The Metaphysics of Theism: A Classical and Neo-Classical Synthesis
Abstract
:1. Introduction
1.1. The Nature of Theism
(1) (Theism) | There is a God, identified as the perfect and ultimate source of created reality. |
(2) (Classical Theism) | God, the perfect and ultimate source of created reality, is:
|
(3) (Neo-Classical Theism) | God, the perfect and ultimate source of created reality, is: (a1) Complex: has proper parts. (b1) Temporal: has temporal succession, location and extension. (c1) Mutable: is intrinsically and extrinsically changeable. (d1) Passible: is causally affectable. |
1.2. Theism Dilemma and Creation Objection
(4) (Theism1) | God, the perfect and ultimate source of created reality, is:
|
(5) (Creation Objection) | C1. If God begins to be related to creation, then God changes. C2. God begins to be related to creation. C3. Therefore, God changes. C4. If God changes, then God is neither immutable nor timeless. C5. Therefore, God is neither immutable nor timeless. |
2. Ontological Pluralism
2.1. The Nature of Ontological Pluralism
(6) (Pluralism) |
|
If one is taking an inventory of everything that there is, the pluralist’s ‘is’ is ambiguous between ∃1 and ∃2, and the items in being must be sorted into either category. The pluralist’s inventory is finer-grained than the list that falls in the domain of the single first-order existential quantifier, since it includes everything that there either is1 or is2.
2.2. Theistic Ontological Pluralism
(7) (Theism2) | God, the perfect and ultimate source of created reality, is: (∃a) in his abstract way of being: (∃c) in his concrete way of being: (a) Simple (a1) Complex (b) Timeless (b1) Temporal (c) Immutable (c1) Mutable (d) Impassible (d1) Passible |
3. Modal Realism
3.1. Genuine Modal Realism
(8) (Realism) |
|
(9) (De Dicto) | It is possible that x ↔ there is a w such that w is a world and at w, x. |
(10) (De Re-P) | x is possibly F ↔ there is a world w and a counterpart x*, such that, in w, x* is F. |
(11) (De Re-N) | x is necessarily F ↔ for every world, w, all counterparts of x are F. |
What price paradise? If we want the theoretical benefits that talk of possibilia brings, the most straightforward way to gain honest title to them is to accept such talk as the literal truth. It is my view that the price is right, if less spectacularly so than in the mathematical parallel. The benefits are worth their ontological cost.
if we say ‘Humphrey might have won the election (if only he had done such-and-such)’, we are not talking about something that might have happened to Humphrey, but to someone else, a ‘counterpart’. Probably, however, Humphrey could not care less whether someone else, no matter how much resembling him, would have been victorious in another possible world.
According to Lewis, possible individuals are part of one and the same possible world if, and only if, they are spatiotemporally related. It follows immediately that no possible world is composed of island universes of spatiotemporally isolated parts. Given the standard analysis of possibility as truth at some possible world, island universes, then, are impossible.
3.2. Leibnizian Realism with Overlap
(12) (Realism*) |
|
(13) (De Re-P2) | x is possibly F ↔ there is a world, w, such that x exists at w and is F at w; x exists at w iff x is wholly present at a region R that is itself a part of w. |
(14) (De Re-N2) | x is necessarily F ↔ for every world, w, x itself exists at w and is F at w; x exists at w iff x is wholly present at a region R that is itself a part of w. |
3.3. Theistic Modal Realism
(15) (Theism3) | God, the perfect and ultimate source of created reality, is: (∃t) in his transcendent way of being: (∃i) in his immanent way of being: (a) Simple (a1) Complex (b) Timeless (b1) Temporal (c) Immutable (c1) Mutable (d) Impassible (d1) Passible |
4. Conclusions
Funding
Institutonal Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Though this is taken to by Schellenberg to be a catch-all definition of religion, some minor religions and practices might not be accurately captrued by it—namely, religious beliefs and practices that do not recognise an ultimate reality. Nevertheless, given the simplicity and overall generality of this deifnition, we will continue to work with it throughout. |
2 | As God has ‘attributes’ (or ‘characteristics) but these attributes (or ‘characteristics’) are not to be conceived of as ‘properties’, one can ask what the nature of these entities is? One way is it to conceive of this attributes as ‘aspects’—qualitative differing, yet numerically identical particular ways that an entity is. Construing these entities in this way enables the primary objections against the cogency of the notion of metaphysical simplicity to be put to rest—as God is taken to bear (qualitatively differing) ‘divine aspects’, rather than ‘divine properties’, which enables God’s power, knowledge, goodness, etc., to be numerically identical to him and each other—as aspects are numerically identical to their bearers and one another—whilst still maintaining a qualitative distinction between them—as aspects qualitatively differ from their bearers and one another. God thus has multiple, qualitatively differing aspects that are ‘improper parts’ of him (i.e., numerically identical to God) rather than ‘proper parts’ of him (i.e., numerically distinct from God). For reasons of space, this account will not be further detailed. However, for a further explanation of this account, see (Sijuwade 2021a). |
