Why Open Theism Is Natural and Classical Theism Is Not
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Natural Religion
[T]here is something about our minds that dispose it to catch religious ideas … [O]ur belief-forming mechanisms would be biased in such a way as to create a tendency or a disposition to acquire, think, and transmit religious ideas instead of some other kinds of ideas.
- They “operate unconsciously, and their signals arrive to consciousness automatically and unreflectively”;
- Most (not all) natural systems begin functioning early in life;
- They are designed for the “fundamental cognitive challenges” that humans historically have faced;
- The operations of these systems “do not depend on anything that is culturally distinctive–not on instruction, or on structured preparations, or on artifacts”.
(A) Elements of the natural world, such as rocks, trees, mountains, and animals are purposefully and intentionally designed by someone(s) who must, therefore, have superhuman power;
(B) These agents are not human or animal
(D) Moral norms are unchangeable—even by gods;
(E) Immoral behavior leads to misfortune; moral behavior to fortune;
(H) Gods exist with thoughts, wants, perspectives, and the free will to act;
(I) Gods may be invisible and immortal, but they are not outside of space and time;
(J) Gods can and do interact with the natural world and people, perhaps especially those that are ancestors of the living and, hence, have an interest in the living. This interaction with the world accounts for perceived agency and purpose in the world that cannot be accounted for by human or animal activity;
(K) Gods generally know things that humans do not (they can be superknowing or superperceiving, or both), perhaps particularly things that are important for human relations;
(L) Gods, because of their access to relevant information and special powers, may be responsible for instances of fortune and misfortune; they can reward or punish human actions.
God has created us in such a way that we can know and be in fellowship with him. He could have done this in many ways; for example, he could have brought it about that our cognitive faculties evolve by natural selection, and evolve in such a way that it is natural for us to form beliefs about the supernatural in general and God himself in particular.
Theism-tracking: natural cognitive biases and systems are theism-tracking if the god concept they give rise to approximates the theologically correct model of God.
3. Classical Theism Is Not Natural
3.1. Four Classical Attributes
3.2. Natural Religion and Classical Theism
[T]here is a sense that the God of classical theism does everything, such that it is impossible to point at particular events that God causes as if to distinguish them from those that God does not cause. It is impossible to point at a particular bush that God rustles, a particular gust of wind in which God is present; God rustles all bushes and is present in all gusts of wind. Thus, insofar as the cognitive mechanisms described above—considered by some to be a “god faculty”—detect God in this bush but not that, this gust of wind but not that, then it is not a particularly good detector of God, who is everywhere always acting in all things, causing them to be.
3.3. God’s Personhood
3.4. Implications for the Doctrine of General Revelation
Philosophy and theology as cultural phenomena are likely dependent on literacy and on sufficient prosperity to allow for the cultivation of expertise in the construction of abstract systems of ideas. The religious impulse of human beings is much more ancient and more widespread. Furthermore, from a CSR perspective, religion is thoroughly enmeshed with the social mind being engaged in a pragmatic mode. Though doctrines and practices can be built on the foundations of natural religion and this superstructure of orthodoxy can circumscribe or even contradict natural religion, doing so will require a great deal of cultural scaffolding.
4. Open Theism Is Cognitively Natural
4.1. Basic Characteristics of Open Theism
- God not only created this world ex nihilo, but can (and at times does) intervene unilaterally in earthly affairs;
- God chose to create us with incompatibilistic (libertarian) freedom—freedom over which he cannot exercise total control;
- God so values freedom—the moral integrity of free creatures and a world in which such integrity is possible—that he does not normally override such freedom, even if he sees that it is producing undesirable results;
- God always desires our highest good, both individually and corporately, and, thus, is affected by what happens in our lives;
- God does not possess exhaustive knowledge of exactly how we will utilize our freedom, although he may well, at times, be able to predict, with great accuracy, the choices we will freely make.
