made crisis of days of power outage in Texas in early spring of 2021 after a few days of unusual winter storms is just one example of how the failure of responsibility results in moral harm (Ball 2021). |
35 | The multiple facets of poverty in the United States are, for instance analyzed in (Haymes et al. 2014). |
36 | See (Young 2011). |
37 | I elaborate on the concept of vulnerable agency in (Haker 2020a, chp. 5, Vulnerable Agency. Human Dignity and Gendered Violence). |
38 | Perhaps the names Cain and Abel already point to what is at stake in the story, namely the envy between the two brothers. Karolien Vermeulen interprets the name of Cain, the “acquired,” as associated with being the property of someone else but she remarks that some associate it with jealosy. Abel’s name stands for breath, vapor, and transience. In any case, the story entails the perspective of only one of the brothers who clearly struggles to be recognized by God while Abel, evoking transience and breath in his name, has no voice in the story. The story itself thus creates an interpretative gap, a narrative ambiguity that provokes the reader to fill in what is missing. The readers thereby continue the conversation that the story begins but certainly does not complete (Vermeulen 2014). |
39 | For the context, interpretation and relevance of the Sermon of the Mount see (Hagner 1997). |
40 | See for a current systematic overview with multiple references (McGregor et al. 2020). |
References
- Adorno, Theodor Wiesengrund. 1983. Negative Dialectics. New York: Continuum. First published 1966. [Google Scholar]
- Adorno, Theodor, and Max Horkheimer. 2016. Dialectic of Enlightenment. London: Verso Books. First published 1944. [Google Scholar]
- Balaton-Chrimes, Samantha, and Victoria Stead. 2017. Recognition, Power and Coloniality. Postcolonial Studies 20: 1–17. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ball, Jeffrey. 2021. The Texas Blackout Is a Story of a Disaster Foretold. Texas Monthly, February 19. [Google Scholar]
- Bedorf, Thomas. 2010. Verkennende Anerkennung. Berlin: Suhrkamp. [Google Scholar]
- Benjamin, Walter. 2003. On the Concept of History. In Walter Benjamin: Selected Writings, Vol. IV, 1938–1940. Edited by Howard Eiland and Michael W. Jennings. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, pp. 389–400. First published 1940. [Google Scholar]
- Benjamin, Jessica. 1988. The Bonds of Love: Psychoanalysis, Feminism, and the Problem of Domination. New York: Pantheon Books. [Google Scholar]
- Benjamin, Walter. 1996. Critique of Violence. In Walter Benjamin: Selected Writings, Vol. I, 1913–1926. Edited by Marcus Bullock and Michael W. Jennings. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, pp. 236–52. [Google Scholar]
- Benjamin, Jessica. 2013. The Bonds of Love: Looking Backward. Studies in Gender and Sexuality 14: 1–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Benjamin, Jessica. 2017. Beyond Doer and Done To: Recognition Theory, Intersubjectivity and the Third. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Bernstein, Jay. 2015. Torture and Dignity: An Essay on Moral Injury. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Boltanski, Luc. 2007. Soziologie der Abtreibung (La Condition Foetale: Une Sociologie De L’avortement Et De L’engendrement, Paris 2004). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. [Google Scholar]
- Butler, Judith. 2005. Giving an Account of Oneself. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Butler, Judith. 2015. Senses of the Subject. New York: Fordham. [Google Scholar]
- Butler, Judith. 2020. The Force of Nonviolence: An Ethico-Political Bind, Kindle edition. London: Verso. [Google Scholar]
- Coulthard, Glen Sean. 2014. Red Skin, White Masks: Rejecting the Colonial Politics of Recognition. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. [Google Scholar]
- Crenshaw, Kimberlé W. 2017. On Intersectionality: Essential Writings. New York: The New Press. [Google Scholar]
- De Beauvoir, Simone. 1962. The Ethics of Ambiguity. New York: Citadel Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1992. Force of Law. The “Mystical Foundations of Authority”. In Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice. Edited by Drucilla Cornell, Michael Rosenfeld and David Gray Carlson. New York: Routledge, pp. 3–67. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1999. Adieu to Emmanuel Levinas. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 2002. The Animal That Therefore I Am (More to Follow). Critical Inquiry 28: 369–418. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Fanon, Frantz. 1967. Black Skin. White Masks. New York: Grove Press. First published 1952. [Google Scholar]