3 | Where to be a God is simply to have the attributes captured by (1). |
4 | This specific construal of Neo-Classical Theism is represented best by Richard Swinburne (2016). An alternative approach was provided by Charles Hartshorne (1984), who introduced the terminology ‘Neo-Classical Theism’, and took God’s properties to be entailed by God’s worshipability. Harthsorne, contra Swinburne, adamantly opposed the idea that properties rightly predicated of God are entailed by God’s possession of omnipotence. However, due to the influence and plausibility of Swinburne’s approach, we will continue to utilise his approach to further elucidate the notion of Neo-Classical Theism. |
5 | However, not every proponent of NCT will take God to be empathetic in this specific way. |
6 | Probably the most famous argument provided by Mullins against the consistency of CT is the Modal Collapse argument. For an explanation of this argument, see (Mullins 2021, pp. 94–96). For two helpful responses to this argument, see (Tomaszewski 2019) and (Schmid 2021). |
7 | Mullins also notes that the affirmation of creation ex nihilo by CT was also to help distinguish the cosmogony of CT from other cosmogonies that are found within other worldviews (such as panentheism). |
8 | An additional way that one could find their way out of the Theism Dilemma would be to question the correctness of the position that Sacred Tradition does conceive of God’s nature in the manner expressed by (1) and/or Sacred Scripture does conceive of God’s nature in the manner expressed by (2). That is, maybe Sacred Tradition does not teach that God is, in fact, simple, timeless, immutable and impassible. Additionally, maybe Sacred Scripture does not teach that God is, in fact, complex, temporal, mutable and passible. Denying that the sources of authority that are affirmed by the traditionalist teach a CT conception of God or a NCT conception of God is indeed a possible way to deal with the Theism Dilemma, but it is not a path that is advised, given that the consensus by scholars working on the issue is that of, on the one hand, the CT conception of God is the traditional teaching concerning the nature of God—with the NCT conception being a recent development in the tradition. And, second, that the NCT position expressing the central tenets of the doctrine of God found within Sacred Scripture—with the CT conception solely expressing the philosophical presuppositions of its adherents (Boyd 2000, p. 24). One would thus need a good reason to doubt the present consensus on this issue. |
9 | An additional benefit that will be noted later is that of the current proposal also being able to provide a ‘deflation’ or ‘reduction’ of these extensions as well—more on this below. |
10 | Throughout this section and the subsequent sections, I will alternate between the terms ‘ways of being’, ‘modes of being’, ‘manners of existence’ and ‘kinds of being’, etc., without any change in meaning. |
11 | The following construal of OP is a basic statement that is subject to certain counterexamples. However, as this statement captures the core tenets of the view, the more complex statement of OP featured in (Turner 2020, pp. 185–88) will not be included. Furthermore, for an argument in favour of the sufficiency of this statement, see (Spencer 2012, pp. 912–14). |
12 | The assumption of the possible existence of abstract and concrete entities will be of great importance in furthering the thesis of this article—more on this below. |
13 | Despite the distinction between the different ontological structures, this does not mean that entities within those domains cannot overlap. The possibility of this type of overlap will be important for the thesis that will be argued for below. For an explanation of this possibility, see (McDaniel 2009, pp. 313–14). |
14 | |
15 | Within the field of modal metaphysics, this thesis is termed a possibilist theory, which is one that takes there to exist merely possible entities that are strictly non-actual. The qualifier ‘Genuine’ is used here to distinguish the type of modal realism featured in the following section from the more prevalent actualist versions associated with with Plantinga (1974) and Robert Adams (1974)—each of which conceives of the nature of a possible world as an abstract object that does not ‘genuinely’ exist—with the ‘actual world’ being the only possible world that does exist within this framework. Nevertheless, in the next section I will be taking the term ‘genuine modal realism’ and the term ‘modal realism’ to be synonymous, and thus I will be alternating in the use of these terms without any change in meaning. |