4.2. A Modified Account of Natural Religion
[The] subjects seemed to characterize God as having to be near something to receive sensory information from it, not being able to attend differentially to competing sensory stimuli, performing tasks sequentially and not in parallel, having a single or limited focus of attention, moving from place to place, and sometimes standing or walking.
4.3. Salvaging the Theism-Tracking Thesis
Although it is now commonly supposed that God exists outside of space, this was not the standard conception among earlier theologians. Medieval Christian authors, despite being generally misread on this point, are in complete agreement that God is literally present, spatially, throughout the universe. One simply does not find anyone wanting to remove God from space, all the way through to the end of the seventeenth century.
Consistently holding that God is omnipresent, but not uniformly present, merely requires that in addition to God’s general omnipresence, God may be specially present to particular locations in some way(s) he is not present to other locations. This may be so whether the manner of divine omnipresence is understood as derivative or nonderivative. For example, God might be derivatively omnipresent while also specially present in specific locations in some derivative fashion. Perhaps God is omnipresent in that God’s power extends everywhere, sustaining all things (Heb. 1:3), while instances of special divine presence are special manifestations of divine power in creation (i.e., instances of special divine action) that do not involve God being spatially present. In this way, general omnipresence and special divine presence could involve the same kinds of presence while being distinguished in terms of degree.
5. Concluding Remarks
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | In all that follows, “God” with a capital G stands for the God of Christian theism while “god” stands for any supernatural agent. |
2 | According to Marsh, this fact bolsters the argument from divine hiddenness. This argument claims that God does not exist because “nonresistant nonbelief” does (Schellenberg 2015). Nonresistant nonbelief is lack of belief in God that is not due to the person resisting a relationship with God. According to the argument, any being worthy of the name God would be perfectly loving. A perfectly loving God would always be open for a relationship with creatures as long as they are also open. |
3 | Alternatively, one could view a correct concept of God as a precondition for a relationship with God. Some claim that one can be in a relationship with God without believing in God (see Schellenberg 2017). |
4 | It is worth noting that there is a debate over the exact nature of omnipresence. The classical theist Paul Helm says that the omnipresent God is spaceless (Helm 2010, p. 41). Yet the medieval scholar Robert Pasnau says that the classical Christian tradition did not affirm that God Is spaceless until the end of the 17th Century (Pasnau 2011, p. 19). |
5 | |
6 | There may be also other models of God that seem similarly cognitively natural, such as some versions of neoclassical or “modified” classical theism (e.g., Peckham 2021). However, open theism is a clearly defined model of God and thus serves as an example. |
7 | God is unified in that all of God’s essential attributes are co-extensive and compossible or coherent. |
8 | Regarding the methodology in Barrett and Keil’s study, it has been pointed out that the stories themselves include anthropomorphic cues (Shtulman 2008). However, for the sake of argument, we will not appeal to this criticism here. |
9 | Barrett does not say cognitively natural gods are punishing/loving as Braddock does, but that they reward and punish. |
References
- Arcadi, James M. 2017. God is Where God Acts: Reconceiving Divine Omnipresence. Topoi 36: 631–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Barlev, Michael, Spencer Mermelstein, Adam S. Cohen, and Tamsin C. German. 2019. The Embodied God: Core Intuitions About Person Physicality Coexist and Interfere with Acquired Christian Beliefs About God, the Holy Spirit, and Jesus. Cognitive Science 43: e12784. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Barlev, Michael, Spencer Mermelstein, and Tamsin C. German. 2017. Core Intuitions About Persons Coexist and Interfere with Acquired Christian Beliefs About God. Cognitive Science 41: 425–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Barrett, Justin L. 2004. Why Would Anyone Believe in God? Walnut Creek: Altamira. [Google Scholar]
