Catholicism and the Natural Law: A Response to Four Misunderstandings
Abstract
:1. The Natural Law
- Parents may abandon their minor children without any justification and without any requirement to provide financial support.
- It is permissible for a city or state to pass post facto laws.
- The maximum punishment for first-degree murder is an all-expense paid vacation to Las Vegas.
- Any city or state may pass secret laws that the public cannot know.
- Anyone may be convicted of a crime based on the results of a coin toss.
- All citizens are forbidden from believing, propagating, or publicly defending the view that there is a moral law against which nations and individuals are measured.
- Your guilt or innocence in a criminal trial depends entirely on your race and not on a judge or jury’s deliberation on legitimately obtained evidence.
- Government contracts are to be distributed based on family connections and bribes and not on the quality of the bids.
- Original parenthood is to be decided by a special board of experts appointed by the governor and not on whether one sires or begets the child.
- No citizen may believe, propagate, or publicly defend the view that there is a transcendent source of being that has underived existence.
2. Four Misunderstandings
2.1. The Natural Law Commits the So-Called “Naturalistic Fallacy”
As a scientist, I am hostile to fundamentalist religion because it actively debauches the scientific enterprise. It teaches us not to change our minds, and not to want to know exciting things that are available to be known. It subverts science and saps the intellect. The saddest example I know is that of the American geologist Kurt Wise…The wound, to his career and his life’s happiness, was self-inflicted, so unnecessary, so easy to escape. All he had to do was toss out the bible. Or interpret it symbolically, or allegorically, as the theologians do. Instead, he did the fundamentalist thing and tossed out science, evidence and reason, along with all his dreams and hopes.
2.2. Natural Law Makes Scripture Superfluous, Mistakenly Affirms Universal Moral Beliefs, and Ignores the Noetic Effects of Sin
The three contentions of the Thomist doctrine of natural law that evoke evangelical criticism are: (1) that independently of divine revelation, (2) there exists a universally shared body or system of moral beliefs, (3) that human reasoning articulates despite the noetic consequences of the Adamic fall.
3. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | This list is inspired by Lon Fuller’s fictional story of an evil monarch named Rex (Fuller 1969, pp. 33–41). |
2 | An exception would be cases in which the parents of minor children die without having provided in their will directions for their children’s guardianship. But even here state laws reflect the primacy of original parenthood by allowing guardianship to the closest relatives (e.g., grandparents, aunt, uncle) with the best interests of the child in mind (e.g., an abusive alcoholic grandparent may be bypassed for a close family friend or aunt). |
3 | “Now, there are some objects of speculation that depend on matter for their being, for they can only exist in matter. And these are subdivided. Some depend on matter both for their being and for their being understood, as do those things whose definition contains sensible matter and which, as a consequence, cannot be understood without sensible matter. For example, it is necessary to include flesh and bones in the definition of man. It is things of these sort that physics or natural science studies. On the other hand, there are some things that, although dependent upon matter for their being, do not depend on it for their being understood, because sensible matter is not included in their definitions. This is the case with lines and numbers—the kinds of objects with which mathematics deals. There are still other objects of speculative knowledge that do not depend upon matter for their being because they can exist without matter; either they never exist in matter, as in the case of God and the angels, or they exist in matter in some instances and not in others, as in the case of substance, quality, potency, act, one and many, and the like. The science that treats of all these is theology or divine science, which is so called because its principal object is God. By another name it is called metaphysics; that is to say, beyond physics, because it ought to be learned by us after physics, for we have to proceed from sensible things to those that are non-sensible. It is also called first philosophy, inasmuch as all the other sciences, receiving their principles from it, come after it…” (Thomas Aquinas 1953, Q5.a1) (In order to make this quote more accessible, I slighted edited it from how it appears in the original). |
4 | C. S. Lewis put it more eloquently: “These, then, are the two points I wanted to make. First, that human beings, all over the earth, have the curious idea that they ought to behave in a certain way, and cannot really get rid of it. Secondly, that they do not in fact behave in that way.” (Lewis [1952] 1997, p. 21). |