16 | As there are no ‘impossible worlds’ within Lewis’ metaphysics, one can refer to a ‘possible’ world simply as a world. |
17 | More on world-boundness below. |
18 | A similar account can be provided for the modal operator ‘it is necessary that’. |
19 | However, as worlds do not overlap in the GMR framework, this principle is to be understood in terms of intrinsic duplication—a given world is composed of duplicates of the entities that are brought together from other worlds. |
20 | In the case that one is not persuaded by Lewis concerning the importance of the pragmatic virtues of a theory in establishing truth value of GMR (i.e., belief in concrete worlds), Bricker (2007, pp. 120–22) has provided two interesting non-pragmatic arguments: a ‘truthmaker argument’ (i.e., given that possibilia require truthmakers, (concrete) worlds are the only entities that can fulfil that truthmaking role) and an ‘argument from intentionality’ (i.e., given that our intentional states about possibilia must stand in relation to relata that exist in reality, (concrete) worlds are the only entities that can be these relata). Bricker believes that these two arguments provide one with good reason to favour GMR over its rivals and establish a foundation for belief in the existence of concrete worlds. |
21 | The primary way that Lewis (1986) shows that the cost of one accepting the existence of an infinite plurality of worlds is affordable is by responding to eight important objections that have been raised against his theory in the literature and then arguing that the alternative theories all themselves face important objections. For a helpful summary of these responses given by Lewis, see Bricker (2007). |
22 | One might ask why we have spent quite a bit of time unpacking the nature of Lewis’ GMR, only to abandon most of its central tenets. The primary reason for this is to allow one to understand the key differences between Lewis’ version of modal realism and the other versions that are on offer, and how the latter versions are still ‘Lewisian’ by retaining some of the central tenets, whilst being rendered as plausible and defensible theses by jettisoning the problematic ones. This jettisoning of the problematic tenets of Lewis version of modal realism is indeed important, given that Lewis’ GMR, and not the notion of GMR per se, is not widely accepted in contemporary metaphysics. |
23 | McDaniel (2006) provided a different conception of the nature of a world—where a world is a collection of tropes, rather than a collection of spacetime regions. McDaniel provided this modification because he believed that the former view faces some important objections. Nevertheless, this article will continue to work with the conception of a world as a collection of spacetime regions, due to the ease in explicating this view compared with that of the newer view—with it being noted here, however, that the central argument of this article is also applicable to McDaniel’s newer view as well. |
24 | An important question to ask is: what does it mean for an object to be wholly present at a region? McDaniel does not answer this question; however, Gilmore (2018, §2) has provided a helpful characterisation of the notion of being wholly present (or, what he terms, being ‘exactly located’) where entity x is wholly present [exactly located] at a region y if and only if x has (or has- at-y) exactly the same shape and size as y and stands (or stands-at-y) in all the same spatial or spatiotemporal relations to other entities as does y. At the heart of this conceptualisation of the notion of being wholly present (or exactly located) is the fact of objects inheriting the same properties and relations of the regions that they are wholly present at—for example, small spheres are wholly present at small spherical regions and share all of the properties and relations of these regions; large cubes are wholly present at large cubical regions and share all of the properties and relations of these regions, etc. For a further characterisation of this notion, see (Gilmore 2018). |
25 | Interestingly, Bricker (2006, p. 65) is open to there being more than one actual world but proceeds to explicate the position detailed here within a ‘one actual world’ framework. We shall follow suit. |
26 | For clarity, the impossible individual category has been suppressed in this image. |
27 | However, in proceeding forward, we will take there to exist solely two categories: possible individuals and non-individuals, given that the second category does not play a role in the theistic framework being developed. |