- Barrett, Justin L. 2007. Cognitive Science of Religion: What Is It and Why Is It: Cognitive Science of Religion. Religion Compass 1: 768–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Barrett, Justin L. 2012a. Born Believers: The Science of Children’s Religious Belief. New York: Free Press. [Google Scholar]
- Barrett, Justin L. 2012b. Toward a Cognitive Science of Christianity. In The Blackwell Companion to Science and Christianity. Edited by Jim B. Stump and Alan G. Padgett. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons, pp. 317–34. [Google Scholar]
- Barrett, Justin L., and Aku Visala. 2018. In What Sense Might Religion Be Natural? In The Naturalness of Belief: New Essays on Theism’s Rationality. Edited by Paul Copan and Charles Taliaferro. Lanham: Lexington Books, pp. 67–84. [Google Scholar]
- Barrett, Justin L., and Frank C. Keil. 1996. Conceptualizing a Nonnatural Entity: Anthropomorphism in God Concepts. Cognitive Psychology 31: 219–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Basinger, David. 1994. Practical Implications. In The Openness of God: A Biblical Challenge to the Traditional Understanding of God. Edited by Clark H. Pinnock, Richard Rice, John Sanders, William Hasker and David Basinger. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press, pp. 155–76. [Google Scholar]
- Bering, Jesse M. 2002. The Existential Theory of Mind. Review of General Psychology 6: 3–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bloom, Paul. 2007. Religion Is Natural. Developmental Science 10: 147–51. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Boyer, Pascal. 2001. Religion Explained: The Evolutionary Origins of Religious Thought. New York: Basic Books. [Google Scholar]
- Braddock, Matthew. 2018. An Evidential Argument for Theism from the Cognitive Science of Religion. In New Developments in the Cognitive Science of Religion. Edited by Hans van Eyghen, Rik Peels and Gijsbert van den Brink. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 171–98. [Google Scholar]
- Braddock, Matthew. Forthcoming. The Problem of Natural Nonbelief: Prehistoric Humans, Religious Debunking, and Divine Hiddenness. In Evolutionary Debunking Arguments in Philosophy. Edited by Diego Machuca. London: Routledge.
- Clark, Kelly James, and Justin L. Barrett. 2010. Reformed Epistemology and the Cognitive Science of Religion. Faith and Philosophy 27: 174–89. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Clark, Kelly James, and Justin L. Barrett. 2011. Reidian Religious Epistemology and the Cognitive Science of Religion. Journal of the American Academy of Religion 79: 639–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Davies, Brian. 2006. The Reality of God and the Problem of Evil. New York: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
- Davis, Stephen T. 2017. Divine Incomprehensibility: Can We Know the Unknowable God? Topoi 36: 565–70. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Demarest, Bruce A. 1982. General Revelation: Historical Views and Contemporary Issues. Grand Rapids: Zondervan. [Google Scholar]
- Diller, Jeanine, and Asa Kasher, eds. 2013. Models of God and Alternative Ultimate Realities. Dordrecht: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Dolezal, James E. 2011. God without Parts: Divine Simplicity and the Metaphysics of God’s Absoluteness. Eugene: Pickwick Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Dolezal, James E. 2017. All That Is in God: Evangelical Theology and the Challenge of Classical Christian Theism. Grand Rapids: Reformation Heritage Books. [Google Scholar]
- Dolezal, James E. 2019. Strong Impassibility. In Divine Impassibility: Four Views of God’s Emotions and Suffering. Edited by Robert J. Matz and A. Chadwick Thornhill. Downers Grove: IVP Academic, pp. 13–52. [Google Scholar]
- Evans, Jonathan St. B. T. 2003. In Two Minds: Dual-Process Accounts of Reasoning. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7: 454–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Feser, Edward. 2017. Five Proofs of Existence. San Francisco: Ignatius Press. [Google Scholar]