- Fraser, Nancy, and Axel Honneth. 2003. Redistribution or Recognition? A Political-Philosophical Exchange. London and New York: Verso. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 1990. Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Cambridge: MIT Press. First published 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 1984. The Theory of Communicative Action. London: Heinemann. [Google Scholar]
- Hagner, Donald Alfred. 1997. Ethics and the Sermon on the Mount. Studia theologica 51: 44–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Haker, Hille. 1999. Moralische Identität. Literarische Lebensgeschichten Als Medium Ethischer Reflexion. Mit Einer Interpretation Der “Jahrestage” Von Uwe Johnson. Tübingen: Francke. [Google Scholar]
- Haker, Hille. 2005. The Fragility of the Moral Self. Harvard Theological Review 97: 359–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Haker, Hille. 2011. Hauptsache Gesund? Ethische Fragen der Pränatal und Präimplantationsdiagnostik. München: Kösel. [Google Scholar]
- Haker, Hille. 2020a. Towards a Critical Political Ethics. Catholic Ethics and Social Challenges. Studien Zur Theologischen Ethik 156. Basel: Schwabe Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Haker, Hille. 2020b. Towards a Decolonial Narrative Ethics. In Ethics and Literary Practice. Edited by Adam Zachary Newton. Basel: MDPI, pp. 72–102. [Google Scholar]
- Haymes, Stephen, Maria Vidal De Haymes, and Miller Reuben. 2014. The Routledge Handbook of Poverty in the United States. Abingdon: Taylor & Francis. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 2011. Natural Law. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. First published 1833. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 2018. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Phenomenology of Spirit. Translated by Terry Pinkard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Herdt, Jennifer. 2020. Forming Humanity: Redeeming the German Bildung Tradition. Chicago Scholarship Online. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Holderegger, Adrian, and Jean-Pierre Wils. 2001. Interdisziplinäre Ethik: Grundlagen, Methoden, Bereiche: Festgabe für Dietmar Mieth zum sechzigsten Geburtstag. Fribourg: Schwabe Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Honneth, Axel. 1995. The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts. Cambridge and Oxford: Polity Press, Cambridge: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Honneth, Axel. 2014. Freedom’s Right. The Social Foundations of Democratic Life. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Honneth, Axel. 2020. Recognition. A Chapter in the History of European Ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Horkheimer, Max. 1972. Traditional and Critical Theory. In Critical Theory: Selected Essays. Edited by Max Horkheimer. New York: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
- Jaeggi, Rahel. 2014. Alienation. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kimmerer, Robin Wall. 2013. Braiding Sweetgrass: Indigenous Wisdom, Scientific Knowledge and the Teachings of Plants, 1st ed. Minneapolis: Milkweed Editions. [Google Scholar]
- LaCocque, Andre. 2015. Onslaught against Innocence: Cain, Abel and the Yahwist. Cambridge: James Clarke & Co. [Google Scholar]
- Lavin, Chad. 2008. The Politics of Responsibility. Urbana: University of Illinois Press. [Google Scholar]
- Levinas, Emmanuel. 1990. Difficult Freedom: Essays on Judaism. London: Athlone Press. [Google Scholar]
- Levinas, Emmanuel. 1998. Otherwise Than Being, or, Beyond Essence. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Markell, Patchen. 2003. Bound by Recognition. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mason, Elinor. 2019. Ways to Be Blameworthy: Rightness, Wrongness, and Responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- McGregor, Deborah, Steven Whitaker, and Sritharan Mahisha. 2020. Indigenous Environmental Justice and Sustainability. Current Opinion in Environmental Sustainability 43: 35–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McNay, Lois. 2008. Against Recognition. Cambridge: Polity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Metz, Johann Baptist. 2007. Faith in History and Society (Glaube in Geschichte und Gesellschaft, 1977). New York: Crossroad. [Google Scholar]
- Morrison, Toni. 2007. Playing in the Dark. New York: Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group. [Google Scholar]