28 | Cameron (2009) was the first individual to identify God as a non-individual that exists from the standpoint of every world, with Almeida (2017a, 2017b) further developing Cameron’s position. The following proposal, however, is not subject to the criticisms that have been raised against this identification by Paul Sheehy (2009) and Matthew Collier (2019), as, first, the notion of Isolation is not present in this version of modal realism, and, second, God is not taken to be causally related to creation from this standpoint (or way of being)—both of which they believe leads to modal collapse. Rather, in this version of modal realism, worlds are indeed causally related, and it is in God’s other way of being: as a possible individual that exists at a world, that God is ‘causally related’ to created reality, and thus there is no possibility of modal collapse. |
29 | This is important as God is not identified in this framework as an abstract entity, but simply as an entity that has the same status of an abstract entity—namely, existing from the standpoint of a world. Collier (2021 p. 59) has helpfully shown that it is not necessary (or sufficient) for an entity to be an abstract entity (with all the features of it), simply because it exists from the standpoint of a given world, as Lewis (1986, p. 83) himself allows impure sets to exists at a world—and not from the standpoint of a world—yet, these entities are abstract rather than concrete entities. |
30 | God, in this mode of existence, would also not be composed of ‘spatial’ and ‘temporal’ parts by not being an occupant of a spatiotemporal region. |
31 | As noted previously, these entities are to be conceived of as aspects. |
32 | God, in this mode of existence, would also be composed of ‘spatial’ and ‘temporal’ parts by being an occupant of a spatiotemporal region. Hence, God, in this specific mode of being, would thus be a material object. Furthermore, God would be wholly present at a region of a particular world if and only if God has (or has-at-that region) exactly the same shape and size of that region and stands (or stands-at-that region) in all the same spatial or spatiotemporal relations to other entities as does that specific region—in short, God shares all of the properties and relations of the regions that he occupies. Both of these suggestions—that God is a material object and is wholly present in this specific way—might sound peculiar and novel, but we can understand the nature of God’s materiality and presence within a region of spacetime as corresponding to that of Hudson’s (2009) and Pruss’ (2013) ubiquitous entension account of omnipresence, which takes God to stand in location relation in a fundamental sense, which results in him being a material object—through entending the region in which he is located. For a detailed discussion of this account of omnipresence, and a historical modification of it in light of the ‘materialist’ implications of the account, see (Inman 2017). |
33 | This is not to say that all the worlds that God exists at would have other entities existing at them. All that is needed for this point to stand is that of the fact that some of these worlds have other entities as inhabitants. |
34 | The possibility of God being multiply located, rather than having counterparts in other worlds, wards off the plurality of Gods objection that has plagued most accounts of Theistic MR. Precisely why this issue has plagued these accounts, is due to the fact that the proponents of other versions of Theistic MR have focused solely on Lewis’ account of modal realism, rather than utilising different versions of modal realism that are available. For an explanation of the plurality of God objection, see (Sheehy 2006, pp. 319–20, 2009) and (Collier 2019, pp. 335–42). |
35 | It is important to note that in the framework of Theistic MR, the notions of ‘CT’ and ‘NCT’ are not correctly taken to be extensions of Theism simpliciter (as they have regularly been taken to be in the contemporary analytic theology literature). Rather, these two notions are now, within Theistic MR, ‘reduced’ to the attributes of transcendence and immanence that are had by God within this metaphysical framework. That is, God is taken to exist in a transcendent way—which allows him to be conceived of in a CT manner (i.e., as simple, timeless, immutable and impassible), and God is taken to exist in an immanent way—which allows him to be conceived of in a NCT manner (i.e., as complex, temporal, mutable and passible). Theistic MR thus provides a way for a much-needed deflation of these two extensions of Theism to be made—which will further the unity between the adherents of CT and NCT. Moreover, by focusing on the attributes of transcendence and immanence, we can now have a more precise understanding of these often-mystifying attributes—where transcendence is usually understood as ‘God being beyond the universe’ and immanence is usually understood as ‘God being within the universe’—which, together, seem to be inconsistent. However, now within the framework of Theistic MR, transcendence is simply that of ‘God existing beyond the concrete worlds’—from the standpoint of those worlds—and immanence is simply that of ‘God existing at the concrete words’—by being wholly present within the regions of those worlds. |