- Green, Adam. 2013. Cognitive Science and the Natural Knowledge of God. The Monist 96: 399–419. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hasker, William. 1989. God, Time, and Knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Heiphetz, Larisa, Jonathan D. Lane, Adam Waytz, and Liane L. Young. 2016. How Children and Adults Represent God’s Mind. Cognitive Science 40: 121–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Helm, Paul. 1990. Impossibility of Divine Passibility. In The Power and Weakness of God. Edited by Nigel M. de S. Cameron. Edinburgh: Rutherford House Books. [Google Scholar]
- Helm, Paul. 1998. John Calvin, the ‘Sensus Divinitatis’, and the Noetic Effects of Sin. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 43: 87–107. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Helm, Paul. 2001. Divine Timeless Eternity. In God and Time: Four Views. Edited by Gregory E. Ganssle. Downers Grove: IVP Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Helm, Paul. 2010. Eternal God: A Study of God without Time. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hick, John. 2000. Ineffability. Religious Studies 36: 35–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hodge, K. Mitch. 2008. Descartes’ Mistake: How Afterlife Beliefs Challenge the Assumption That Humans Are Intuitive Cartesian Substance Dualists. Journal of Cognition and Culture 8: 387–415. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Johnson, Dominic. 2016. God Is Watching You: How the Fear of God Makes Us Human. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jong, Jonathan, Christopher Kavanagh, and Aku Visala. 2015. Born idolaters: The Limits of the Philosophical Implications of the Cognitive Science of Religion. Neue Zeitschrift für Systematische Theologie und Religionsphilosophie 57: 244–66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kahneman, Daniel. 2011. Thinking, Fast and Slow. New York: Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- Launonen, Lari. 2018. The Naturalness of Religion: What It Means and Why It Matters. Neue Zeitschrift Für Systematische Theologie Und Religionsphilosophie 60: 84–102. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Launonen, Lari. 2021. Cognitive Regeneration and the Noetic Effects of Sin: Why Theology and Cognitive Science May Not Be Compatible. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 13: 113–37. [Google Scholar]
- Marschler, Thomas. 2016. Substantiality and Personality in the Scholastic Doctrine of God. In Rethinking the Concept of a Personal God: Classical Theism, Personal Theism, and Alternative Concepts of God. Edited by Thomas Schartl, Christian Tapp and Veronika Wegener. Munster: Aschendorff Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Marsh, Jason. 2013. Darwin and the Problem of Natural Nonbelief. Monist 96: 349–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mawson, T. J. 2006. God’s Body. The Heythrop Journal 47: 171–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mawson, T. J. 2014. Cognitive Science of Religion and the Rationality of Classical Theism. In The Roots of Religion: Exploring the Cognitive Science of Religion. Edited by Roger Trigg and Justin L. Barrett. New York: Routledge, pp. 149–66. [Google Scholar]
- McCauley, Robert N. 2011. Why Religion Is Natural and Science Is Not. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mullins, R. T. 2016. The Difficulty of Demarcating Panentheism. Sophia 55: 225–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Mullins, R. T. 2021a. Classical Theism. In T&T Clark Handbook of Analytic Theology. Edited by James M. Arcadi and James T. Turner. London: T&T Clark. [Google Scholar]
- Mullins, R. T. 2021b. God and Emotion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Norenzayan, Ara, Will M. Gervais, and Kali H. Trzesniewski. 2012. Mentalizing Deficits Constrain Belief in a Personal God. PLoS ONE 7: e36880. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Norenzayan, Ara, Azim F. Shariff, Will M. Gervais, Aiyana K. Willard, Rita A. McNamara, Edward Slingerland, and Joseph Henrich. 2016. The Cultural Evolution of Prosocial Religions. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 39: e1. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Pasnau, Robert. 2011. On Existing All at Once. In God, Eternity, and Time. Edited by Christian Tapp and Edmund Runggaldier. Surrey: Ashgate. [Google Scholar]