- Morrison, Toni. 2017. The Origin of Others. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mosès, Stephane. 2009. The Angel of History: Rosenzweig, Benjamin, Scholem. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Orange, Donna M. 2010. Recognition as Intersubjective Vulnerability in the Psychoanalytic Dialogue. International Journal of Psychoanalytic Self Psychology 5: 227–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pippin, Robert B. 2000. What Is the Question for Which Hegel’s Theory of Recognition Is the Answer? European Journal of Philosophy 8: 155–72. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Plaskow, Judith. 1980. Sex, Sin, and Grace: Women’s Experience and the Theologies of Reinhold Niebuhr and Paul Tillich. Lanham: University Press of America. [Google Scholar]
- Pope Francis. 2015. Encyclical Letter “Laudato Si” on the Care for Our Common Home. Vatican: Vatican Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pritchard, Elizabeth A. 2002. Bilderverbot Meets Body in Theodor W. Adorno’s Inverse Theology. The Harvard Theological Review 95: 291–318. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ricœur, Paul. 1992. Oneself as Another. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ricœur, Paul. 2005. The Course of Recognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Roth, Philip. 2000. The Human Stain: A Novel. Boston and New York: HMH Books. [Google Scholar]
- Rothberg, Michael. 2019. The Implicated Subject: Beyond Victims and Perpetrators. Cultural Memory in the Present. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schapp, Wilhelm. 1953. In Geschichten verstrickt. Vom Sein von Mensch und Ding. Hamburg: Meiner. [Google Scholar]
- Schiller, Friedrich. 1971. Kallias, Oder über die Schönheit. Über Anmut und Würde. Stuttgart: Reclam. [Google Scholar]
- Schiller, Friedrich. 2016. On the Aesthetic Education of Man. London: Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- Sohn, Michael. 2014. The Good of Recognition: Phenomenology, Ethics, and Religion in the Thought of Levinas and Ricœur. Waco: Baylor University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, Charles. 1992. Multiculturalism and the Politics of Recognition: An Essay. Edited by Amy Gutmann. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Theunissen, Michael. 1984. The Other. Studies in the Social Ontology of Husserl, Heidegger, Sartre, and Buber (Orig.: Der Andere: Studien zur Sozialontologie der Gegenwart, 1977). Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Vermeulen, Karolien. 2014. Mind the Gap: Ambiguity in the Story of Cain and Abel. Journal of Biblical Literature 133: 29–42. [Google Scholar]
- Waldenfels, Bernhard. 2004. Bodily Experience between Selfhood and Otherness. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 3: 235–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Waldenfels, Bernhard. 2006. Schattenrisse der Moral. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. [Google Scholar]
- Waldenfels, Bernhard. 2010. Responsive Ethik zwischen Antwort und Verantwortung. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 58: 71–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Waldenfels, Bernhard. 2011. Phenomenology of the Alien: Basic Concepts. Studies in Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Waldenfels, Bernhard. 2016. Das Leibliche Selbst. Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des Leibes. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. [Google Scholar]
- Warren, Magnusson, and Shaw Karena. 2002. Political Space: Reading the Global through Clayoquot Sound. Globalization and Community. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. [Google Scholar]
- Whyte, Kyle. 2018. Critical Investigations of Resilience: A Brief Introduction to Indigenous Environmental Studies and Sciences. Daedalus 147: 136–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Williams, Robert R. 1997. Hegel’s Ethics of Recognition. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Williams, Robert R. 2012. Tragedy, Recognition, and the Death of God: Studies in Hegel and Nietzsche. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Young, Iris Marion. 2011. Responsibility for Justice. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Haker, H. Recognition and Responsibility. Religions 2021, 12, 467. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12070467
Haker H. Recognition and Responsibility. Religions. 2021; 12(7):467. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12070467
Chicago/Turabian StyleHaker, Hille. 2021. "Recognition and Responsibility" Religions 12, no. 7: 467. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12070467
APA StyleHaker, H. (2021). Recognition and Responsibility. Religions, 12(7), 467. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12070467