36 | Interestingly, the means of dealing with the Theism Dilemma that has been provided by Theistic MR is similar to the method that has been proposed by a number of Christian thinkers to deal with the incompatible attributes that are rightly predicated of Jesus Christ. That is, the notion of ‘reduplicative predication’, where the apparently incompatible attributes (e.g., being omnipotent and being limited in power)—each of which is rightly predicated of Christ—are relativised to each of Christ’s natures (i.e., Christ is omnipotent relative (qua) his divine nature and is limited in power relative (qua) his human nature). The relativisation method proposed by Theistic MR seeks to provide a similar means of dealing with the Theism Dilemma, and thus the current proposal—from a methodological perspective—is not without some formal precedent in Church history. For a helpful introduction to the method of reduplicative predication in a Christological context, see (Pawl 2016, pp. 117–18). Furthermore, one can also see a similar approach featured in the work of Charles Hartshorne (1967), where he defends the notion of ‘bi-polar’ theism based on the metaphysics of Alfred North Whitehead—hence, we thus have further precedent for the present proposal in wider religious history as well. For a further detailed unpacking of this notion of bi-polar theism, see (Hartshorne 1967, 1984). |
37 | For more on the nature of grounding within a general context, see (Schaffer 2016). Additionally, for an explication of the notion of grounding within a theistic context, see (Sijuwade 2021b). |
References
- Adams, Robert. 1974. Theories of Actuality. Nous 8: 211–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Almeida, Michael. 2017a. Theistic Modal Realism I: The Challenge of Theistic Actualism. Philosophy Compass 12: 1–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Almeida, Michael. 2017b. Theistic Modal Realism II: Theoretical Benefits. Philosophy Compass 12: 1–14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bernstein, Sara. 2021. Ontological Pluralism about Non-Being. In Non-Being: New Essays on the Metaphysics of Nonexistence. Edited by Sara Bernstein and Tyron Goldschmidt. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 1–16. [Google Scholar]
- Boyd, Gregory A. 2000. God of the Possible: A Biblical Introduction to the Open View of God. Grand Rapids: Baker Books. [Google Scholar]
- Bricker, Phillip. 2001. Island Universes and the Analysis of Modality. In Reality and Humean Supervenience: Essays on the Philosophy of David Lewis. Edited by Gerherd Preyer and Frank Siebelt. Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 27–56. [Google Scholar]
- Bricker, Phillip. 2006. Absolute Actuality and the Plurality of Worlds. Philosophical Perspectives 20: 41–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bricker, Phillip. 2007. Concrete Possible Worlds. In Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics. Edited by Theodore Sider, John Hawthorne and Dean W. Zimmerman. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 111–34. [Google Scholar]
- Builes, David. 2019. Pluralism and the problem of purity. Analysis 79: 394–402. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cameron, Ross. 2009. God exists at every (modal realist) world: Response to Sheehy. Religious Studies 45: 95–100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Caplan, Benjamin. 2011. Ontological Superpluralism. Philosophical Perspectives 25: 79–114. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Collier, Matthew J. 2019. God’s necessity on anselmian theistic genuine modal realism. Sophia 58: 331–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Collier, Matthew J. 2021. God’s place in the world. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 89: 43–65. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Craig, William L. 2001. God, Time, and Eternity. Illnois: Kluwer Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Creel, Richard E. 1997. Immutability and Impassibility. In A Companion to Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Phillip L. Quinn and Charles Taliaferro. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 322–28. [Google Scholar]
- Davies, Brian. 2004. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion: Third Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dolezal, James. 2011. God without Parts. Oregon: Pickwick Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Dolezal, James. 2017. All That Is in God: Evangelical Theology and the Challenge of Classical Christian Theism. Grand Rapids: Reformation Heritage Books. [Google Scholar]
- Gilmore, Cody. 2018. Location and Mereology. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/location-mereology/ (accessed on 6 August 2021).