5 | Just as some human beings cannot learn mathematics or master a language because of immaturity or disability, some human beings never come to know the natural law for the same reasons. This is why it is wrong to say that Aquinas or the Catholic Church teaches that the natural law is innate in each and every human being. |
6 | This is a point made by J. Budziszewski, “[P]reservation of its being means not the preservation of its bare existence, but the preservation of the mode of life that the fulfillment of its nature requires–a mode of life that is shaped by all of its natural inclinations, not just the first inclination, but others too.” (Budziszewski 2014, p. 249). |
7 | A supererogatory act is one that is above and beyond the call of duty, as in the case of a soldier jumping on a live grenade to save his buddies. He does not will his own death, but he knowingly sacrifices his own life to save others. (We know he is not willing his own death because he would not be disappointed if the grenade turned out to be a dud). Perhaps this is the sort of sacrifice Jesus had in mind when he said, “No one has greater love than this, to lay down one’s life for one’s friends.” (Jn 15:13–NRSV). |
8 | It is important to note here that Aquinas and the Church are not suggesting that moral relativists and atheists do not exist. What they are saying is that human beings have a natural inclination to pursue ultimate truths about morality and God. After all, the moral relativist’s rejection of the natural law and the atheist’s rejection of God’s existence means that each has an inclination to pursue the truth of these questions, even though each arrives at answers antithetical to conclusions drawn by Aquinas and the Church. Nevertheless, the Church maintains that we are ordered toward these ends because they really do exist, and that in the case of God we cannot know him in the fullest sense until we experience him in the beatific vision in the afterlife. |
9 | |
10 | The Catechism (2000) affirms teleology as integral to its explication of the natural law: “The moral law presupposes the rational order, established among creatures for their good and to serve their final end, by the power, wisdom, and goodness of the Creator. All law finds its first and ultimate truth in the eternal law.” (1951) (emphasis added). |
11 | It should go without saying that Wise’s literalistic interpretation of the Bible—in particular, the first chapters of Genesis—is not the only way to interpret Scripture while maintaining a high view of it. See, e.g., (Carroll 2002). |
12 | As I note elsewhere: “Although Aquinas believed that God, the Sovereign Good, ‘is the object and cause of Happiness,’ one need not believe in God to recognize, as Dawkins does, that human beings by nature are ordered toward happiness. Aquinas, of course, maintained that nothing short of God could suffice for Perfect Happiness, since everything that gives us imperfect happiness—pleasure, bodily goods, wealth, honor, intellectual accomplishments—is fleeting and temporary. Nevertheless, the point here is that Dawkins, despite his best efforts, cannot rid himself of the common sense reflexes that require the reality of final causality.” (Beckwith 2019, p. 82, quoting Thomas Aquinas 1920, I.II, Q5, art. 5, respondeo) |
13 | This dialogue is inspired by a similar one authored by Budziszewski (2014, p. 248). |
14 | Hume writes: “In every system of morality, which I have hitherto met with, I have always remarked, that the author proceeds for some time in the ordinary ways of reasoning, and establishes the being of a God, or makes observations concerning human affairs; when all of a sudden I am surprised to find, that instead of the usual copulations of propositions, is, and is not, I meet with no proposition that is not connected with an ought, or an ought not. This change is imperceptible; but is however, of the last consequence. For as this ought, or ought not, expresses some new relation or affirmation, ’tis necessary that it should be observed and explained; and at the same time that a reason should be given; for what seems altogether inconceivable, how this new relation can be a deduction from others, which are entirely different from it. But as authors do not commonly use this precaution, I shall presume to recommend it to the readers; and am persuaded, that this small attention would subvert all the vulgar systems of morality, and let us see, that the distinction of vice and virtue is not founded merely on the relations of objects, nor is perceived by reason.” (Hume [1739] 2000, p. 302). |
15 | English translation of Humani Generis quote is unique to Catechsim. The Vatican’s official translation of the encyclical differs slightly. It can be found online here: http://www.vatican.va/content/pius-xii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_p-xii_enc_12081950_humani-generis.html (accessed on 21 May 2021) |