- Peckham, John. 2021. Divine Attributes: Knowing the Covenantal God of Scripture. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Peels, Rik, Hans van Eyghen, and Gijsbert van den Brink. 2018. Cognitive Science of Religion and the Cognitive Consequences of Sin. In New Developments in the Cognitive Science of Religion. Edited by Hans van Eyghen, Rik Peels and Gijsbert van den Brink. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 199–214. [Google Scholar]
- Peoples, Hervey C., Pavel Duda, and Frank W. Marlow. 2016. Hunter-Gatherers and the Origins of Religion. Human Nature 27: 261–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Pinnock, Clark H. 1994. Systematic Theology. In The Openness of God: A Biblical Challenge to the Traditional Understanding of God. Edited by Clark H. Pinnock, Richard Rice, John Sanders, William Hasker and David Basinger. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press, pp. 101–25. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Alvin. 2011. Where the Conflict Really Lies: Science, Religion, & Naturalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rhoda, Alan R. 2011. The Fivefold Openness of the Future. In God in an Open Universe: Science, Metaphysics, and Open Theism. Edited by William Hasker, Dean Zimmerman and Thomas J. Oord. Eugene: Pickwick, pp. 69–93. [Google Scholar]
- Rogers, Katherin. 1996. The Traditional Doctrine of Divine Simplicity. Religious Studies 32: 165–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schellenberg, John L. 2015. The Hiddenness Argument: Philosophy’s New Challenge to Belief in God. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schellenberg, John L. 2017. Divine Hiddenness: Part 2 (Recent Enlargements of the Discussion). Philosophy Compass 12: e12413. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schjoedt, Uffe, Hans Stødkilde-Jørgensen, Armin W. Geertz, and Andreas Roepstorff. 2009. Highly Religious Participants Recruit Areas of Social Cognition in Personal Prayer. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 4: 199–207. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Shtulman, Andrew. 2008. Variation in the Anthropomorphization of Supernatural Beings and Its Implications for Cognitive Theories of Religion. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 34: 1123–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Slone, D. Jason. 2004. Theological Incorrectness: Why Religious People Believe What They Shouldn’t. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sterelny, Kim. 2018. Religion Re-Explained. Religion, Brain & Behavior 8: 406–25. [Google Scholar]
- Swinburne, Richard. 2016. The Coherence of Theism, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Vainio, Olli-Pekka. 2016. What Does Theology Have to Do With Religion? Dual-process Accounts, Cognitive Science of Religion and a Curious Blind Spot in Contemporary Theorizing. Open Theology 2: 106–12. [Google Scholar]
- van Eyghen, Hans. 2020. Arguing From Cognitive Science Of Religion. London: Bloomsbury Academic. [Google Scholar]
- White, Claire. 2021. An Introduction to the Cognitive Science of Religion: Connecting Evolution, Brain, Cognition, and Culture. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Whitehouse, Harvey. 2008. Cognitive Evolution and Religion: Cognition and Religious Evolution. Issues in Ethnology and Anthropology 3: 35–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Wiertz, Oliver. 2016. Classical Theism. In Rethinking the Concept of a Personal God: Classical Theism, Personal Theism, and Alternative Concepts of God. Edited by Thomas Schartl, Christian Tapp and Veronika Wegener. Munster: Aschendorff Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 2010. Inquiring About God. Edited by Terence Cuneo. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Launonen, L.; Mullins, R.T. Why Open Theism Is Natural and Classical Theism Is Not. Religions 2021, 12, 956. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12110956
Launonen L, Mullins RT. Why Open Theism Is Natural and Classical Theism Is Not. Religions. 2021; 12(11):956. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12110956
Chicago/Turabian StyleLaunonen, Lari, and R. T. Mullins. 2021. "Why Open Theism Is Natural and Classical Theism Is Not" Religions 12, no. 11: 956. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12110956
APA StyleLaunonen, L., & Mullins, R. T. (2021). Why Open Theism Is Natural and Classical Theism Is Not. Religions, 12(11), 956. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12110956