- Hartshorne, Charles. 1967. A Natural Theology for Our Time. Illinois: Open Court. [Google Scholar]
- Hartshorne, Charles. 1984. Omnipotence and Other Theological Mistakes. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hudson, Hud. 2009. Omnipresence. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology. Edited by Thomas P. Flint and Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 199–216. [Google Scholar]
- Inman, Ross. D. 2017. Omnipresence and the location of the immaterial. In Oxford Studies in the Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Jonathan L. Kvanvig. Oxford: Oxford University Press, vol. VIII, pp. 168–206. [Google Scholar]
- Kripke, Saul. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, David K. 1983. Postscripts to “Counterpart Theory and Quantified Modal Logic”. Philosophical Papers. Oxford: Oxford University Press, vol. VI, pp. 40–46. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, David K. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, David K. 1999. Anselm and Actuality. In Particulars, Actuality, and Identity over Time. Edited by Michael Tooley. New York: Routledge, vol. VIV, pp. 283–97. [Google Scholar]
- McDaniel, Kris. 2004. Modal Realism with Overlap. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82: 137–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McDaniel, Kris. 2006. Modal Realisms. Philosophical Perspectives 20: 303–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McDaniel, Kris. 2009. Ways of Being. In Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Edited by Davd Chalmers, David Manley and Ryan Wasserman. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 290–319. [Google Scholar]
- McDaniel, Kris. 2010. A Return to the Analogy of Being. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 813: 688–717. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McDaniel, Kris. 2017. The Fragmentation of Being. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Merricks, Trenton. 2019. The only way to be. Noûs 53: 593–612. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mullins, Ryan. T. 2021. Classical Theism. In T&T Handbook of Analytic Theology. Edited by James M. Arcadi and James T. Turner. London: T&T Clark, pp. 85–100. [Google Scholar]
- Pawl, Timothy. 2016. In Defense of Conciliar Christology: A Philosophical Essay. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Peckham, John. 2019. The Doctrine of God: Introducing the Big Questions. London: T&T Clark. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Alvin. 1974. The Nature of Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pruss, Alexander. 2013. Omnipresence, Multilocation, the Real Presence and Time Travel. Journal of Analytic Theology 1: 60–72. [Google Scholar]
- Sanders, Fred. 2017. Classical Theism Makes a Comeback. Didaktikos 1: 47. [Google Scholar]
- Schaffer, Jonathan. 2016. Grounding in the image of causation. Philosophical Studies 173: 49–100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schellenberg, Jonathan. L. 2005. Prolegomena to a Philosophy of Religion. New York: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schmid, Joseph. C. 2021. The fruitful death of modal collapse arguments. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 1–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sheehy, Paul. 2006. Theism and modal realism. Religious Studies 42: 315–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sheehy, Paul. 2009. Reply to Cameron. Religious Studies 45: 101–4. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sider, Theodore. 2011. Writing the Book of the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sijuwade, Joshua. R. 2021a. Divine Simplicity: The Aspectival Account. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 1–37. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sijuwade, Joshua. R. 2021b. Building the monarchy of the Father. Religious Studies, 1–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Spencer, Joshua. 2012. Ways of Being. Philosophy Compass 7: 910–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stump, Eleonore. 2016. The God of the Bible and the God of the Philosophers. Wisconsin: Marquette University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Swinburne, Richard. 1994. The Christian God. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Swinburne, Richard. 2016. Coherence of Theism: Second Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Tomaszewski, Christopher. 2019. Collapsing the modal collapse argument: On an invalid argument against divine simplicity. Analysis 79: 275–84. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Turner, Jason. 2010. Ontological Pluralism. Journal of Philosophy 107: 5–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Turner, Jason. 2012. Logic and Ontological Pluralism. Journal of Philosophical Logic 41: 419–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Turner, Jason. 2020. Ontological Pluralism. In The Routledge Handbook of Metametaphysics. Edited by Ricki Bliss and James T. M. Miller. New York: Routledge, pp. 184–95. [Google Scholar]
- Zagzebski, Linda. 2013. Omnisubjectivity: A Defense of a Divine Attribute. Wisconsin: Marquette University Press. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Sijuwade, J.R. The Metaphysics of Theism: A Classical and Neo-Classical Synthesis. Religions 2021, 12, 967. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12110967
Sijuwade JR. The Metaphysics of Theism: A Classical and Neo-Classical Synthesis. Religions. 2021; 12(11):967. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12110967
Chicago/Turabian StyleSijuwade, Joshua Reginald. 2021. "The Metaphysics of Theism: A Classical and Neo-Classical Synthesis" Religions 12, no. 11: 967. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12110967
APA StyleSijuwade, J. R. (2021). The Metaphysics of Theism: A Classical and Neo-Classical Synthesis. Religions, 12(11), 967. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12110967