16 | I say “legitimate human law” because Aquinas holds that some so-called human laws are unjust and thus not real laws. See (Thomas Aquinas 1920, II.I, Q96, art. 4, respondeo). |
17 | |
18 | I am aware that there is a spectrum of views on abortion, that there are not just two camps, as popular media often portray it. But for the point I am trying to make here, it is not necessary that I cover all those views. |
References
- Ashton, John F. 2000. In Six Days: Why 50 Scientists Choose to Believe in Creation. Green Forrest: Master Books. [Google Scholar]
- Beckwith, Francis J. 2007. Defending Life: A Moral and Legal Case against Abortion Choice. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Beckwith, Francis J. 2019. Never Doubt Thomas: The Catholic Aquinas as Evangelical and Protestant. Waco: Baylor University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Boonin, David. 2002. A Defense of Abortion. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Boonin, David. 2019. Beyond Roe: Why Abortion Should Be Legal—Even if the Fetus is a Person. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Budziszewski, J. 2011. What We Can’t Not Know: A Guide, Revised and Expanded Edition. San Francisco: Ignatius Press. [Google Scholar]
- Budziszewski, J. 2014. Commentary on Thomas Aquinas’ Treatise on Law. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Carroll, William E. 2002. Creation, Evolution, and Thomas Aquinas. Revue des Questions Scientifiques 171: 319–47. [Google Scholar]
- Crowe, Jonathan. 2017. Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Law Theories. In The Cambridge Companion to Natural Law Jurisprudence. Edited by George Duke and Robert P. George. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 103–29. [Google Scholar]
- Catechism of the Catholic Church: Revised in Accordance with the Official Latin Text Promulgated by Pope John Paul II, 2nd ed. Washington: United States Conference of Catholic Bishops.
- Dawkins, Richard. 2006. The God Delusion. London: Bantam. [Google Scholar]
- Fuller, Lon L. 1969. The Morality of Law, Revised edition. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, Carl F. H. 1995. Natural Law and Nihilistic Culture. First Things 49: 55. [Google Scholar]
- Hume, David. 2000. A Treatise on Human Nature. Edited by David Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton. Oxford: Clarendon Press. First published 1739. [Google Scholar]
- King, Martin Luther, Jr. 1963. Letter from a Birmingham Jail. April 16. Available online: https://www.africa.upenn.edu/Articles_Gen/Letter_Birmingham.html (accessed on 21 May 2021).
- Lee, Patrick. 2019. The New Natural Law Theory. In The Cambridge Companion to Natural Law Ethics. Edited by Tom Angier. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 73–91. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, Clives Staples. 1997. Mere Christianity. London: Collins. First published 1952. [Google Scholar]
- Pius XII. 1950. Humani Generis. August 12. Available online: http://www.vatican.va/content/pius-xii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_p-xii_enc_12081950_humani-generis.html (accessed on 21 May 2021).
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1920. Summa Theologica. Literally translated by Fathers of the English Dominican Province. Available online: http://www.newadvent.org/summa/ (accessed on 21 May 2021).
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1953. Super Boethium De Trinitate, trans. Armand Mauer. Toronto. Available online: https://isidore.co/aquinas/english/BoethiusDeTr.htm#51 (accessed on 21 May 2021).
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1968. On Being and Essence (De Ente Et Essentia). Translated by Armand Maurer. Toronto: Pontifical Institute Medieval Studies. [Google Scholar]
- Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 1971. A Defense of Abortion. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1: 47–66. [Google Scholar]
- Warren, Mary Anne. 1973. On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion Rights. The Monist 57: 43–61. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Beckwith, F.J. Catholicism and the Natural Law: A Response to Four Misunderstandings. Religions 2021, 12, 379. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12060379
Beckwith FJ. Catholicism and the Natural Law: A Response to Four Misunderstandings. Religions. 2021; 12(6):379. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12060379
Chicago/Turabian StyleBeckwith, Francis J. 2021. "Catholicism and the Natural Law: A Response to Four Misunderstandings" Religions 12, no. 6: 379. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12060379
APA StyleBeckwith, F. J. (2021). Catholicism and the Natural Law: A Response to Four Misunderstandings. Religions, 12(6), 379. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12060379